Alternate Routes

Article

Resisting Subjection, Subjected Resistance:

Sadomasochism, Feminism, Moral Regulation and Self-

Formation

Phil Robinson

Once the technologies of control become the object of erotic

attachment, who is to say whether control is subverted by
eroticism, or whether eroticism is reintegrated into control?

(John K. Noyes, 1997:14)

Introduction:

Just as Foucault has lamented on how the "homosexual became a per-

sonage" (Foucault, 1978:43) in the late nineteenth century, so too did

sadomasochism (SM), a term originally coined by Krafft-Ebbing,

become a medicalized identity. However, while the incorporation of

sadomasochism into the discourse on sexuality may have occurred over

a century ago, it has only been in the late twentieth century that practitio-

ners of sadomasochism have begun to positively embrace their identi-

ties, form 'communities' and establish themselves as a political

constituency. The reasons for this can be traced to numerous events

including the rise of consumerist culture, the development of gay and

lesbian communities, and the re-emergence of feminism. For the present

purpose, the link between feminism and sadomasochism is particularly

insightful because SM has been a point of both celebration and contesta-
tion within lesbian-feminist communities. On the one hand, anti-SM les-

bian-feminists have attempted to morally regulate SM practices and
practitioners by claiming that SM is harmful to all women and that the
pio-SM position is a form of subjection to 'false consciousness' and

62 Volume 16, 2000



Chemins Altematif

'patriarchal values'. To counter this, lesbian SMers claim to be engaging

in transgressive political acts that resist and challenge forms of oppres-

sion. Furthermore, they claim that SM plays a therapeutic role and is a
means to self-actualization and 'truth.'

Both the pro- and anti-SM positions within lesbian-feminist commu-

nities can be seen as attempts to integrate lesbian-feminist theory with

personal desire (Butler, 1982) and lifestyle. While there are many differ-

ences between the two positions, they both hold on to some notion of the

'truth' about sex and grant it explanatory power, either as the site of

women's oppression or as a path to individual self-fulfillment. This dia-

lectic has been evident throughout the 'sex wars'. It is my view that the
'sex wars', including the debate over SM, have been occurring in the

context of a partial move away from emancipatory movements informed

by Marxist frameworks towards what Gidden's (1991) has termed "life

politics." I use this term of Gidden's to reflect a politics that does not

entirely abandon the emancipatory or liberatory agenda of movements

like feminism, but tends to conjoin this approach with one that focuses

on personal and collective fulfillment and actualization. The move away

from emancipatory movements and their attendant obligations and duties

is reflective of a move towards an ethic that stresses individual auton-

omy and where group membership is exercised through freedom of

choice and consumption (Rose, 1989,1994).

The debate between anti-SM lesbian-feminists and their pro-SM

counterparts raises numerous questions about the relationship between

subjectification and regulation on the one hand, and the potential for

resistance and liberation on the other. It is my argument that SM does
have the potential to resist certain forms of subjectification and that

claims that it represents a threat of harm to the social body are not ade-

quately substantiated. At the same time, by adopting certain technologies

of control from the larger social context, such as a power-powerless or

dominant-submissive dynamic, SM's potential for resistance is seriously

curtailed. Furthermore, while anti-SM lesbian-feminists are chastising

their pro-SM counterparts' immorality and lack of discipline, and while

SM lesbian-feminists herald their 'sexual liberation', there is a third
issue that needs to be articulated: the targets of moral regulation have, as

is consistent with patterns of moral regulation (Hunt, 1997:281), taken it

upon themselves to engage in a process of self- and community-forma-

tion. This process is therapeutic in nature and, in my view, may become

Volume 16, 2000 6.?



Alternate Routes

a point of resistance in itself. The emphasis on self- and community-for-

mation, as I hope to show, amount to new regulatory regimes within SM
communities. While this regulation cannot be assumed to be positive or

negative, it does serve as a reminder of Foucault's (1978) insistence that

'liberation', defined as freedom from regulation, is not possible.

Before discussing the main arguments within the SM debate, I would
like to briefly address the reasons for my own interest in this topic. I am
writing from a position that distinguishes between morality and my own
personal distaste and unease with simulations that blur distinctions

between sex and violence. My own sense of taste, then, is different from
my sense of morality in that a substantiated claim of social harm needs
to be evident before I accept something as inherently moral in nature. As

a self-identified pro-feminist man, it has been my project for many years
to develop an ethical position that is congruent with my identity and with
my sexuality. Included in this project is my desire to construct a political
approach to SM other than those currently offered. In light of this, the
intellectual endeavor I am undertaking can also be understood as a
project of self-formation.

SM as Subjectification: The Radical Feminist Critique
The existence of self-identified lesbian-feminist sadomasochists poses a

direct challenge to both feminist and lesbian-feminist theories. To begin,

the idea that women who identify as lesbian and as feminists could be
engaged in consensual 'violence' challenges a view of "lesbianism as

the beginning of passion, vulnerability, mutuality and trust" that offers

the possibility for a "re-posing of power as the extension and creation of

new ways of loving" (Butler, 1982:169). Inherent in this is also a chal-

lenge to how women are defined, which for many radical feminists has
included a moral differentiation from men. Lesbian-feminism, it

appears, has been faced with both a theoretical contradiction and a crisis

of discipline within its ranks. As a response, anti-SMers need a theoreti-

cal and moral position to reassert 'true' feminist self-formation and pur-

poseful solidarity. 1

The general response from radical feminists 2 has been that willful

participation in SM is a form of 'false consciousness' that is consistent
with patriarchal relations:

64 Volume 16. 2000



Chemins Altematif

The primary claim of [radical feminism] is that the erotici-

zation of violence or domination, and of pain or powerless-

ness, is at the core of sadomasochism and, consequently,

that the practice of sadomasochism embodies the same val-

ues as heterosexual practices of sexual domination in gen-

eral and sexually violent practices like rape in particular

(Bar-On, 1982:75).

Additionaly, SM actually strengthens these relations:

To degrade someone, even with that person's consent, is to

endorse the degradation of persons. It is to affirm that the

abuse of persons is acceptable. For if some people may be

humiliated and despised, all may be (Hein, 1982:87; empha-
sis in original).

SM is seen as an intolerable perpetuation of violence against women,
'male values' and 'patriarchal relations' that also mocks the very real

suffering of oppressed groups. As Herman states,

I am condemning s/m sex - sex that necessarily involves
and takes its pleasures in the (consensual and ritualized)

infliction of pain and humiliation within a setting that draws

upon and mimics the non-consensual abuse (as in main-

stream) of real-people - raped women, subjugated slaves,

and tortured prisoners (1996:152; emphasis in original).

