The Age of Human Rights Journal, 12 (June 2019) pp. 13-34 ISSN: 2340-9592 DOI: 10.17561/tahrj.n12.2 13 MEDICAL MALPRACTICE AS A TORT IN THE U.S., AS A CRIME IN ITALY: FACTORS, CAUSES, PATHS AND OUTCOMES ANDREA DI LANDRO1 Abstract: The aim of the paper is, firstly, to try to understand the reasons for the different approaches to medical malpractice in two legal systems taken as models: the U.S., where professional negligence is almost exclusively subject of tort law; Italy, where criminal law instruments are instead widely used. The different extent of criminal responsibility for negligence and omission seems connectable to different political and cultural models: individualistic liberalism, on the one hand, solidarist statism and communitarianism, on the other hand; in juridical terms, to the ideal contrast between the reactive State and the active State; to the different approach to the relationship between subject and body, dominical-individual versus collectivist- social; with a tendential "privatization" of the health-good, in the US model, and a "socialization" of the good-health itself, in the Italian model. Secondly, the paper tries, in a comparative perspective, to evaluate these different approaches, in terms of access to justice, paths and outcomes of the two models. The article attempts to highlight the strengths and the weaknesses of the contingent-fee system in the U.S. tort arena, and of the criminal justice system as "free legal aid" in Italy: a balanced solution should also allow victims hindered by the costs and the length of civil actions the possibility of using these latter form of protection, avoiding that criminal justice is exploited for compensatory purposes. Indeed, tort law more easily can meet compensatory claims, due to the lower probative standard required, the preponderance of evidence, rather than the beyond any reasonable doubt standard, required in criminal law. Also in terms of outcomes, the main problems arising in the two systems need to be tackled: the problem of few persons compensated, allowing a greater number of injured parties to access to justice and obtain fair compensation; the problem of symbolic criminal convictions (observed in the Italian experience), avoiding the automatic use of suspended penalties and monetary penalties as substitute of penalties weighing on professional practice and freedom, since these automatic mechanisms limit the preventive effectiveness of the criminal sanction and run the risk of creating discrimination on a census basis. Keywords: medical malpractice, negligence, omission, access to justice, standard of proof. SUMMARY: I. Introduction. Medical malpractice in U.S. law. No criminal responsibility for personal injury negligence or involuntary manslaughter due to minor (not gross) negligence. From practical problems to political-criminal problems… II. (continued)…the distribution of omissive and negligent crimes, between individualistic liberalism, solidaristic statism and communitarianism; between the reactive State and the active State; between the individual model of property and the collective/communitarian model of inalienability; between “privatized” and “socialised” healthcare. III. “Access to justice”, paths and outcomes: contingent fee in tort area and criminal justice as “free legal aid”; “preponderance of evidence” and “beyond reasonable doubt”; compensation for a few people and symbolic criminal convictions. 1 Associate Professor of Criminal Law, University of Central Sicily “Kore”, Italy (andreadilandro@gmail.com). ANDREA DI LANDRO The Age of Human Rights Journal, 12 (June 2019) pp. 13-34 ISSN: 2340-9592 DOI: 10.17561/tahrj.n12.2 14 I. Introduction. Medical malpractice in U.S. law. No criminal responsibility for personal injury negligence or involuntary manslaughter due to minor (not gross) negligence. From practical problems to political-criminal problems… In Anglo-American law, medical conducts with inauspicious outcomes are subject matter mainly in the arena of civil law (malpractice tort law). In the arena of negligent liability, an important comparative difference is that in North-American criminal law, battery is generally punished only if commited with intent (so-called specific intent), and only exceptionally, in some jurisdictions, if due to negligence2. On the contrary, in Italian criminal law we find the crime of personal injury negligence (punishable with imprisonment of up to three months, or with a fine up to 309 euro: articles 590 - 590 sexies of the Italian criminal code), in addition to the crime of negligent homicide (punishable ex officio, as is standard in the Italian procedural system, with imprisonment from six months to five years: art. 589 - 590 sexies of the Italian criminal code). In common law, negligence has historically been approached autonomously with respect to different areas of the legal system. In criminal proceedings only gross negligence is relevant; in civil proceedings minor negligence is evaluated, in other words, unintentional fault. In fact, normally, negligence (also called carelessness) by health professionals and the related causal problems, especially about the omissive actus reus, are subject matter of civil law3. Therefore, in the U.S., criminal responsibility of the doctor is traditionally more limited than civil responsibility. In the context of criminal law, the first function of mental states (mens rea), with particular reference to negligence, is indeed to distinguish criminal and non-criminal conduct4. In U.S. law, unlike English law, great efforts have been undertaken to define gross negligence (criminal negligence), especially in the Model Penal Code (M.P.C.), Sec. § 2.02, lett. d): «A person acts negligently with respect to the material element of a crime when he/she should be aware of the substantial and unjustified risk related to his / her behavior. The risk must be of such a nature and entity that its failure to perceive by the agent subject, given the nature and purpose of his conduct, as well as the circumstances 2 V. Saunders v. State, 208 Tennessee 347, 345 S.W. 2d 899 (Tenn.1961), in LOEWY, Criminal Law, Eagan, Minnesota, 2003, 67. 