Forum Not Truth But Tolerance: A (Much Belated) Response to Atif Khalil Sherman A. Jackson I should like to begin this essay with a sincere apology. More than five years have passed since Professor Atif Khalil penned his scholarly critique of some of my suggestive ruminations on intra-Islamic theological ecumen- ism in the introduction to my translation of Abū Ḥāmid al-Ghâzalî’s Fayṣal al-Tafriqa.1 While scholarly convention – not to mention etiquette ‒ would certainly demand a much more timely response than I have been able to manage, I am afraid that I can plead no better than to throw myself on the understanding of those who have insight into and appreciation for the vari- ous ways in which the horrific attacks of September 11, 2001 have skewed the scholarly agenda of many an Islamicist. I sincerely hope that this delay will not be construed as some kind of veiled or surreptitiously snide dis- missal of Professor Khalil’s thoughtful analysis. I also hope that it will not have gone so far as to suggest any inability on my part to respond to what I shall argue amounts to a clever but ultimately wrong-minded critique. According to Professor Khalil, despite the ingenuity with which I approach the issue of Muslim theological diversity, many of my central ________________________________________________________________________ Sherman A. Jackson is the King Faisal Chair of Islamic Thought and Culture, Professor of Religion and Professor of American Studies and Ethnicity at the University of Southern California. Jackson: Not Truth But Tolerance 147 arguments are beset with “‘internal contradictions and incongruencies’ that might otherwise evade the casual reader” (85). At bottom, these can be summarized as: (1) the lack of an objective criterion for distinguishing “le- gitimate [interpretive] traditions from illegitimate ones”; (2) an inescapable relativism, especially given my apparent assertion that the true meaning of historically transcendent scripture remains hopelessly closed to histori- cally embedded, contingent human beings; (3) the notion that we can have ‘aqīdah (sustained belief about God) independent of a systematic rational method to produce and sustain it; (4) the false dichotomy I assert between eisegesis and tafsīr (Qur’ānic exegesis); and (5) my failure to consider what the likes of the famed if controversial Muḥyī al-Dîn ībn ‘Arabī might con- tribute to a project of theological ecumenism. There are a number of other minor issues and extrapolations tucked in the interstices of all of this. But what I have enumerated here constitutes the backbone of Khalil’s critique. I should like to begin my response by noting that, despite my recognition of the utility of al-Ghâzalî’s work for a contemporary program of theological ecumenism, the main point of my introduction was to empower the reader to arrive at a more informed understanding of the translated text. Through- out Professor Khalil’s critique, however, it is not always clear whether his issue is with me or al-Ghâzalî, or both. In the end, it turns out to make little difference. For, as we shall see, Khalil’s critique is ultimately grounded in a fundamental and consistent misunderstanding of both al-Ghâzalî and me. Both al-Ghâzalî and I are clear and explicit about the objective of his (and by extension my) project ‒ to establish a criterion for theologi- cal tolerance. The title of the book is On the Boundaries of Theological Tolerance in Islam. And the opening pages of the introduction explicitly state that al-Ghâzalî’s aim is, “not to establish who among the theologi- cal schools is ‘right,’ but to demonstrate the folly and unfairness of the practice of condemning a doctrine as heresy simply because it goes against one’s own theology.”2 Khalil, on the other hand, seems bent on convert- ing al-Ghâzalî’s (and my) aim into one of pursuing and policing theologi- cal truth ‒ of establishing the means via which correct doctrine might be arrived at and of laying down a criterion on the basis of which true be- liefs might be objectively differentiated from false ones. This is why, for example, he takes me to task for not spelling out an objective criterion for distinguishing “legitimate” from “illegitimate” interpretive backdrops against which scripture might be read. For on this omission, I (and here he explicitly targets me) am ultimately bound to accept as valid “all pos- sible doctrine,” since a boundless array of equally legitimate interpretive The American Journal of Islamic Social Sciences 28:4148 backdrops must yield a boundless array of equally legitimate