These anti-SM critiques view SM practices as being appropriated from
the dominant culture (Herman, 1996:150) or, as Rich has stated, an

"acceptance by some lesbians of male homosexual mores" (1983:203).

Thus, when Davis, a lesbian-feminist sadomasochist, calls on lesbian-

feminism to "own your 'illegitimate' children" (1987:13), the response

from radical-feminist Atkinson is direct: "Your "enemy" is not the

Establishment per se. In fact, you claim as your life force the distillation

of the essence of that Establishment. Your enemy is the resistance of the

Establishment to recognize you as its own" (1982:91; emphasis in origi-

nal).

Volume 16, 2000 65



Alternate Routes

While pro-SM advocacy has not been welcome by most radical-femi-

nists, there seems to be a hesitancy amongst some radicals to be overly

critical of lesbian SM practitioners. One reason for this is the belief that
SM, although not justifiable, is a means to escape feelings of powerless-

ness that are inflicted upon lesbians and is a result of being "conditioned

to making bland observations and cynical jokes in response to obsceni-

ties of a national scale and perversity of universal magnitude. We are
numbed to the point of being at home with cruelty and despair" (Hein,

1982:88). The argument that lesbians have been subjected to a form of

conditioning or 'false consciousness' is central to the rejection of SM
practitioners' ability to consent. In essence, Marxist critiques of contract

theory are applied to sexual intercourse with the result that consent is not

possible in a patriarchal context where, it is argued, "men have power"

and "women are powerless" (Morgan, 1982:117). Just as some radical-

feminists argue that heterosexual intercourse cannot be separated from

rape because of structural inequities (i.e. MacKinnon, 1987), lesbian

sadomasochists cannot consent to practicing SM because their subjectiv-
ities and "desires are formed largely by social ideologies and institu-

tions" (Saxe, 1992:60). As Russell states,

Women have been reared to be submissive, to anticipate and
even want domination by men. But wanting or consenting

to domination and humiliation does not make it nonoppres-

sive. It merely demonstrates how deep and profound the

oppression is (1982:177).

Clearly there are problems with this claim, not the least of which is its

circular and self-supporting logic: what lesbian SMers do with each

other is patriarchy's fault and, rather than revealing a problem in radical

feminist logic, the existence of lesbian sadomasochists only serves to

prove how powerful patriarchy actually is. A related problem, which is
addressed by many SM lesbians, is the disempowerment that results
from a renunciation (if women's potential for individual agency.

The claim that SM is a private practice has also been denounced by
many radical-feminists. For Saxe, the acts themselves and their conse-

quences cannot be considered private. Even if they could be considered

private, she reminds us that "the so-called private sphere of the bedroom

is the site ol much of women's worst misogynist oppression" (1992:61).

66 Volume 16, 2000



Chemins Altematif

She believes that SM is highly visible, a concern that Morgan furthers by
arguing that depictions of lesbian SM reflect and reinforce patriarchal
portrayals of women as naturally masochistic (1982:110). This is viewed
as dangerous for women because, regardless of the participants' inten-
tions, the context in which these depictions are interpreted cannot be

controlled (see Star, 1982). Bar-On (1982) has reached the conclusion

that the social nature of sex means that sexual choices cannot rightfully

be decided upon by the individual alone. She argues that everything that

is social is rule governed and warns of the dangers that disallowing sex-

ual regulation could incite (1982:74). In many ways, as Rose (1989) has

pointed out, she is correct in that what is often considered private is in

fact public to the extent that it is governable. Nonetheless, the trend

towards legislating correct and incorrect sexual behaviour within femi-

nist communities led Butler, somewhat sympathetically, to site this as a

reason for the growth of SM. This is what she terms the "paradox" of

"the personal is political": when personal life is expected to conform to a

strict politics, sex seems to become "radically public" and open to com-

munal scrutiny (1982:171).

Critiques of the pro-SM position often include a challenge to its liber-

atory potential. Herman, wary of the possibility of sliding down the slip-

pery relativist slope, asserts that "radical pluralist" approaches to

difference need not cede the right to make value judgements (1996:151).

Similarly, Hein warns of the inherent liberalist approach to the realiza-

tion of the self that characterizes SM (1982:84). True liberation, it is
argued, is impossible under conditions of abuse - regardless of whether

the abuse is consentual (Bar-On, 1982) - and cannot be reached through

the fulfillment of individual desires. As Butler states, in response to Cal-

ifia's previous claim that desire is "impeccably honest", "to conceive of

desire as [an] 'impeccably honest' law unto itself as key to destroying

repressive sexual orders is to exaggerate the autonomy and intelligence

of desire" (1982:173). Desire, Butler argues, can only be as free as its

holders. In fact, some writers, such as Atkinson, argue that sexual libera-

tion is not a feminist goal because "feminists are women who are sick to
death of being defined sexually" (1982:91). However, other writers do

consider sexual liberation to be important but reject SM because it does
not involve making a personal and political choice to construct one's

own sexuality on one's own terms. If sexuality is socially constructed, as

most feminist theory posits, then the correct approach is to reconstruct

Volume 16, 2000 67



Alternate Routes

desire in such a way as to eliminate power dynamics from all relation-
ships. While it is observed that "perfect feminist relationships" are

impossible within a male-controlled society (Rian, 1982:47), it is none-

theless "crucial that both power and politics get reshaped and deepened

from having passed through the lesbian experience" (Butler, 1982:173).

Sexual relationships can also not be separated from the rest of life, a sep-

aration that is "patriarchal through and through" and associated with SM
(Bar-On, 1982:80).

For radical-feminists, sex represents an expression of intimacy and a

political bond that needs to be carefully managed. While its 'truths' can

be reclaimed only by cleansing it of patriarchy, it is also, as Foucault has

said, "the point of weakness where evil portents reach through to us"

(1978:69). Within this framework sex cannot be a means to self-realiza-

tion until after women have acquired self-determination and control over
the social structures that shape women's lives and sexual imagination.

Until that point, lesbians need to be vigilant in their moral self-forma-

tion, if for no other reason than for the sake of the movement.

In exploring the radical-feminist position, it is worth noting that the

Marxist roots of this emancipatory movement are clearly evident in

many respects. The approach taken is based largely upon Marx's histori-

cal materialism and has privileged one form of oppression as being

determinant. The privileged form of oppression of course revolves

around gender, or men's oppression of women within patriarchy,
although the specific way that this is formulated varies (for instance,

some emphasize reproduction, others emphasize sex itself, etc.). The

oppressed - women - are clearly distinguished from the oppressors and
are completely devoid of power. Women who disagree with this account
of their social position are deemed to have internalized a false conscious-

ness which, in conjunction with their totalizing and absolute powerlcss-

ness in relation to men, nullifies their ability to consent to anything.

