Acta Polytechnica Vol. 51 No. 4/2011 Two Remarks to Bifullness of Centers of Archimedean Atomic Lattice Effect Algebras M. Kalina Abstract Lattice effect algebras generalize orthomodular lattices as well as MV-algebras. This means that within lattice effect algebras it is possible to model such effects as unsharpness (fuzziness) and/or non-compatibility. The main problem is the existence of a state. There are lattice effect algebras with no state. For this reason we need some conditions that simplify checking the existence of a state. If we know that the center C(E) of an atomic Archimedean lattice effect algebra E (which is again atomic) is a bifull sublattice of E, then we are able to represent E as a subdirect product of lattice effect algebras Ei where the top element of each one of Ei is an atom of C(E). In this case it is enough if we find a state at least in one of Ei and we are able to extend this state to the whole lattice effect algebra E. In [8] an atomic lattice effect algebra E (in fact, an atomic orthomodular lattice) with atomic center C(E) was constructed, where C(E) is not a bifull sublattice of E. In this paper we show that for atomic lattice effect algebras E (atomic orthomodular lattices) neither completeness (and atomicity) of C(E) nor σ-completeness of E are sufficient conditions for C(E) to be a bifull sublattice of E. Keywords: lattice effect algebra, orthomodular lattice, center, atom, bifullness. 1 Preliminaries Effect algebras, introduced by D. J. Foulis and M. K. Bennett [3], have their importance in the investigation of uncertainty. Lattice ordered effect algebras generalize orthomodular lattices and MV- algebras. Thus they may include non-compatible pairs of elements as well as unsharp elements. Definition 1 (Foulis and Bennett [3]) An effect al- gebra is a system (E; ⊕,0,1) consisting of a set E with two different elements 0 and 1, called zero and unit, respectively and ⊕ is a partially defined binary operation satisfying the following conditions for all p, q, r ∈ E: (E1) If p ⊕ q is defined, then q ⊕ p is defined and p ⊕ q = q ⊕ p. (E2) If q ⊕ r is defined and p ⊕ (q ⊕ r) is defined, then p ⊕ q and (p ⊕ q) ⊕ r are defined and p ⊕ (q ⊕ r) = (p ⊕ q) ⊕ r. (E3) For every p ∈ E there exists a unique q ∈ E such that p ⊕ q is defined and p ⊕ q = 1. (E4) If p ⊕1 is defined then p = 0. The element q in (E3) will be called the supplement of p, and will be denoted as p′. In the whole paper, for an effect algebra (E, ⊕,0,1), writing a ⊕ b for arbitrary a, b ∈ E will mean that a ⊕ b exists. On an effect algebra E we may define another partial binary operation � by a � b = c ⇔ b ⊕ c = a. The operation � induces a partial order on E. Namely, for a, b ∈ E b ≤ a if there exists a c ∈ E such that a � b = c. If E with respect to ≤ is lattice ordered, we say that E is a lattice effect algebra. For the sake of brevity we will write just LEA. Further, in this article we often briefly write ‘an effect algebra E’ skipping the operations. S. P. Gudder ( [5, 6]) introduced the notion of sharp elements and sharply dominating lattice effect algebras. Recall that