interpreta- tions. As he put it, “This … opens the door to an acceptance of not only Process Theologian Hanbalites and Aristotelian-Neoplatonic Ash‘arites, but anyone who simply claims to speak on behalf of Islamic revelation, no matter how convoluted their logic might seem” (87). This lack of a criterion for separating true from false backdrops cum-doctrine is a par- ticularly glaring oversight on my part, given that al-Ghâzalî, according to Professor Khalil, “suggests the exact opposite in Fayṣal al-Tafriqa, when he argues for the need of a common and agreed upon methodol- ogy to eliminate flawed interpretations (pp. 93‒96)” (87, emphasis mine). To be sure, both al-Ghâzalî and I have an obvious interest in truth cum- correct theological doctrine.3 But, contrary to Professor Khalil’s reading, Fayṣal al-Tafriqa bayna al-Islam wa al-zandaqa is simply and emphati- cally not about the pursuit of truth, at least not as a primary, first order con- cern; nor is it, precisely for this reason, ultimately about accommodating multiple expressions of truth; nor is it even about distinguishing truth per se from falsehood per se. Rather Fayṣal al-Tafriqa is about sharpening and policing the definition of unbelief and affirming that not all untruth neces- sarily amounts to kufr (formal unbelief)! In this light, Professor Khalil’s focus on what is substantively valid, correct, or legitimate simply misses the point. For the very crux of al-Ghāzalī’s argument is that any number of views that are substantively invalid ‒ indeed, demonstrably false, untrue or incorrect ‒ may be tolerated inasmuch as they do not constitute kufr! Again, al-Ghâzalî’s aim is to distinguish who is a Muslim – theologically speaking – and who is not and to confirm, much to the chagrin of those he characterizes as “extremists,” that one can be a Muslim despite one’s subscription to any number of substantively wrong theological views.4 As for Professor Khalil’s assertion that al-Ghâzalî aspired to lay down a “universal principle” to serve as “a common and agreed upon methodology to eliminate flawed interpretations,” this too reflects a ba- sic misunderstanding of al-Ghâzalî’s project. For in Fayṣal, he is not at all interested in establishing correct or eliminating flawed doctrine per se. Rather, in Fayṣal, his concern lies with the tyranny of the uni- versal and the exclusivist claims of those ‒ for example, ‘Abd al-Qāhir al-Baghdādī ‒ who believe themselves, rightly or wrongly, to be in pos- session of correct theological doctrine and that the resulting “incorrect” doctrines of their theological adversaries necessarily amounts to unbelief. Two examples from Fayṣal itself should help to throw my argument into relief. The first comes with al-Ghâzalî’s treatment of Twelver Shiism.5 Speaking of the Imāmī doctrine of occultation (ghaybah), he states explicitly: Jackson: Not Truth But Tolerance 149 This is a false, clearly absurd and extremely abominable doctrine. But it poses no threat to religion. In fact, the only threat it poses is to the fool who believes in it…. The point here is that not everyone who embraces senseless hallucinations must be branded an Unbeliever, even if his doctrines are clearly absurd.6 Al-Ghâzalî clearly believes the Twelver Shiite doctrine of occultation to be neither valid nor legitimate, certainly not in the sense that Khalil uses these terms. And yet, it is precisely his aim in Fayṣal to refute and interdict such practices as branding Twelver Shiites as unbelievers simply because they hold this substantively incorrect belief. Indeed, Twelver Shiites, de- spite their “wayward doctrine,” fall perfectly within the parameters of Is- lam that al-Ghâzalî articulates and defends in Fayṣal. Again, pace Profes- sor Khalil, al-Ghâzalî’s (and my) aim is simply not to rid the market of all wrong ideas and replace these with substantively correct ones. Rather, the only idea that al-Ghâzalî (or I) wants to rout from the field is the idea that all wrong theological views invariably take one outside the pale of the faith. The second example speaks to Professor Khalil’s understanding of al- Ghâzalî’s “common and agreed upon methodology” as being for the pur- pose of determining which traditions are valid and which are not. Again, Khalil’s point here is that without an objective criterion for determining which traditions can be legitimately relied upon in interpreting scripture and which cannot, we have no way of distinguishing the true from the false among the interpretations generated thereby. On this inability, all inter- pretations must be recognized