Fortunately, there is hope for a revolution that will bring true liberation

and freedom. And, just as Marx did not anticipate any flexibility in capi-

talism, so too do radical-feminists believe that neither their politics nor

their identities will need to change in the process of subverting patriar-

chy.

It needs to be mentioned that I have focused primarily on one form of

radical feminism for my analysis. I have intentionally presented a rela-
tively unified position and have tried to present some of the basic tenets

68 Volume 16. 2000



Chemins Attentatif

for analytical purposes. There are several radical feminist objections to

SM that have not been mentioned thus far, such as the racism and anti-
semitism that some believe to be inherent in it (see Sims et. al., 1982). It

will become apparent through the course of my argument that my intent
is not to discard feminism or Marxism per se. Rather, my intent is to pro-
vide an account of the arguments put forth and to begin examining the

foundations upon which they rest in anticipation of a comparison to the

arguments and foundations of the pro-SM position.

SM as Resistance: The Pro-SM Position
As sadomasochists 'come out' in increasing numbers, the position that

they articulate has moved from a defense of their right to privacy to an

emphasis on political identity, spirituality and epistemology. Included in

this shift has been an insistence that SM is a legitimate sexual orientation
(Noyes, 1994:4) and, as such, deserves the same respect and protection

as other cultural minorities (i.e. Davis, 1987). In this sense, anti-SM dis-

course is deemed similar to racism and homophobia. The literature that

has been produced is diverse and, while academic literature has

increased, the majority claims its authority from the experience of SM
practitioners. It is important to note that the pro-SM position often (but

not always) aligns itself with feminism, and as such, has articulated itself

as a liberatory movement.

One of the impetuses for the growth in literature has been radical

feminist critiques of SM. These critiques, according to Rubin, force

members of "minority sexual communities" to "face an endless stream

of propaganda which rationalizes abuses against them, attempts to

impair their self esteem, and exhorts them to recant" (1987:225-6).

Rubin recognizes a need to evaluate sexual behaviour, but insists that an

all-engulfing attack on SM is a form of "cultural imperialism" that bases
its judgement not on issues of consent or harm, but rather on an inability

"to digest the concept of benign sexual variation" (1987:226). The argu-

ment here is that the radical feminist position problematizes conven-

tional styles of sex while simultaneously refusing to consider the

possibility that other styles exist. The reason for this, according to

Rubin, is because "if S/M is understood as the dark opposite of happy

and healthy lesbianism, accepting that happy and healthy lesbians do S/

M would threaten the logic of the belief system out of which this opposi-

Volume 16, 2000 69



Alternate Routes

tion was generated" (1987:215). The system of logic Rubin criticizes, in

addition to attributing oppression to particular styles of sexuality, insists

that certain sex acts are the 'cause' for other acts. By expanding the

scope to include a threat of harm not only to SM practitioners but to the
entire social body, the radical feminists have constructed a justification

for increased regulation.

In the context of the radical feminist position, SMers, particularly les-

bian-feminist SMers, have expanded the type and range of their claims

to legitimacy. Not only is SM defended as an individual freedom of
choice, it is positioned as being capable of providing numerous personal

benefits to its practitioners and as being an act of resistance that chal-

lenges current oppressive structures. In addition, increased emphasis has

been placed on the role of consent, fantasy, interpretation and the simula-

tive nature of SM 'play'.
Individual practitioners of SM have claimed to receive numerous per-

sonal benefits through the staged simulation of fantasy and desire.

Included amongst these benefits are therapeutic effects such as assertive-

ness training, release from tension, an ability to 'come to power',

increased bodily awareness, and assistance in dealing with personal fears

and experiences of abuse3 (see Thompson, 1991 and Portillo, 1991).

While many radical feminists have suggested that any problems experi-

enced by SMers are the result of patriarchy and are being addressed

through the re-enactment of patriarchal values and power structures, SM
practitioners focus on the simulative context and on the individual inter-

pretation and meaning attributed to 'playing' through 'scenes.' Much of

the sociological literature supports the interpretive approach to SM, cit-

ing the emphasis placed on control, trust and consent in its enactment, as

well as research findings in which the majority of SMers have been

found to feel positive about themselves and their sexuality (see studies

cited in Weinberg, 1994).

Hopkins has suggested that the simulative nature of SM needs to be
distinguished from replications of patriarchal relationships. He acknowl-

edges that SM is not unproblematic within a context of patriarchal ine-
quality while simultaneously noting that the core features of patriarchy,

such as coercive violence, arc absent in SM settings. The stance taken by
Hopkins is premised on his acceptance of the "radically honest, demo-

cratic model of consent" developed within SM communities (1994: 127).
He has also noted the potential for gender subversion within SM prac-

70 Volume 16, 2000



Chemins Attentat if

tices in the way they can challenge a static patriarchal framework in

which men are dominant and women submissive.

Radical feminists generally do not accept the argument that SM can
subvert women's traditionally submissive role because they believe that

power cannot be defeated by enacting it. SM practitioners, on the other
hand, view power as inevitable. Rather than forming what one could

consider fantasies of a power-free society, the pro-SM position argues

that parodying power relations is a form of resistance that also enables

them to gain a better understanding of power - an understanding that

some perceive to be withheld by elites who have a vested interest in

maintaining its invisibility. Undoubtedly, as Foucault has argued, "power

is tolerable only on condition that it mask a substantial part of itself

(1978:86). Attempting to escape the subjectivizing function attached to

power could be viewed as a radically transgressive form of resistance.

As stated by Noyes, "the masochistic move is to seize upon the machin-

ery of domination and pervert its usage, attempting to derive nothing but

sexual pleasure from machines that were designed to effect the smooth

running of social structures" (1997:12).

While Noyes argues that parodying technologies of control is subver-

sive, he simultaneously questions its revolutionary potential by arguing

that such parodies can perpetuate technologies of social control. This lat-

ter insight is neither recognized nor accepted by many practitioners of

SM. For instance, in a recent anthology, "leatherfolk" (a term used for

SM practitioners who wear leather attire) are described as being the
"avatars of the new" (Thompson, 1991:xx), the "next generation" in the

"evolution of sexuality" (Portillo, 1991:50) who are committing "the

ultimate act of defiance" (Portillo, 1991:55). This "ultimate act" is aimed

at challenging "a world that functions on sexual repression", a world in

which "The explosion of private sexual fantasy into public view is a

powerful political statement" (Bronski, 1991:64). It is ironic that the SM
literature argues that oppression is not reducible to sex and simulta-

neously claims either that radical sex has revolutionary potential or that

freedom is synonymous with sexual liberation. This is an important

point that will be raised again shortly.