3 On the relationship between criminal and civil negligence, in UK law, see HERRING & PALSER, The Duty of Care in Gross Negligence Manslaughter, in Crim. L. Rev., 2007, p. 24. 4 BLOCH-McMUNIGAL, Criminal Law: A Contemporary Approach. Cases, Statutes, and Problems, New York, 2005, p. 210. MEDICAL MALPRACTICE AS A TORT IN THE U.S., AS A CRIME IN ITALY: FACTORS, CAUSES, PATHS AND OUTCOMES The Age of Human Rights Journal, 12 (June 2019) pp. 13-34 ISSN: 2340-9592 DOI: 10.17561/tahrj.n12.2 15 known to him, involves a serious deviation from the standards of diligence that a reasonable person would observe in the same circumstances». It must be said that this autonomous, complex definition of criminal negligence, principally based on two elements "Substantial and unjustified risk of which the subject should be aware" and the "lack of perception that implies a serious deviation from the standards of diligence" ("failure to perceive” that “involves a serious deviation from the standard of care"), does not receive unanimous approval by the commentators 5 . In criminal proceedings, the fact that mental state is essentially a question of degree usually causes problems, from both a theoretical and a practical point of view6. In various U.S. jurisdictions, in order to put into effect and apply the Model Penal Code in case law, several epithets are used to describe the amount of negligence necessary to integrate negligent homicide. The most typical are: «criminal negligence», «gross negligence» and «culpable negligence». "About the only certainty of meaning one can ascribe to these epiteths - to quote a current U.S. manual7 - is that they require more than ordinary negligence, i. e., more than would be required in a civil case. Undesirable as this lack of certainty may be, it is probably unavoidable. Nobody has yet devised a formula which more precisely describes the degree of negligence necessary for involuntary manslaughter". To explain the “something extra” necessary for criminal negligence and to avoid a reprehensible vicious circle of evaluation tests, focus is usually placed on the «moral defect» that «can properly be imputed to instances where the defendant acts out of insensitivity to the interests of other people, and not merely out of an intellectual failure to grasp them»8. A notion of criminal negligence impregnated, therefore, by subjectivity, that contains a basis of morality9. It could also be defined as an intuitive conception of the mental state, that must be "felt" (by the jury), rather than analyzed. To the Italian doctrine, which has a long tradition of commitment to the myth- value of legality, this idea might seem contrary to the defense of civil rights: yet in the U.S. this is considered the best indication upon which to trace the boundary of criminal relevance, of negligence and other notions. 5 In a critical sense, see FLETCHER, Dogmas of the Model Penal Code, in 2 Buffalo Criminal Law Review, 3 (1998); ID, Basic Concepts of Criminal Law, Oxford, 1997, chap. 8; SIMONS, Dimensions of Negligence in Criminal and Tort Law, 3 Theoretical Inq. L., 305 (2002); EDGAR, Mens Rea, in Encyclopedia of Crime and Justice, 1037 (1983): "The terms that positively indicate the mens rea, basic, are fictions. The law deals with probative problems related to the mental states through the use of presumptions". 6BLOCH-McMUNIGAL, paper cited, p. 211. 7 LOEWY, Criminal Law, MN, 2003, 39. 8 Comment to Model Penal Code, § 2.02, Negligence. 9 HUSAK & SINGER, Of Innocence and Innocents: The Supreme Court and Mens Rea Since Herbert Packer, 2 Buffalo Criminal Law Review, 860 (1999). ANDREA DI LANDRO The Age of Human Rights Journal, 12 (June 2019) pp. 13-34 ISSN: 2340-9592 DOI: 10.17561/tahrj.n12.2 16 In a sense it is the “price” that the Anglo-Saxon system pays for a concept of negligence exclusive to the criminal system. A concept lacking in certain analytical parameters for establishing the notion, and above all the civil/penal shift, the “something extra” of criminal negligence appears to be resolved intuitively, "self-evident" to the criminal system itself. A system that definitively entrusts laymen to evaluate the criminal relevance of negligence. What is the approach of U.S. law regarding civil negligence? In the Second Reformulation of US Civil Law (Restatement of Torts, Second), the basic structure of civil negligence includes minor negligence. Civil negligence is defined in plainer terms than criminal negligence: "Negligence is conduct that falls below the standard established by law for the protection of others against unreasonable risk of harm. It does not include reckless conduct that disregards the interests of others". It is interesting to note how the most recurring question in U.S. law manuals is, in inverted