as correct, since no tradition or interpretive backdrop can rightfully claim a status that it denies to all the rest. Again, however, a careful reading of al-Ghâzalî reveals that his preoccupation is not at all with determining which traditions are legitimate and which are not. Rather, his point of departure is the simple and undeniable fact that Muslim scriptural interpretations are informed by a variety of competing interpretive backdrops. To see him as focusing on (and to see me as having to focus on) which of these is legitimate and which is not is simply to miss his (and my) point.7 For even where a tradition is deemed “illegitimate,” this alone does not doom the status of the views it engenders. Speaking, for example, of the widely diffused tradition of rationalist kalām (speculative theology) as an interpretive backdrop and “methodology,” al-Ghâzalî states: [W]ere we ourselves to put aside all pretensions of deference and decorum, we would declare outright that delving into speculative theology [kalām] is religiously forbidden (ḥarām)… (123). To avoid misunderstanding here, I should note this was a judg- ment made by al-Ghâzalî in passing in Fayṣal, as any fair reading The American Journal of Islamic Social Sciences 28:4150 of the text will plainly bear out.8 Still, he explicitly negates kalām’s status as a, or the, normative backdrop or methodology against or via which to read or vindicate scripture. And yet, al-Ghâzalî clearly does not intend to proscribe all doctrines that recline upon kalām. This is because the legitimacy or validity of the interpretive tradition from which an interpretation draws its substance is for him largely a moot point. The operative issue is, rather, how the interpretation itself relates to his criterion for tolerance ‒ that is, not whether it is substantively right or wrong but whether or not it constitutes kufr. In many ways, and with a number of obvious qualifications, Fayṣal al-Tafriqa might be more profitably understood not as a theological tract but as a political one ‒ far more akin in spirit and intent with, say, John Locke’s A Letter Concerning Toleration than with Augustine’s On Christian Doctrine.9 Its aim is neither to affirm, establish, or police the concrete substance of theological truth but to referee and impose a sem- blance of discipline upon competing pronouncements of theological in- fidelity. Understanding this subtlety is key to understanding the role and function of reason in Fayṣal. And understanding al-Ghâzalî’s deployment of reason in this text is the key to understanding that ‒ pace Professor Khalil, neither al-Ghâzalî nor I are advocates of theological relativism. For al-Ghâzalî, reason is not the primary – and certainly not the exclu- sive ‒ means to religious truth; indeed, for him ‒ pace modern liberalism ‒ reason is emphatically not the only means of knowing. Rather, truth and knowing for al-Ghâzalî are often far more subtle and subjective indulgences. This epistemological insight is clearly reflected in his critique of rationalist kalām, in which he scoffs at the claim that speculative theology (deemed by many at the time to be reason par excellence) is the only way to truth: [A]nyone who believes that the way to faith (îmân) is speculative theology, abstract proofs, and systematic categorization is himself guilty of unsanctioned innovation. For faith in God comes rather of a light which God casts into the hearts of His servants, as a gift and gratuity from Him. Sometimes this comes in the form of a proof that appears to one internally but which one cannot explain to others; sometimes it comes through visions in one’s sleep; sometimes it comes by witnessing the ways of a religious man whose light is transferred to one upon befriending and spending time with him; and sometimes it comes by way of circumstantial considerations…. (121)10 Now, while systematic reason may not be the means via which one arrives at all of one’s religious convictions, reason remains, ceteris pa- Jackson: Not Truth But Tolerance 151 ribus, the most likely if not only ostensibly objective11 medium through which such views can be publicly negotiated cum-validated. The aim of Fayṣal is to enlist reason as a public medium for negotiation by laying down the “rules of engagement.” These rules, however, are neither cali- brated nor bound to preempt the emergence of any and all substantively wrong views. Rather, the whole point of al-Ghâzalî’s Fayṣal, literally, “decisive criterion”; it is to determine how wrong a recognizably wrong view must be if its proponent is to be legitimately