Volume 16, 2000 71



Alternate Routes

SM, Self-Formation and Community-Formation

One component of moral regulation noted by Hunt is that it "characteris-

tically incites those at whom it is directed to engage in practices of self
formation" (1997:281). This is particularly true of SMers, although I

would also add that, in some circumstances, moral regulation also incites

processes of community-formation. While the processes through which

many sadomasochists have developed personal and community identi-

ties differ to varying degrees, attempts to regulate and morally indict

sadomasochists has spawned some consistency in efforts to instruct the

subjectivities of its practitioners. This maneuver can be interpreted as

primarily defensive, although it could be argued that other influences,

such as self-help and new age movements, have also acted as impetuses.

However, based on the evidence available, I would conclude that these

latter movements have primarily facilitated, not caused, the trend

towards self- and community-formation within sadomasochist commu-

nities.

For the most part, medical and psychiatric expertise have been drawn

upon only insofar as SM confronts medical and legal prohibitions or in
the dispensing of knowledge for the purpose of healthy sexual practice.

The primary form of expertise evident in the literature is experience

itself, which is fitting given the emphasis placed upon the self in the pro-

cess of formation. The credibility of experience as expertise can perhaps

also be understood in the context of SM's contested relationship with the

professions. Clearly, self-formation aims towards a positive definition of

the self, something that may not be possible from those who have histor-

ically been complicit with sanctions against SM. An additional form of

expertise that is increasingly referenced is spiritual expertise, although

this form of expertise is itself generally based in personal experience.

Self-formation amongst SM practitioners is simultaneously diverse
and isomorphic. In many respects, it reflects what Simonds (1995) refers

to as the "paradox of self-help literature": on the one hand, the self is

viewed as a project that is constantly being constructed; on the other

hand, a true self already exists and is waiting for discovery. While this

paradox is reflected in the SM community, it requires two additional
considerations. First, while many SMers are searching for their 'truth',

they may not locate it within the mind. Rather, for some, the body holds

the key to the self (see Fair, 1987:1 84). I do realize that some commenta-

tors, such as Giddens (1991), have remarked that in late modernity the

72 Volume 16. 2000



Chemins Altematif

body has become reflexive and a site to be controlled and constructed,

but this does not necessarily equate with a search for truth itself in the

body.

A second concern I have with the paradox is that the message pre-
sented by some SM advocates is to accept yourself as you are, not as
what you should or could become (see Davis, 1987; Jacques, 1993). This

could be interpreted as an essentialist position, and some SM practitio-
ners do indeed perceive themselves to be 'bom that way' (i.e. Vesta,

1991), but it is intended (at least by some) as a statement about accepting

your desires and subjectivity without judgement. In this regard the goal

is to unapologetically abandon normative expectations.

The spiritual and epistemological aspects are perhaps the most inter-

esting developments in the trend towards self-formation amongst SMers.

For instance, in the introduction to Leathetfolk: Radical Sex, People,

Politics and Practice, Thompson describes leatherfolk as "the most

expert investigators of eros" (1991:xiii) for whom "radical sexual expe-
rience is a triumphant reminder to live in the Now" and a "fierce com-
mitment to life" (xvi). The message is that SM is "a process of
liberation" (xiv) or self-formation that can "serve deep spiritual needs

for wholeness and completion" (xvii). SM, according to Thompson,

appears to be a very enticing means to heal wounds, erase shame and

come to terms with negative aspects of our selves. It is worth quoting

liberally from his writing:

Through erotic enactment and the emotional catharsis it pro-

vides, radical sexuality can be an empowering, soul-making

process... For many in the leather community today, S/M

actually means "sex magic." It is their art, and craft, and

means of taking a shamanic journey into the "other world"

of personal and collective myth. It is in that secret inner

place where the healing occurs.The soul is an earthy place,

and we cannot sanitize it in order to make claims of "getting
well." As we descend through the psyche's strata we dis-

cover violence: Dream images of strange drama and torture

are not uncommon. The inner world is a place of blood and

fire, tears and mud. It is the soul's nature to be in organic

upheaval, a perpetual state of death and rebirth, just like the

Volume 16, 2000 7J



Alternate Routes

outer world around it. We cannot put a lid on our soul busi-
ness and its disquieting work. In this context, to acknowl-

edge and explore one's S/M interests and instincts is to act

in the truth (xviii).

Thompson's writing actively implores the reader to seek help, to address

the dangers that lie deep within the self and to act in the name of 'truth.'

His perspective is not unique within the anthology he edited; in fact,

there is an entire section addressing such topics as "the spiritual dimen-

sions of bondage," complete with interviews from spiritual leaders like

Purusha the Androgyne and the "magical masochist" Fakir Musafar.

Despite differences in the content and process of self-formation, there

are similarities in how the technologies of the self are deployed. For

instance, there are many references to what Foucault (1978) has

described as the urge to discover the secrets that sex holds and an insis-

tence that it reveals its truths about ourselves. In fact, the emphasis on

'truth' and its accessibility is a frequent theme throughout much of the

literature. The discovery or construction of 'truth' is presented as self-

actualization through the mastery of one's own experience - especially

sexual experience. Giddens (1991) has commented upon the increased

tendency to focus on self-actualization as a goal that can be achieved

through the mastery of the body and sexuality. In order for the process of

separating 'true' from 'false' selves to be successful, it requires authen-

ticity - which, according to Giddens, is dependent upon understanding

one's own self-formation and identity as being distinct from the technol-

ogies of control. Without such a distinction, the moral meaning is lost.

This insight from Giddens may be helpful, at least to some degree, in

explaining the seeming need for SMers to claim a distance from sexual

mores and regulatory systems. Then again, it is possible that this dis-

tance is simply for pleasure - as Foucault (1978) has commented, the act

of resisting sexual regulation is a source of pleasure in itself.