an element x of the LEA E is called sharp if x ∧ x′ = 0. Jenča and Riečanová in [7] proved that in every lattice effect algebra E the set S(E) = {x ∈ E; x ∧ x′ = 0} of sharp elements is an orthomodular lattice which is a sub-effect algebra of E, meaning that if among x, y, z ∈ E with x ⊕ y = z at least two elements are in S(E) then x, y, z ∈ S(E). Moreover S(E) is a full sublattice of E, hence a supre- mum of any set of sharp elements, which exists in E, is again a sharp element. Further, each maximal sub- set M of pairwise compatible elements of E, called a block of E, is a sub-effect algebra and a full sub- lattice of E and E = ⋃ {M ⊆ E; M is a block of E} (see [16, 17]). Central elements and centers of effect algebras were defined in [4]. In [14, 15] it was proved that in every lattice effect algebra E the center C(E) = {x ∈ E; (∀y ∈ E)y = (y ∧ x) ∨ (y ∧ x′)} = S(E) ∩ B(E), (1) where B(E) = ⋂ {M ⊆ E; M is a block of E}. Since S(E) is an orthomodular lattice and B(E) is an 26 Acta Polytechnica Vol. 51 No. 4/2011 MV-effect algebra, we obtain that C(E) is a Boolean algebra. Note that E is an orthomodular lattice if and only if E = S(E) and E is an MV-effect alge- bra if and only if E = B(E). Thus E is a Boolean algebra if and only if E = S(E) = B(E) = C(E). Recall that an element p of an effect algebra E is called an atom if and only if p is a minimal non- zero element of E and E is atomic if for each x ∈ E, x �= 0, there exists an atom p ≤ x. Definition 2 Let (E, ⊕, 0) be an effect algebra. To each a ∈ E we define its isotropic index, notation ord(a), as the maximal positive integer n such that na := a ⊕ . . . ⊕ a︸ ︷︷ ︸ n-times exists. We set ord(a) = ∞ if na exists for each posi- tive integer n. We say that E is Archimedean, if for each a ∈ E, a �= 0, ord(a) is finite. An element u ∈ E is called finite, if there exists a finite system of atoms a1, . . . , an (which are not necessarily distinct) such that u = a1 ⊕ . . . ⊕ an. An element v ∈ E is called cofinite, if there exists a finite element u ∈ E such that v = u′. We say that for a finite system F = (xj ) k j=1 of not necessarily different elements of an effect al- gebra (E, ⊕,0,1) is ⊕-orthogonal if for all n ≤ k x1 ⊕ x2⊕· · ·⊕ xn = (x1 ⊕ x2 ⊕· · ·⊕ xn−1) ⊕ xn exists in E (briefly we will write n⊕ j=1 xj ). We define also ⊕∅ = 0. Definition 3 For a lattice (L, ∧, ∨) and a subset D ⊆ L we say that D is a bifull sublattice of L, if and only if for any X ⊆ D, ∨ L X exists if and only if∨ D X exists and ∧ L X exists if and only if ∧ D X exists, in which case ∨ L X = ∨ D X and ∧ L X = ∧ D X. It is known that if E is a distributive effect al- gebra (i. e., the effect algebra E is a distributive lattice — e. g., if E is an MV-effect algebra) then C(E) = S(E). If moreover E is Archimedean and atomic then the set of atoms of C(E) = S(E) is the set {naa; a ∈ E is an atom of E}, where na = ord(a) (see [20]). Since S(E) is a bifull sublattice of E if E is an Archimedean atomic LEA (see [13]), we obtain that 1 = ∨ C(E) {p ∈ C(E); p is an atom of C(E)} = ∨ E {p ∈ C(E); p is an atom of C(E)} for every Archimedean atomic distributive