branded an infidel. Professor Khalil seems to think that this kind of accommodation amounts to theological relativism. But this, again, bespeaks a serious mis- understanding of al-Ghâzalî’s (and my) project, as well as the very nature and pluralistic sensibilities of Islam as a “religion.” In a word, “tolerated” is simply not the same as “correct,” “endorsed,” or “agreed with.” Nor does the fact that I tolerate a wrong view in others mean that I have no interest – or even a reduced interest ‒ in ensuring that my own views are substan- tively correct.12 Since, however, the true ground of so much theological be- lief is demonstrably subjective and closed to the dictates13 of reason, I must accept the fact that I may not be able to communicate my beliefs faithfully to others or enlist their assent. Again, however, such recognition should not be mistaken for a lack of conviction regarding my own views. Rather, for me, absolute truth exists ‒ and I know what it is! I also know, however, that you “know” too and that I may not be able to convince you of my truth.14 At its essence, al-Ghâzalî’s (and my) project is about allowing each of us to look upon our own truth as absolute without having to look upon what we deem to be the falsehoods of our coreligionists as absolute in the sense of constituting kufr. This is hardly an exercise in theological relativism. For, assuming due-diligence, it neither entails nor necessitates the slightest hes- itation in judging one’s own or others’ views to be absolutely true or false.15 If I had to guess, I would hazard that Professor Khalil’s reading of al- Ghâzalî (and of me) owes much to the intellectual liberalism enshrined by the Western academy, where closed, subjective conduits of knowledge ‒ the heart (qalb), the self/soul (nafs), the primordial disposition (fiṭrah), guid- ance from God (hudā) ‒ have no epistemological value at all. This in turn prompts him to superimpose upon al-Ghâzalî (and me) an Enlightenment understanding of the relationship between knowledge, truth, and reason. What we know, we know only through reason; and our claims to knowledge/ truth can be validated only by rational arguments.16 On this understanding, what al-Ghâzalî must be seeking to negotiate through his patently rational approach in Fayṣal is the substantive content of truth. For not only is truth the business of reason; it is the latter’s inevitable and inextricable result. http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Fitrah The American Journal of Islamic Social Sciences 28:4152 Again, however, a careful reading of al-Ghâzalî reveals that not only is he opposed to this kind of rationalist fundamentalism,17 Fayṣal is dedicated to negotiating not truth but tolerance. The role and function of reason in this text is to promote not the religious truth but the secular peace! Whether or not this or that Muslim group or individual ultimately ends up in possession of the actual religious truth is a matter to be left to God in the life to come.18 In the here and now, the issue is how competing claims to truth and judg- ments of falsehood can be accommodated – not endorsed! – without threat- ening or undermining the integrity of Islam and the Muslim community. This is the actual ideational context and utilitarian intent of Fayṣal. In its light, not only does the bulk of Professor Khalil’s major criticisms be- gin to fade, his more minor criticisms are also revealed to be problematic. Take, for example, the claim that I argue that “revelation qua revelation, insofar as its source is ahistoric, remains forever inaccessible to the histori- cally contingent theologian (of any school) and that the most people can do is engage in limited, fallible attempts to interpret and understand the divine intention behind scripture…” (87). Again, having misdiagnosed the main objective of Fayṣal, Professor Khalil goes on to confuse the ques- tion of what we can know with that of what we can prove. I never said (or implied) that because humans are embedded in history they can never know the intended meaning of scripture. How could I, when Islam’s very creation narrative includes transcendent God teaching contingent Adam the names of all things? And for the post-creation period of secular his- tory, the Qur’ān repeatedly refers to God’s gifting humans – that is, not just prophets – direct knowledge of truth. Pharaoh, for example, and his people, are said to have received God’s signs but to have, “rejected them, out of impudence and arrogance, despite the certainty of their truth that had settled in their souls” (27:14). And