Ironically, Rose ( 1989) has pointed out that managing the self is par-

tially about the repression or even obliteration of the self. In other words,

as one forms the self, any previous selves or alternative choices are sub-

sumed. This insight is particularly applicable to SM, not only because

the construction of the self represses other selves, but because the very

nature of SM involves playing artifical roles in circumstances in which

74 Volume 16, 2000



Chem'ms Alternatif

the participants may be entirely interchangeable. One's individual iden-

tity may not really matter that much in SM scenes.
The formation of a SM identity is a prerequisite for joining a SM

community. For all intensive purposes, SM communities can be charac-
terized by voluntary associations with others who share similar interests

in sadomasochistic sexual consumption. While there seems to be

increasing acceptance of SM as a cultural minority, it would be prema-
ture to assume that all SM practitioners take this position. Indeed, it
would be problematic to assume that all SM practitioners are involved in
a SM community because these communities take many forms and are
not always visible. For instance, SM communities may not have a spa-
tially defined location as they often develop over the internet or through

newsletters and magazines (see Iloulberg, 1995). It is also important to

note that there are often different SM communities, even within the same
geographical area.

Regulation is an important aspect of the SM community. The primary
role that it plays in this regard is to police the sexual conduct of its mem-

bers, although this does not occur in a formal manner. Rather, SM practi-
tioners have repeatedly claimed that the importance of reputation within

small minority communities acts to ensure that people who do not accept

the rules around consent and safety are identified and have difficulty

finding willing partners (i.e. Rubin, 1987; Weinberg, 1994). In addition

to this, there have been numerous SM manuals and guides that have been
published for the purpose of creating shared understandings of the

expectations of SM participants (i.e. Jacques, 1993). While these devel-
opments are definitely positive, there seems to be an assumption that the

formation of communities negates problems related to sexualized vio-

lence. Certainly not all SM practitioners are involved in a close-knit
community. The tendency for SMers to glorify the lovingness and mutu-

ality of the SM community has been commented upon by Bersani
(1995:87), although I suspect that the vulnerability felt within the SM
community is the impetus for the overly cheery depictions in the litera-

ture.

The development of SM communities is premised on the exercising
of citizenship through voluntary affiliation and sexual consumption.

4

However, these communities increasingly appear to be demanding mem-

bers to regulate themselves in a manner that is in keeping with the rules

of consent and safety. This is entirely justifiable. What may not be so

Volume 16, 2000 75



Alternate Routes

justifiable and may in fact become a point of resistance within SM com-
munities is the tendency to increasingly regulate members' identities and

value systems. Similar to how gay and lesbian communities developed

and imposed standards defining what it meant to be gay or lesbian, so

too might SM communities adopt increasingly rigid identities and val-
ues. Duncan (1996) has already identified problems experienced by

some SM lesbians of colour who feel that differences within SM com-
munities have not been addressed and remain hierarchical.

Sexual identity categories are problematic in that they are inherently

instruments of regulatory regimes. However, as Foucault (1978) has

noted, they simultaneously facilitate resistance. They are a prerequisite

for political mobilization and for the development of communities and a

common language through which resistance can be expressed (Weeks,
1991:92). In short, sexual identities are both enabling and disabling. To

avoid the regulative possibilities as well as the urge to essentialize, my
own approach would be to adopt something akin to Epstein's (1987)
notion of sexual identities and communities as consisting of a combina-

tion of external ascription and chosen affiliation. This could possibly

provide the fluidity needed to accommodate difference while not aban-

doning the potential for developing a strong political constituency.

Discussion and Conclusion:

So what is an observer to make of this situation? As I stated in the intro-

duction, one of my reasons for undertaking this project is an attempt to
develop an ethical and political approach to SM. If one is generally sup-
portive of emancipatory movements like feminism and is simultaneously

committed to the 'liberal' values of 'free' choice, 5 what would be an eth-

ical and politically desirable stance to take? The task of determining

such a position is not made any easier when one considers that regula-

tion, including moral regulation, is inherently neither positive nor nega-

tive (see Hunt, 1997). And, as Herman (1996:148) has pointed out,

supporting sadomasochism and its practitioners is as much of a moral

decision as it would be to not support them. What follows is not a com-

prehensive appraisal of all the issues that need to be considered, but

rather it is my own attempt to begin addressing what I feel are some of
the basic concerns and contradictions that have been raised.

76 Volume 10. 2000



Chemins Alternotif

Sadomasochism does occur within a context where social relations

are imbued with a dominant-submissive dynamic. While this dynamic is

apparent within work and family relationships, as Chancer (1992) and

others have analyzed, it is perhaps most apparent within the realm of sex

and sexuality. Regardless of whether the sexualization of power relation-

ships is viewed as a 'natural' occurrence or a symptom of something like

patriarchy, SM, even if considered as parody, does reflect and reify this

context. In this regard, SM can be characterized as "profoundly conser-
vative in that its imagination of pleasure is almost entirely defined by the

dominant culture" (Bersani, 1995:87). The construction of a sexual ori-

entation that defines itself through its participation in the technologies of

control is an act of accepting power as it is already structured. By this

account, SM - parody or not - supports the structures of power and, by
giving them the appearance of being harmless and playful, gives these

structures an attractiveness that is presented as being outside of ideology

and politics (see Bersani, 1995). Contrary to the idealistic claims of SM
practitioners, one cannot escape from and re-enter the social context at

will.

It is my interpretation of the context in which SM occurs that keeps
me from discarding the radical feminist argument entirely. Structural
arguments, such as that put forth by radical feminists, are not holistic

enough to provide a complete account of sex, power, or the social. None-

theless, an awareness of oppression - and I support the use of the term

'oppression,' although I do not believe its form is as simple as posited by

radical feminists - can cause a strong "gut" reaction6 to images, for

instance, of SM practitioners enacting scenes with dominant "Nazis" and
submissive "Jews." Public statements that indicate an unapologetic

enjoyment of torture can have a strong impact, regardless of the intent of

the speaker. For instance, I had a negative reaction upon reading excerpts

like this one from an SM practitioner who is reflecting on "stalking its
prey": "I wanted to be mean, tough, vicious, revengeful, cruel, and cold.

The women I found fed the dark side with their desires to be taken and

beaten and told what to do. This paradise of hell was mine, and with con-

sent!" (Antolovich, 1991:152). The writer, Antolovich, goes on to raise

the issue of consent, although she does not answer her own question:

Volume 16, 2000 77



Alternate Routes

Inside my own inner dungeon I asked myself, "What is their
consent about anyway? What does their consent mean

when all they've known is abusive relationships? With me
they at least give permission. How can a person really con-
sent when they think that their role is to do everything they

are told to do? How can they give consent when they want
to please absolutely, either because they are in lust/crush or

codependence?" I started to wonder if the Law of the Uni-
verse - "Like attracts like" - was in action here: my dark
side attracting their dark side. Meanwhile... (1991:252).