lattice ef- fect algebra E. In [8] it was shown that there exists an LEA E for which this property fails to be true. Important properties of Archimedean atomic lattice effect algebras with an atomic center were proven by Riečanová in [21]. Theorem 1 (Riečanová [21]) Let E be an Archime- dean atomic lattice effect algebra with an atomic cen- ter C(E). Let AE be the set of all atoms of E and AC(E) the set of all atoms of C(E). The following conditions are equivalent: 1. ∨ E AC(E) = 1. 2. For every atom a ∈ AE there exists an atom pa ∈ AC(E) such that a ≤ pa. 3. For every z ∈ C(E) it holds z = ∨ C(E) {p ∈ AC(E); p ≤ z} = ∨ E {p ∈ AC(E); p ≤ z}. 4. C(E) is a bifull sub-lattice of E. In this case E is isomorphic to a subdirect product of Archimedean atomic irreducible lattice effect alge- bras. Theorem 2 (Paseka, Riečanová [13]) Let E be an atomic Archimedean lattice effect algebra. Then the set S(E) of all sharp elements of E is a bifull sublat- tice of E. We will deal only with atomic Archimedean lattice effect algebras E. We have C(E) ⊂ S(E) ⊂ E. Be- cause of this inclusion and Theorem 2, considering the bifullness of the center C(E) in E is equivalent to considering the bifullness of C(E) in S(E). And S(E) is an orthomodular lattice. For this reason, in the rest of the paper we will restrict our attention to atomic orthomodular lattices L and their centers C(L). For the sake of completeness, we give the def- inition of an orthomodular lattice. Definition 4 Let L be a bounded lattice with a unary operation ′ (called complementation) satisfy- ing the following conditions 1. for all a ∈ L (a′)′ = a, 2. for all a, b ∈ L if a ≤ b then b′ ≤ a′, 3. for all a, b ∈ L if a ≤ b then a ∨ (a′ ∧ b) = b. Then L is said to be an orthomodular lattice (OML for brevity). Remark 1 Though in OML’s we have just lattice- theoretical operations ∨ and ∧, we will use also ef- fect algebraic operations ⊕ and � with the meaning a ⊕ b = a ∨ b iff a ≤ b′ and a � b = c iff b ⊕ c = a. 27 Acta Polytechnica Vol. 51 No. 4/2011 2 Orthomodular lattice L whose center is not a bifull sublattice Let us have the following sequences of atoms (sets): a0 = {(x, y) ∈ R2; 0 ≤ x ≤ 1, y ∈ R}, al = {(x, y) ∈ R2; l < x ≤ l + 1, y ∈ R}, for l = 1, 2, . . ., b0 = {(x, y) ∈ R2; −1 ≤ x < 0, y ∈ R}, bl = {(x, y) ∈ R2; −l − 1 ≤ x < −l, y ∈ R}, for l = 1, 2, . . ., (2) cj = {(x, y) ∈ R2; −j ≤ x ≤ j, y ≤ j · x}, for j = 1, 2, . . ., dj = {(x, y) ∈ R2; −j ≤ x ≤ j, y > j · x}, for j = 1, 2, . . ., pj = {j}, for j = 1, 2, . . .. For such a choice of atoms, q1 �= q2 are compatible if and only if q1∩q2 = ∅. Fig. 1 shows the compatibility among atoms. For their non-compatibility (denoted by �↔) the following rules hold cj �↔ ai, cj �↔ bi for all j = 1, 2, . . . and i = 0, . . . , j − 1, dj �↔ ai, dj �↔ bi for all j = 1, 2, . . . and i = 0, . . . , j − 1, cj �↔ di for all i, j = 1, 2, . . . such that i �= j, cj �↔ ci, dj �↔ di for all i, j = 1, 2, . . . such that i �= j. � � �� � � � � � � � � � � p1 p2 p3 p4 p5 p6 pn pn+1 � � �� � � � � � � � � � � a0 b0 a1 b1 a2 b2 an bn � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � c1 