if “signs” here is too ambiguous to dispose of the matter, we need only note the case of a segment of the Chil- dren of Israel who are explicitly credited with having an accurate reading of scripture: “They hear the speech of God and then knowingly distort its meaning after they had clearly understood it” (2:75). In none of these cases is there any question but that historically embedded humans can know the intent of scripture. What they cannot do – and this was the point that Pro- fessor Khalil seems to have misconstrued – is impose their historically embedded understandings on others, who do not share their interpretive background, as self-authenticating, unassailable, universally valid truth. Another minor criticism leveled by Professor Khalil is his apparent attribution to me of a rather curious strain of antirationalism, according to which reason is deemed incapable of knowing anything. I never said Jackson: Not Truth But Tolerance 153 or implied this (nor did al-Ghāzalī).19 What I suggested, rather, following the lead of al-Ghâzalî, was that systematic reason has its epistemological limits. Of course, reason can know, certainly from the perspective of the reasoner him- or herself. But we should be clear here that theology reclines not simply upon the natural faculty of reason but upon specific regimes or systems of reason. And while these regimes or systems can produce metacognitive, internally self-authenticating knowledge or truth, what they cannot do is sustain universal claims to this truth and knowledge across boundaries that separate them from other regimes or systems of reasoning.20 Again, Professor Khalil finds this to be highly problematic. For, for him, this denies the possibility of arriving at universal truth that can be indepen- dently validated as such. As he put it, “if no school can claim comprehensive [read, “universal”] doctrinal truth, then are we not forced to accept that all schools can, in the absence of an agreed upon method, claim it at the relative level?” (87). My response to this would be, “No, all schools can claim – and actually believe! ‒ it at the absolute level!” What al-Ghâzalî wants to do is simply keep these mutually competing and contradictory claims to absolute truth and falsehood from leading to a national pastime spent at the gallows. Related to this point is Professor Khalil’s criticism of my claim that one can have ‘aqīdah without relying on theology as a systematic means of arriving at and validating it. Here, however, he appears to stare reality in the face but to misapprehend it by dint of the rationalist fundamental- ism he seems to have embraced. He notes explicitly (though he deems it misleading for me to note it) that the Prophet (ṢAAS) could have “direct access to transcendent truth by virtue of his prophethood,” and that “He had no need for a theological method to understand revelation because he was in a state of constant communion with God” (89).The reality, however, is that the Prophet had no need for theology (or fiqh, for that matter) not because he was in communion with God (after all, Muslims believe that God can inspire (yulhim) or guide (yahdī) any of us). The Prophet had no need for theology because his authority and status as Prophet relieved him of any and all necessity of validating his views to others. In other words, he could claim for his theological views ‒ by sheer, undemocratic, pro- phetic fiat ‒ an authority that no one else could either claim or challenge. At the bottom, however, the real issue here is, again, the difference between “arriving at” and “validating” a belief. As a matter of private, indi- vidual belief, anyone could give assent to his or her understanding of what the Prophet handed down and hold that as their theological belief, with no effort or even ability to validate this. The moment, however, they ventured into the public and claimed (or implied) that this belief was normative for others; they, unlike the Prophet, would have to point to something beyond The American Journal of Islamic Social Sciences 28:4154 that belief itself ‒ for example, rational argument, historical precedent, their recognized status as a person of gnosis, or supersensory knowledge ‒ in order to endow it with enough authority to validate it. Clearly, however, this process of validation would be separate and distinct from the actual instantiation of the belief itself. Professor Khalil’s understanding of the role of reason, however ‒ that is, as the necessary basis of both the instan- tiation and the validation of beliefs ‒ seems to blind him to this