Antolovich herself questions the ability of her partners to consent and

her only apparent answer is that, "With me they at least give permis-
sion." The question that Antolovich asked is left unanswered, thereby

lending some credibility to the radical feminist argument that consent is

not possible when power is unequally distributed.

The radical feminist argument against the acceptability of consent as

a defense for SM is nonetheless very problematic. Theoretically, I would
agree that true consent - that which is unaffected by power relations - is

not possible in a SM relationship. I would also argue, and quite strongly,
that this theoretical stance, while intellectually revealing, is inapplicable

because no relationships have an equal distribution of power. Certainly

differences or similarities in structural location - for instance class, gen-

der, and race - affect the distribution of power, but so does personality,

reputation, and other criteria. The gender reductionist stance adopted by

radical feminism does not and cannot provide a full account of power,

other than to wish it away - a wish that is as much a fantasy as any being

acted out on the SM scene.
The argument that SM does take place within a social context where

power is regularly used and abused is accepted for my purposes here,
although accepting this is not meant to imply I agree with the radical

feminist claim that SM is harmful to society generally or to women in
particular. The evidence for such a claim docs not exist beyond theoreti-

cal statements suggesting an intuitive relation between SM and violence
against women. If the patriarchal context is to be considered in an analy-

sis ol SM, then it is important to consider the amount of violent imagers

that is produced ami consumed daily within that context. Sadomasoch-

7.S Volume 16, 2000



Chemins Attentat if

ism is not unique: in fact, images of consensual flagellation are far less

prevalent and arguably much less harmful than, for example, movies that

are rife with graphic images of war and mindless cruelty. With this in

mind, it is important to carefully consider claims that SM is responsible
for or a contributing factor in 'real life' violent sexual acts anymore than

Rambo is responsible for real massacres.

A full account of the context in which SM is practiced also requires a
consideration of the increasingly 'virtual' or symbolic nature of popular

culture. As early as 1969 Gebhard suggested that "it may be that a soci-

ety must be extremely complex and heavily reliant upon symbolism

before the inescapable repressions and frustrations of life... can be

expressed symbolically in S&M" (cited in Weinberg, 1994:276). In this
sense, then, perhaps SM can be viewed as a mere simulation amongst
many simulations. However, Gebhard also notes that dominance-sub-

mission relationships must be embedded within a culture that values

aggression before SM can become institutionalized (Weinberg,
1994:276-277). This latter consideration reinforces my hesitancy to

whole-heartedly endorse SM. While there is some potential for resis-

tance through SM, the subversive parody of power is always temporary

and never mounts a substantial challenge to structural relations of power.

If liberation requires attacking the roots of political rationality, as Fou-

cault (1981) has claimed, then arguments positing the liberatory power

of SM are seriously misguided.
Radical feminism requests that SM practitioners reconstruct their

desires or, at the very least, repress them for the sake of the movement.

Thinking critically of one's desires is laudable, although it is incorrect to

assume that this is antithetical to SM. But this is not the point I wish to

make. Rather, the concern I have is with attempts by a social movement

to enforce such a strict regime of moral regulation upon its members.

Such attempts, like moral regulation projects in general, can never be

completely successful. This is not to suggest that creating shared values

is a bad thing; what it does suggest is that the development of a social

movement's subjective understanding of itself and its cause must be

capable of change and be flexible enough to account for difference. In

other words, standards need to be relative and not absolute, just as appar-

ent contradictions within the movement need to be discussed but not

arbitrarily and artificially legislated into silence.

Volume 16, 2000 79



Alternate Routes

The tendency for emancipatory movements like radical feminism to

morally regulate its supporters in an absolutist manner is one of the rea-

sons, in my view, for the attractiveness of 'life politics.' A second reason
for the growth of life politics, with its emphasis on empowerment

through consumption, is a response to the lack of control people feel

over what can broadly be deemed 'the social.' Structural approaches

have been faced with resistance and an inability to counter the numerous

ways in which their claims can be co-opted without necessarily resulting

in a restructuring of power relations. Blame for this could arguably rest

with the structural approaches themselves, but the increasingly interna-

tional context in which their claims must be made has rendered the struc-

tural targets of change (politics, economics, and culture, for instance)

unresponsive. A third reason, and perhaps the most important, is that
consumer culture and life politics is simply more suited to a context of

rampant individualism. In this context, the technologies that push people

to develop themselves as unique individuals through consumption is at

odds with the communal identification required by structural move-

ments.

My reason for raising the move away from emancipatory politics and
toward life politics is because it relates to SM in several ways. For the
sake of clarity, it needs to be restated that my use of the term 'life poli-
tics' does not presuppose the disappearance or illegitimacy of emancipa-

tory movements. This is particularly true for the SM communities' that
ironically claim sex and sexuality do not cause oppression, and at the

same time make claims of being structurally oppressed because of their

sexuality. I do believe that sex and sexuality are repressed, contra Fou-

cault, but the claim that SM practitioners are structurally oppressed sim-
ilar to gays, lesbians, or people of colour requires some consideration.

What is being posited is more than a claim for tolerance or even accep-

tance: the claim suggests that anyone committed to addressing inequality

needs to be an advocate for SM in order to be authentic. Failing to do so
would be an admission of intolerance, insensitivity and complacency -

in effect, an act of oppression itself.

Butler (1997) has argued that culture-based identities can be the tar-

get of systemic oppression, but her argument is based on an analysis of

sexual orientation, not SM. The experience of 'sexual minorities',

namely gay men and lesbians, is often used by SM advocates to argue
thai they too are a sexual minority that deserves certain 'rights'.

7 While I

80 Volume 16. 2000



Chemins Altematif

agree that SM practitioners do face discrimination in certain circum-
stances, for instance at some lesbian-feminist events, I do not consider

this to be systemic (nor, in some situations, unjustified). In order to be

systemic, SM would need to be recognized as an identity, a point that I
shall now address.