c2 c3 cn−1 d1 d2 d3 dn−1 Fig. 1: Greechie diagram of sets of atoms For non-compatible atoms the following equalities hold cj ⊕ dj = j−1⊕ i=0 (ai ⊕ bi) = ck ∨ cj = dk ∨ dj = ck ∨ dj = dk ∨ cj = cj ∨ al = cj ∨ bl = dj ∨ al = dj ∨ bl for 1 ≤ k < j and 0 ≤ l < j. Denote B̂0, B̂j (for j = 1, 2, . . .) complete atomic Boolean algebras with the corresponding sets of atoms A0, Aj (j = 1, 2, . . .), given by A0 = ∞⋃ i=0 {ai} ∪ ∞⋃ i=0 {bi} ∪ ∞⋃ j=1 {pj}, (3) Aj = ∞⋃ i=j {ai} ∪ ∞⋃ i=j {bi} ∪ ∞⋃ j=1 {pj} ∪{cj , dj}. (4) Disjointness occurring among some atoms of the sys- tem (2) is equivalent to the fact that A0 and Aj (j = 1, 2, . . .) are unique maximal sets of pairwise compatible atoms. Theorem 3 (Kalina [9]) Let L̂ = ∞⋃ i=0 B̂i. Let L1 be the complete OML generated by sets of atoms ∞⋃ i=0 {ai, bi} ∪ ∞⋃ j=1 {cj , dj} and N the complete Boolean algebra generated by the set of atoms ∞⋃ j=1 {pj}. Then (L̂, ∨, ∧,0,1) is a complete OML and L̂ ∼= L1 ×N. An element u ∈ B̂l is finite if and only if u = q1⊕ q2⊕ . . .⊕ qn for an n ∈ N and q1, q2, . . . , qn ∈ Al. Set Ql = {u ∈ Bl; u is finite}, l = 0, 1, 2, . . .. Then Ql is a generalized Boolean algebra, since Bl = Ql ∪̇ Q∗l is a Boolean algebra, where Q∗l = {u ∗; u∗ = 1l � u and u ∈ Ql} (see [22], or [2, pp. 18-19]). This means that Bl is a Boolean subalgebra of finite and cofinite elements of B̂l (l = 0, 1, 2, . . .). Theorem 4 (Kalina [8]) Denote L = ∞⋃ l=0 Bl. Then (L, ∨, ∧,0,1) is a compactly generated orthomodular lattice with the family (Bl) ∞ l=0 of atomic blocks of L. The center of L, C(L), is not a bifull sublattice of L. 3 Completion of the center of L We are going to show that it is possible to extend the orthomodular lattice L from Theorem 4 to L̄, whose center, C(L̄), is a complete Boolean algebra which is not a bifull sublattice of L̄. Denote F a fixed non-trivial ultrafilter on N (the index set of atoms pj ). Then F has the following properties which will be important for our construc- tion: • Let F ⊂ N. Then either F ∈ F or N \ F ∈ F. • Let F ⊂ N be a finite set. Then F /∈ F. • If F1 ∈ F and F2 ∈ F then F1 ∩ F2 ∈ F. • If F1 ∈ F and F2 ⊃ F1 then F2 ∈ F. 28 Acta Polytechnica Vol. 51 No. 4/2011 Let QL1 denote the set of all finite elements of L1. Further set PF = {⊕ i∈F pi; F /∈ F } (5) and G = {f ⊕ g; g ∈ QL1, f ∈ PF}, G⊥ = {h′ ∈ L̂; h ∈ G}. Theorem 5 Let L̃ = G ∪̇ G⊥. Then the system( L̃, ∨, ∧,0,1 ) is an orthomodular lattice. The center C(L̃) = {f ∈ L̃; f ∈ PF or f ′ ∈ PF}, and C(L̃) is a complete Boolean algebra which is not bifull in L̃. Proof. First we show that L̃ is a bounded lattice. Consider elements h1, h2 ∈ G. Then there exist el- ements g1, g2 ∈ QL1 and elements f1, f2 ∈ PF such that h1 = f1 ⊕ g1, h2 = f2 ⊕ g2. (6) By the properties of the non-trivial ultrafilter F we get that f1 ∨ f2 ∈ PF and f1 ∧ f2 ∈ PF . Since g1, g2 are finite elements of L1, we get that g1 ∨ g2 ∈ QL1 and also g1 ∧ g2 ∈ QL1. Since L1 is generated by the sets of atoms ∞⋃ i=0 {ai, bi} and ∞⋃ j=1 {cj, dj}, each g ∈ QL1 is ⊕-orthogonal to each f ∈ PF . This im- plies that G is closed under ∨ and ∧. Because G⊥ consists of complements of