distinction. But, unless we are talking about correct doctrine (as determined, that is, by some specific criterion), it seems to me merely to state the obvious to say that one can have all kinds of beliefs about God without systematic ways of arriving at or validating them. Professor Khalil’s obsession, how- ever, with doctrinal correctness ‒ in tandem with the almost mechanically causal relationship he seems to posit between reason and truth ‒ leads him to impose this obsession on al-Ghâzalî (and me). Reason and only rea- son can produce and judge truth. Otherwise, “All we could attain in re- gards to … [our] truths would be a kind of mindless assent to a very small and specific set of assertions about God that are explicitly spelled out in revelation” (89). Now, even if we leave aside the question of what, then, judges reason, and even if we ignore the implications of acknowledging that some things can be known directly by virtue of how explicitly they are laid out in revelation, we are inexorably brought back to the fact that measuring the concrete correctness of competing doctrines is simply not al-Ghâzalî’s program, at least not in Fayṣal. On the contrary, al-Ghâza- lî’s concern lies, again, not with doctrinal correctness but with tolerance. This misapprehension of the distinction between truth or doctrinal cor- rectness and tolerance also informs Professor Khalil’s critique of my refer- ence to process theologian Charles Hartshorne. Khalil suggests that I am disingenuous when I invoke Hartshorne’s logic but do not subscribe to it. Again, however, this is based on a misapprehension of the meta-context of my and al-Ghâzalî’s project and the role that these references to Harts- horne play in it. Professor Khalil starts out by noting correctly that I adduce Hartshorne to back the argument that Traditionalist Hanbalites could make an equal claim to being rational, since, on Hartshorne’s logic, “settling” on the throne, for example, could not be deemed irrational.21 But then he goes on to claim that by using Hartshorne to argue for equal “legitimacy” be- tween Traditionalists and Rationalists, I run into the problem of not having a criterion for distinguishing “legitimate traditions from illegitimate ones” (87). I have already dealt with this above. Here, however, I would simply add that my reference to Hartshorne was not at all an effort to identify an alternative backdrop (or logic) that might lead to correct doctrine; it was Jackson: Not Truth But Tolerance 155 simply to argue for the existence, pace the Muslim Rationalists, of multiple regimes of reason (‘aql), and to point up the fact that if the criterion for acceptance of a doctrine was simply that it be reasonable, Traditionalist doctrine should pass muster. Again, this was an effort to enlist Hartshorne into the cause of al-Ghâzalî’s campaign for tolerance, not, as Professor Khalil seems to see the matter, of co-opting him into the cause of truth. There are two final points that Professor Khalil raises that are actually, in my view, rather marginal to the main argument but still deserve perhaps some comment. The first of these is his critique of the distinction I draw between eisegesis and tafsīr. Here, let me state openly that if I were to rewrite this section ten years later, I would word it more carefully. I would not, however, change the basic substance of what I said. What I said was that as a discipline, tafsīr is supposed to amount to a simple exercise in exegesis ‒ that is, of extracting the meanings of words in simple diction- ary fashion. Khalil challenges this and argues that in point of fact tafsīr routinely if not necessarily entails some level of eisegesis. Now, in the main, I agree with Khalil. But I think he rather exaggerates (and in so do- ing distorts) my point. I was not arguing that tafsīr never entails eisegesis; in fact, the example I gave of Imām Ahmad clearly demonstrated that it does.22 My point was simply that because tafsīr is supposed to be a simple matter of extracting meaning in simple dictionary fashion ‒ that is, with no formal, ideological presuppositions informing this process ‒ every theo- logian would want to pretend that he or she was involved precisely and only in this enterprise when doing theology. But theology, I argued, being grounded as it is in the attempt to make sense of revelation in the context of some formal or quasi-formal regime of reason, cannot dispense with eisegesis, even if it is not always willing to admit this.23 Now, Khalil points to the fact that al-Ṭabarī contradicts the definition of tafsīr I attributed