There has been some movement within SM communities to define
SM as a sexual orientation and a public identity. This is evident in the
importance placed on publicly 'coming out' (for instance, Portillo,

1991). However, this approach contradicts some of the defenses for SM
put forth, such as the claim that SM roles and power dynamics are kept
in the 'playroom' and hence are not a threat to the larger society. More

importantly, however, it suggests an essentialist notion of what SM sig-
nifies, which poses problems for SM communities' emphasis on the
importance of interpretation and fluidity of meaning. If SM is presented
as a (at least somewhat) static and fixed identity, then it would also fol-

low that a definition of what constitutes a sadomasochist is required. I

have avoided such an endeavor thus far because defining the sadomas-

ochist requires placing boundaries around what constitutes SM. This has

been done, but the definitions presented generally revolve around some

notion of fantasy, interpretation, safety and consent (examples can be

found in Jacques, 1993). These criteria are not sufficient for the task of

differentiating SM from 'normal' sexual activity and hint that such a def-
inition may very well be incompatible with SM's interpretive and fluid

nature. It is my own view, which is shared by some SM practitioners (i.e.
Thompson, 1991) that a concrete division between SMers and non-

SMers is impossible, particularly since the acts that are assumed to com-

prise SM scenes are not uncommon (i.e. bondage).
The difficulty inherent in delineating the difference between SM and

other, non-SM sexual activities suggests sexual acts themselves are not

sufficient in the allocation of rights. The distinction Foucault has made

between the 'freedom of relationships' and the 'freedom of sexual acts'

is helpful in this regard (cited in Weeks, 1991:166). While Foucault was

referring to 'freedoms', his framework can be applied to 'rights' such

that there is a differentiation between 'relationship rights' and 'sexual

rights.' The former would include the right to determine with whom and
under what conditions one engages in sexual activity and personal rela-

tionships in general. The latter, on the other hand, refers to sexual acts or

styles which individuals are free to participate in if they so choose. 'Sex-

Volume 16, 2000 81



Alternate Routes

ual rights,' because they are based on sexual style, are not subject to sys-

temic discrimination. My argument here is different from some pro-SM
positions, particularly that of Rubin (1987), which seems to claim that

sexual 'style' equates with 'cultural minority' in a legal sense. If Rubin's

connection is accepted, then any leisure activity and styles thereof could

claim their own particular 'rights.'

Despite my argument that SM practitioners should not be recognized
as a distinct constituency deserving their own 'rights,' I strongly oppose

any form of regulation that inhibits their ability to freely participate in

consensual SM activities. All remaining legal prohibitions against SM
need to be challenged. Furthermore, public services, such as the legal

system, the police, sexual assault centers, and the health care system

need to offer services that are free from any discriminatory bias against

SM practitioners. Similarly, public education on sexuality and health
needs to include some basic information on SM. In essence, while I

reject the notion that 'rights' should be allocated based on an individual

or group's identification with SM, I do believe that the needs of SMers

should be incorporated into public services and treated in the same man-

ner as many other recreational activities.8 1 do realize that such an incor-
poration invariably risks increasing the degree to which SM
communities are regulated, but I am not in a position to determine
whether the net impact would be positive or negative for SM practitio-
ners.

One of my main concerns in addressing SM is my own awareness of
the ways in which it has been used to destabilize feminism and gay and

lesbian politics. While debates over this issue within feminist and gay

communities is inevitable, the existence of SM has contributed to a con-
text in which these communities are increasingly pressured to govern

themselves and regulate SM in order to acquire public approval, funding,
and political credibility. This will not change in the future. To some

extent, contradictions are inescapable within political movements that

value difference. Other than what has already been stated here, I do not

offer any additional recommendations except to emphasize the need for

discussion and flexibility in the political approaches that are considered.

While I have attempted to articulate my personal approach to SM and
some possible future directions for sexual politics, my perspective is not
fixed and will undoubtedly change as the political climate and my own
subjective understanding of the issues evolve. In the end, however, per-

82 Volume 16. 2000



Chemins Altematif

haps Rubin is correct when she states that, "ultimately, acceptance is

gained by political power as much as by rational argument" (1987:225).

Notes

1. Hunt (1997) discusses how moral self-formation is critical for the agents of

moral regulation, as well as the tendency to institute self-control within social

movements to promote the capacity for purposeful conduct.

2. The term 'radical feminist' or 'radical feminism' will be used to connote the

anti-SM position. While this is not an entirely adequate signifier, there tends to

be a relation between the more radical strands of feminism and the anti-SM

position. By using this term, 1 also hope to avoid confusion between the anti-

SM lesbian-feminist position and the pro-SM lesbian-feminist position.

3. Note that most SM practitioners reject the assumption that SM practice is the
effect of personal histories of abuse.

4. 1 have adopted this description of citizenship from Rose (1989).

5. I have put 'liberal' in quotes simply because there seems to be a tendency in

both the radical feminist and lesbian-feminist literature on sadomasochism to

attach negative connotations to anything attributed to 'liberalism' (even while

both positions incorporate some version of it). While values of 'free' choice are

certainly liberal, I think it is dangerous to use 'liberal' as a code word to

arbitrarily dismiss everything associated with it as 'bad' or even 'patriarchal.'

'Free' is in quotes simply to acknowledge that free choice is never truly 'free' in

the sense that individual subjectivity and autonomy are far from absolute within

a liberal social context.

6. I borrow this term from Hopkins (1994).

7. I have not been able to locate a clear articulation of what these 'rights' would

entail, other than the eradication of explicit legal prohibitions and vague

references to freedom from shame through social recognition.

8. I am thinking, for instance, about the health services provided to recreational

sport associations.

Volume 16, 2000 83



Alternate Routes

References Cited

Atkinson, Ti-Grace

1982 "Why I'm Against S/M Liberation." Pp. 90-92. In Linden ct al (eds.),
Against Sadomasochism: A Radical Feminist Analysis. San Pal Alto, C.A.: Frog

in the Well.

Bar On, Bat-Ami

1982 "Feminism and Sadomasochism: Self-Critical Notes." Pp. 72-82. In Lin-

den et al (eds.), Against Sadomasochism: A Radical Feminist Analysis. San Palo

Alto: Frog in the Well.

Bersani, Leo

1995 Homos. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.

Bronski, Michael

1991 "A Dream is a Wish Your Heart Makes: Notes on the Materialization of

Sexual Fantasy." Pp. 56-64. In Mark Thompson (ed.), Leatherfolk: Radical Sex,

People, Politics and Practice. Boston: Alyson Publications, Inc.

Butler, Judith

1982 "Lesbian S & M: The Politics of Dis-illusion." Pp. 168-175. In Linden et
al (eds.), Against Sadomasochism: A Radical Feminist Analysis. San Palo Alto:

Frog in the Well.

1991 "Imitation and Gender Insubordination." Pp. 13-31. In Diana Fuss (ed.),

Inside/Out: Lesbian Theories, Gay Theories. New York: Routledge.

Chancer, Lynn S.

Sadomasochism in Everyday Life: The Dynamics of Power and Powerlessness.

New Brunswick, N.J.: Rutgers University Press.

Davis, Katherine

1987 "Introduction: What We Fear We Try to Keep Contained." Pp. 7-13. In
Samois (eds), Coming To Power: Writings and Graphics on Lesbian S/M. Bos-

ton: Alyson Publications, Inc.