elements of G, we have that also G⊥ is closed under ∨ and ∧. Now assume that h1 ∈ G and h2 ∈ G⊥. Then h′2 ∈ G and we can write h1 = f1 ⊕ g1, h′2 = f2 ⊕ g2 with the same meaning of f1, f2, g1, g2 as in formula (6). This means that h2 = f ′ 2 � g2. Then, be- cause of the monotonicity of the ultrafilter F, we have (f1 ∨ f ′2) ′ ∈ PF and hence f1 ∨ f ′2 ∈ G ⊥. Moreover, g2 ∈ QL1 is orthogonal to f1 which implies (f1 ∨ f ′2) � g2 = f1 ∨ (f ′ 2 � g2) ∈ G ⊥. Since G is a monotone system (meaning that with an arbitrary element δ1 ∈ G it contains also all elements δ2 ∈ L̂ such that δ2 ≤ δ1), we get from the duality between G and G⊥ that (f1 ∨ g1) ∨ (f ′2 � g2) = h1 ∨ h2 ∈ G ⊥ Dually we get that h1 ∧ h2 ∈ G. This implies that L̃ = G ∪̇ G⊥ is a lattice. Obviously it is a bounded and orthocomplemented lattice. Showing that it is an OML is a matter of routine. We will omit the detailed proof. Let us consider an element f ∈ L̃ such that f ∈ PF or f ′ ∈ PF . Then f is a central element. If f is such that neither f ∈ PF nor f ′ ∈ PF , then there exist atoms α1, α2 ∈ ∞⋃ i=0 {ai, bi} ∪ ∞⋃ j=1 {cj , dj} fulfilling α1 �↔ α2 and α1 ≤ f , α2 �≤ f . Then f is not a central element. This proves that C(L̃) = {f ∈ L̃; f ∈ PF or f ′ ∈ PF}. Due to the fact that F is a non-trivial ultrafilter, C(L̃) is a complete Boolean algebra. The only central element that is greater than all atoms pj for j = 1, 2, . . ., is 1, hence we have that∨ C(L̃) {pj ; j = 1, 2, . . .} = 1. On the other hand, let us take an arbitrary atom α ∈ ∞⋃ i=0 {ai, bi} ∪ ∞⋃ j=1 {cj , dj} and assume that ∨ L̃ {pj ; j = 1, 2, . . .} does exist. Since α is orthogonal to all atoms from the set ∞⋃ j=1 {pj}, we have that α is orthogonal to∨ L̃ {pj ; j = 1, 2, . . .} and hence ∨ L̃ {pj ; j = 1, 2, . . .} �= 1. It can be shown (see [8]) that ∨ L̃ {pj ; j = 1, 2, . . .} does not exist. This implies that C(L̃) is not a bifull sublattice of L̃. � 4 σ-complete orthomodular lattice L̃σ whose center is not a bifull sublattice Let I denote the set of all ordinal numbers less than Ω (the first uncountable ordinal number). Further, denote E the set of all limit ordinal numbers up to Ω and J = I \ E. Assume sets of elements {pi; i ∈ I}, {ai; i ∈ I}, {bi; i ∈ I}, {ci; i ∈ I}, {di; i ∈ I}, where the cor- responding elements for i ∈ J will act as atoms. We will have a partial relation �↔ modelling non- compatibility. This partial relation will have the fol- lowing form among atoms cj �↔ ai, cj �↔ bi for all j ∈ J and i ≤ j, dj �↔ ai, dj �↔ bi for all j ∈ J and i ≤ j, 29 Acta Polytechnica Vol. 51 No. 4/2011 cj �↔ di for all i, j ∈ J such that i �= j, cj �↔ ci, dj �↔ di for all i, j ∈ J such that i �= j. Sets of elements {pi; i ∈ I}, {ai; i ∈ I}, {bi; i ∈ I}, {ci; i ∈ I}, {di; i ∈ I} will present atoms for i ∈ J and for κ ∈ E we will have pκ = ∨ i<κ pi, (7) aκ = ∨ i<κ ai, (8) bκ = ∨ i<κ bi, (9) cκ = ∨ i<κ ci = ∨ i<κ di = dκ = aκ ⊕ bκ. (10) As a possible model for the just presented sets of elements fulfilling the non-compatibility relation we may have the following: Let us choose a good order of positive real numbers of type Ω, i.e., positive real numbers