terms, speculation on a question that is increasingly widespread among Italian criminal law scholars. Italian scholars focus on the question of legitimacy and/or opportunity to adjust restrictive terms regarding the concept of criminal negligence, to eventually cover cases of gross negligence (whether conscious or not). American criminal law scholars, on the contrary, start from the limit of grossness (the already existent de iure), consider whether it is desirable that in different areas of substantive law the concept of mental states becomes uniform, thus arriving to align criminal and civil negligence10. II. (continued) ... the distribution of omissive and negligent crimes, between individualistic liberalism, solidaristic statism and communitarianism; between the reactive State and the active State; between the individual model of property and the collective/communitarian model of inalienability; between "privatized" and "socialised" healthcare. The role of criminal law in Italy cannot be assessed outside of the overall legal, political and cultural context. To quote the Spanish scholar Silva Sanchez «The pretension to harmonize a maximum State and a minimum criminal law constitutes a contradiction in terms. For a single reason: insecurity about the perception of the services [...] directly or indirectly coming from the State leads to the exploitation of criminal law to guarantee (at least so it is claimed) them»11. From a political and cultural point of view, the "maximum State" (to resume the expression of Silva Sanchez) seems connected, in Italy (and perhaps in continental Europe in general), to the greater trust traditionally placed in regulatory interventions of the State. The idea is that "institutional public regulation is superior in allocating optimal well-being 10 Cfr. BLOCH-McMUNIGAL, paper cit., 318. 11 SILVA SANCHEZ, La expansión del derecho penal Aspectos de la política criminal en las sociedades postindustriales, Madrid, 2011, in particular chap. 4. MEDICAL MALPRACTICE AS A TORT IN THE U.S., AS A CRIME IN ITALY: FACTORS, CAUSES, PATHS AND OUTCOMES The Age of Human Rights Journal, 12 (June 2019) pp. 13-34 ISSN: 2340-9592 DOI: 10.17561/tahrj.n12.2 17 when compared to the "market". In other words, the developement of political-normative regulations produces superior desirable results on well-being than the commitment of the same well-being to uncontrolled forces within civil society"12. Given these premises, in States (like Italy) where criminal law traditionally carries out such a role, an invitation to prudence seems due. As when it is suggested to decisivly "trim" many branches off a criminal law system that is perceived, almost presumptively, as suffocating and primitive. The objective is to "transplant" concepts, models, ideas and systematic constructions applied by another legal system actualised in a different country13. In other words, a cure worse than the disease, if the much lauded elimination/reduction of some parts of the criminal "penal apparatus", despite its flaws, are not compensated by the introduction of adequate forms of substitutive control. The principle of criminal law as a last resort (extrema ratio), which certainly expresses a noble request, can simultaneously represent a "magic bullet" that easily lends itself to indistinct and uncontrolled use. A principle whose insignia seems obvious to recognise, but that still includes too many unknown "variables". Primarily "the difficulty or the impossibility of precisely defining the need for criminal sanctions and the sufficiency of non-criminal alternatives, with respective degrees of effectiveness, given the infeasibility of previous tests, shortcomings, discords and the doubtful value of unestimatable empirical findings"14. Beyond the hypercritical attempts to "demolish without reconstructing" and the preconceived defense of existing laws, it must be acknowledged – with F. Mantovani - that the main challenge of current criminal law seems to be its "crisis of solitude". In the face of various social problems, criminal law is often left not as the last (extrema) resort, but as the sole resort (ratio) in an attempt to "keep the peace"15. This also seems to be the case of medical responsibility. In the abscence of valid and alternative systems of control and socio-cultural counterforces, is it really feasible or desirable that criminal law recedes from a "hard line" defense of life, well-being and personal safety?16 12 SGUBBI, Il reato come rischio sociale, Bologna, 1990, 17. 13 To use an engineering metaphor, a "cogwheel" that spins in a given apparatus of rules could turne out to be not as functional in another one. 14 MANTOVANI, La "perenne crisi" e la "perenne vitalità" della pena. E la "crisi di solitudine" del diritto penale, in Studi in onore di Giorgio Marinucci, Milan, 2006, 1181. The author speaks also of "crisis of the crisis", in the sense that "the crisis of the criminal law is accompanied by the crisis of the proposed alternative models to the criminal law itself". 15 ID, paper cit., 1202. 16 As MANTOVANI teaches (paper cit.), the modern history of the criminal law consists precisely in a (never outdated) dialectic between legitimization, de-legitimization and re-legitimation: attempt to remove such dialectic contrapositions, from this point of view, represents only a sterile "intellectualism", a "reductionism" that smacks of an idealized "illuminism out of time and space". Even FIANDACA-MUSCO agree that <