Duncan, Patricia L.

1996 "Identity, Power, and Difference: Negotiating Conflict in an S/M Dyke

Community." Pp. 87-114. In Brett Beemyn and Mickey Fliason (eds.), Queer

Studies: A Lesbian, Gay, Bisexual and I'ransgender Anthology. New York: New

York University Press.

84 Volume 16, 2000



Chemins Attentat if

Epstein, Steven

1987 "Gay Politics, Ethnic Identity: The Limits of Social Constructionism."

Socialist Review. 93/94:9-54.

Farr, Susan

1987 "The Art of Discipline: Creating Erotic Dramas of Play and Power." Pp.

183-191. In Samois (eds.), Coming to Power: Writings and Graphics on Les-

bian S/M. Boston. Alyson Publications, Inc.

Foucault, Michel

1978 The History of Sexuality, Volume One: An Introduction, (trans. Robert

Hurley). New York: Random House.

1981 "Omnes et Singulatim: Towards a Criticism of 'Political Reason'." Pp.

223-254. In S. McMurrin (ed.), The Tanner Lectures on Human Values (Volume

2). Salt Lake City: University of Utah Press.

Giddens, Anthony

1991 Modernity and Self-Identity: Self and Society in the Late Modern Age.

Cambridge, U.K.: Polity Press.

Hein, Hilde

1982 "Sadomasochism and the Liberal Tradition." Pp. 83-89. In Linden et al

(eds.), Against Sadomasochism: A Radical Feminist Analysis. San Palo Alto,

C.A.: Frog in the Well.

Herman, Didi

1996 "Law and Morality Re-Visited: The Politics of Regulating Sado-Masoch-

istic Porn/Practice." Pp. 147-166. In Austin Sarat and Susan Silbey (eds.), Stud-

ies in Law, Politics and Society (Vol.15). Greenwich, Conn.: JAI Press.

Hopkins, Patrick D.

1994 "Rethinking Sadomasochism: Feminism, Interpretation, and Simulation."

Hypatia. 9(1): 116-141.

Houlberg, Rick

1995 "The Magazine of a Sadomasochism Club: The Tic That Binds." Pp.269-

286. In Thomas S. Weinberg (ed.), S&M: Studies in Dominance and Submis-

sion. Amherst, N.Y.: Prometheus Books.

Volume 16, 2000 85



Alternate Routes

Hunt, Alan

1997 "Moral Regulation and Making-Up the New Person: Putting Gramsci to
Work." Theoretical Criminology. 1(3):275-301.

Jacques, Trevor

1993 On the Safe Edge: A Manual I-'orSM Play. Toronto: WholcSM Publishing.

MacKinnon, Catherine

1987 Feminism Unmodified. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

Morgan, Robin

1991 "The Politics of Sado-Masochistic Fantasies." Pp. 109-123. In Linden et al

(eds.), Against Sadomasochism: A Radical Feminist Analysis. San Palo Alto,

C.A.: Frog in the Well.

Noyes, John K.

1997 The Mastery of Submission: Inventions of Masochism. Ithaca: Cornell

University Press.

Portillo, Tina

1991 "I get Real: Celebrating My Sadomasochistic Soul." Pp. 49-55. In Mark
Thompson (cd.), Leatherfolk: Radical Sex, People, Politics and Practice. Bos-

ton: Alyson Publications, Inc.

Rian, Karen

1982 "Sadomasochism and the Social Construction of Desire." Pp. 45-50. In

Linden et al (eds.), Against Sadomasochism: A Radical Feminist Analysis. Last

Palo Alto, C.A.: Frog in the Well.

Rich, Adrienne

1983 "Compulsory Hetcroscxuality and Lesbian Existence." Pp. 177-205. In

Ann Snilow, Christine Stansell, and Sharon Thompson (eds), Powers ofDesire:

The Politics of Sexuality. New York: Monthly Review Press.

Rose, Nikolas

1989 Governing the Soul: The Shaping ofthe Private Self. London: Routlcdgc.

1994 "Expertise and the Government of Conduct." Pp. 359-397. In Austin Sarat

and Susan Silbey (eds.), Studies in Law, Politics and Society (Vol.14). Green-

wich, Conn.: JAI Press.

86 Volume 16, 2000



Chemins Attentat if

Rubin, Gaylc

1987 "The Leather Menace: Comments on Politics and S/M." Pp. 194-229. In

Samois (eds.), Coming to Power: Writings and Graphics on Lesbian S/M. Bos-

ton: Alyson Publications, Inc.

Russell, Diana E.H.

1982 "Sadomasochism: A Contra-Feminist Activity." Pp. 176-183. In Linden ct
al (eds.), Against Sadomasochism: A Radical Feminist Analysis. East Palo Alto,

C.A.: Frog In The Well.

Saxe, Lorena Leigh

1992 "Sadomasochism and Exclusion." Hypatia. 7(4):59-72.

Simonds, Wendy

1995 "All-Consuming Selves: Self-Help Literature and Women's Identities." In

Debra Grodin and Thomas R. Lindlof (eds.), Constructing the Self in a Medi-

ated World. Thousand Oaks: Sage.

Sims, Karen, Rose Mason and Darlene Pagano

1982 "Racism and Sadomasochism: A Conversation With Two Black Lesbi-

ans." Pp. 99-105. In Linden et al (eds.), Against Sadomasochism: A Radical

Feminist Analysis. San Palo Alto, C.A.: Frog In the Well.

Star, Susan Leigh

1982 "Swastikas: The Street and the University." Pp. 131-136. In Linden et al

(eds.), Against Sadomasochism: A Radical Feminist Analysis. San Palo Alto,

C.A.: Frog in the Well.

Thompson, Mark

1991 "Introduction." Pp. xi-xx. In Mark Thompson (ed.), Leatherfolk: Radical

Sex, People, Politics, and Practice. Boston: Alyson Publications, Inc.

Vesta, Dianna

1991 "Fantasy, Fetish, and the Goddess." Pp. 267-275. In Mark Thompson

(ed.), Leatherfolk: Radical Sex, People, Politics, and Practice. Boston: Alyson

Publications, Inc.

Weeks, Jeffrey

1991 Against Nature: Essays on History, Sexuality and Identity. London: Rivers

Oram Press.

Volume 16, 2000 87



Alternate Routes

Weinberg, Thomas S.

1994 "Research in Sadomasochism: A Review of Sociological and Social Psy-

chological Literature." Annual Review of Sex Research. 5:257-279.

g8
Volume 16, 2000