will be enumerated by ordinal numbers from J . For i ∈ J and r > 0, r ∈ R, we denote ri the i-th number in the chosen good order. Then we identify the set {pi; i ∈ J } with the set of all positive real numbers, i.e., pi = ri. Further we put for i, j ∈ J ai = {(ri, y) ∈ R2; y ∈ R}, bi = {(−ri, y) ∈ R2; y ∈ R}, ci = {(rj , y) ∈ R2; j ≤ i, y ≤ ri · rj} ∪ {(−rj , y) ∈ R2; j ≤ i, y ≤ −ri · rj}, di = {(rj , y) ∈ R2; j ≤ i, y > ri · rj} ∪ {(−rj , y) ∈ R2; j ≤ i, y > −ri · rj}. For κ ∈ E we define the corresponding elements pκ, aκ, bκ, cκ, dκ by equalities 7, 8, 9, 10, respectively. Compatibility among different atoms is given by dis- jointness of the corresponding sets. This implies that the uniquely given maximal sets of pairwise compat- ible atoms are Ã0 = ⋃ i∈J {ai, bi, pi}, Ãj = ⋃ i ∈ J i > j {ai, bi} ∪ ⋃ i∈J {pi} ∪ {cj, dj} for j ∈ J . Sets of atoms Ã0 and Ãj for j ∈ J , gener- ate complete Boolean algebras B̃0 and B̃j for j ∈ J , respectively. For κ ∈ E we get complete atomic Boolean algebras B̃κ generated by sets of atoms Ãκ = ⋃ i∈J {pi} ∪ {aκ, bκ} ∪ ⋃ i ∈ J i > κ {ai, bi}. This means that for κ ∈ E B̃κ ⊂ B̃0. The union of all complete atomic Boolean algebras, L̃ = B̃0 ∪ ⋃ i∈I B̃i, is a complete OML. An element f ∈ L̃ will be called countable if there exists an at most countable set of atoms (an at most countable set of indices K) {qk}k∈K ⊂ Ã0 or {qk}k∈K ⊂ Ãi for i ∈ J , such that f = ⊕ k∈K qk. By definition of elements pi, ai, bi, ci, di for i ∈ I we get that each of these elements is countable. Let K denote the set of all countable elements of L̃ and K⊥ = {f ∈ L̃; f ′ ∈ K}. Further, let P de- note the set of all countable elements generated by {pi, i ∈ J }, and P⊥ = {f ∈ L̃; f ′ ∈ P}. Theorem 6 Let L̃σ = K∪̇K⊥. Then ( L̃σ, ∨, ∧,0,1 ) is a σ-complete OML. The center C(L̃σ ) = P∪̇P⊥ and it is not a bifull sublattice of L̃σ. Proof. Each of the atoms pi, ai, bi, ci, di for i ∈ J (and hence also each of the elements pi, ai, bi, ci, di for i ∈ I) is countable. This implies that L̃σ is an OML. Since it is by definition closed under countable meets and joins, it is σ-complete. Elements pi for i ∈ I are central because each of the elements pi is compatible with all atoms of L̃σ. This implies that P∪̇P⊥ ⊂ C(L̃σ ). On the other hand, let f be a countable element, f /∈ P. Then there exists ci such that ci �≤ f for i ∈ J and an atom out of e ∈ {aj, bj , cj, dj} for j < i, e ≤ f . Then ci �↔ e and hence cj �↔ f . Similarly, if f ∈ K⊥, there exists ci ≤ f and an atom out of e ∈ {aj, bj , cj, dj} for j < i such that e �≤ f . In this case e �↔ ci and hence also e �↔ f . We conclude that C(L̃σ ) = P∪̇P⊥. We show that C(L̃σ ) is not a bifull sublattice of L̃σ. Obviously ∨ C(L̃σ) {pi, i ∈ I} = 1. Assume that ∨ L̃σ {pi, i ∈ I} does exist. Then all el- ements e ∈ ⋃ i∈I {ai, bi, ci, di} are orthogonal with all elements from the set ⋃ I {pj} and consequently also with ∨ L̃σ {pi, i ∈ I}. This implies ∨ L̃σ {pi, i ∈ I} �= 1. This means that C(L̃σ ) is not a bifull sublattice of L̃σ. � 30 Acta Polytechnica Vol. 51 No. 4/2011 Acknowledgement Support from the Science and Technology Assistance Agency under contract No. APVV-0073-10, and from the VEGA grant agency, grant number 1/0297/11, is gratefully acknowledged. References [1] Chang, C. C.: Algebraic analysis of many-valued logics. Trans. Amer. Math. Soc. 88 (1958), 467–490. [2] Dvurečenskij, A., Pulmannová, S.: New Trends in Quantum Structures. Dordrecht, Boston, London, and Isterscience, Bratislava : Kluwer Acad. Publisher, 2000. [3] Foulis, D. J., Bennett, M. K.: Effect algebras and unsharp quantum logics. Found. Phys. 24 (1994), 1 325–1 346. [4] Greechie, R. J., Foulis, D. J., Pulmannová, S.: The center of an effect algebra. Order 12 (1995), 91–106. [5] Gudder, S. P.: Sharply dominating effect alge- bras. Tatra Mountains Math. Publ. 15 (1998), 23–30. [6] Gudder, S. P.: S-dominating effect algebras. In- ternat. J. Theor. Phys. 37 (1998), 915–923. [7] Jenča, G., Riečanová, Z.: On sharp elements in lattice ordered effect algebras. BUSEFAL 80 (1999), 24–29. [8] Kalina, M.: On central atoms of Archimedean atomic lattice effect algebras. Kybernetika 46 (2010), 4, 609–620. [9] Kalina, M.: Mac Neille completion of centers and centers of Mac Neille completions of lat- tice effect algebras. Kybernetika 46 (2010), 6, 635–647. [10] Kôpka, F.: Compatibility in D-posets. Internat. J. Theor. Phys. 34 (1995), 1 525–1 531. [11] Mosná, K.: About atoms in generalized efect algebras and their effect algebraic extensions. J. Electr. Engrg. 57 (2006), 7/s, 110–113. [12] Mosná, K., Paseka, J., Riečanová, Z.: Order convergence and order and interval topologies on posets and lattice effect algebras. In Proc. inter- nat. seminar UNCERTAINTY 2008, Publishing House of STU 2008, 45–62. [13] Paseka, J., Riečanová, Z.: The inheritance of BDE-property in sharply dominating lattice ef- fect algebras and (o)-continuous states. Soft Computing, 15 (2011), 543–555. [14] Riečanová, Z.: Compatibility and central ele- ments in effect algebras. Tatra Mountains Math. Publ. 16 (1999), 151–158. [15] Riečanová, Z.: Subalgebras, intervals and cen- tral elements of generalized effect algebras. In- ternat. J. Theor. Phys., 38 (1999), 3 209–3 220. [16] Riečanová, Z.: Generalization of blocks for D- lattices and lattice ordered effect algebras. In- ternat. J. Theor. Phys. 39 (2000), 231–237. [17] Riečanová, Z.: Orthogonal sets in effect al- gebras. Demontratio Mathematica 34 (2001), 525–532. [18] Riečanová, Z.: Smearing of states defined on sharp elements onto effect algebras. Internat. J. Theor. Phys. 41 (2002), 1 511–1524. [19] Riečanová, Z.: Subdirect decompositions of lat- tice effect algebras. Internat. J. Theor. Phys. 42 (2003), 1 425–1 433. [20] Riečanová, Z.: Distributive atomic effect akge- bras. Demontratio Mathematica 36 (2003), 247–259. [21] Riečanová, Z.: Lattice effect algebras densely embeddable into complete ones. Kybernetika, 47 (2011), 1, 100–109. [22] Riečanová, Z., Marinová, I.: Generalized ho- mogenous, prelattice and MV-effect algebras. Kybernetika 41 (2005), 129–142. Martin Kalina E-mail: kalina@math.sk Dept. of Mathematics Faculty of Civil Engineering Slovak Univ. of Technology Radlinského 11, Sk-813 68 Bratislava, Slovakia 31