to him (91). In a sense, however, this actually confirms the point that I was trying to make: eisegesis routinely invades the domain of exegesis. But Khalil takes al-Ṭabarī’s contradiction of the definition of tafsīr I adduced and attributed to him to be a contradiction of the definition itself. Yet, when we consult such authoritative classical lexicons as Lisân al-‘Arab, we find precisely the definition of tafsīr I cited: “fsr … and tafsîr is to uncover the meaning of a difficult expression (wa al-tafsîr kashf al-murâd ‘an al-ḷafz al-mushkil).”24 Again, my point was not that tafsīr never en- tailed eisegesis. My point was rather that, properly speaking, it is not sup- posed to ‒ even if, especially in the service of theology, it routinely does. Finally, there is the suggestion that I was remiss in not mentioning the famed Sufi Muḥyī al-Dîn Ibn ‘Arabī in the context of explicating my (and The American Journal of Islamic Social Sciences 28:4156 al-Ghâzalî’s) project. There is much to be said about this, but let me limit myself here to the following. It seems to me that Ibn ‘Arabī in particular would be a problematic figure to integrate into a discussion of al-Ghâzalî’s project, inasmuch as the entirety of Ibn ‘Arabī’s thought, as I understand him, proceeds on the basis of a cosmology fundamentally at odds with that of al- Ghâzalî. For al-Ghâzalî – certainly in the context of the theological universe and interlocutors he assumes in Fayṣal 25 ‒ the Creator-created dichotomy and distinction is both vertical (that is, hierarchical) and absolute. For Ibn ‘Arabī, on the other hand, and his waḥdat al-wujūd (unity of existence), this distinction might be said to be neither vertical nor entirely absolute. As one of my teachers (a master and proponent of Ibn ‘Arabī’s thought) used to explain it, one can say, “God is this chair,” even if one cannot say, “This chair is God.” Now, I am not sure about how all of this might or might not be reconciled with al-Ghâzalî. But I fail to see how caution and prudence in this regard can be turned into a charge of gratuitous, unwarranted omission. There are numerous lesser issues in Professor Khalil’s critique on which one might wish to comment.26 In closing, however, I would like to take the opportunity to address a broader problem informing the study of Islam in the West of which I think Professor Khalil’s analysis might be a reflection. Given the power and prestige of the Western academy – including the rise and incursion into Islamic studies of the social sci- ences, according to whose approach the foundational texts and tradition of Islam are often marginal to a determination of the normative param- eters of the religion ‒ it seems that Muslims who write out of a classical idiom are increasingly less understood on their own terms. Instead, the interpretive prisms of the Western academy and its intellectual liberalism routinely impose meanings and implications that distort if not subvert the integrity of classical and neo-classical Islamic thought. Beyond their sub- stance, moreover, these interpretive interventions routinely go on to im- ply a finality that all but raises them beyond critique. This is not always the case; but it seems to be increasingly so. We see it, for example, in the superimposition of fundamentalist/literalist interpretations onto the Muslim legal tradition by scholars who avoid any serious engagement of Islamic law itself. On this approach, Muslims cannot honestly extract a pluralistic political theory from the Qur’ān, Sunnah or Shari‘ah tradition, because those writing in the powerful Western academy cannot.27 We see it as well in the tendency to graft the legal monism of the Western nation- state onto Islam, in which light Muslims must take it to be their duty to impose a uniform body of rules indiscriminately across all segments of society, because this is what modern Western states purport to do. Shari‘ah Jackson: Not Truth But Tolerance 157 in this context, whether it really is or not, comes to be seen as a mortal threat to all non-Muslims and even Muslims who might dare to dissent.28 And now, with Professor Khalil, one wonders if we are witnessing yet another incursion of Western liberalism in the form of imposing the pursuit, if not imposition, of truth as the only real and legitimate concern of religion, to the exclusion ‒ in our case, of tolerance, but more generally of order, efficiency, and a host of other secular concerns. Viewed through this prism, Islam can only commit to tolerance as an apology, a pale substi- tute for its failure to live up to its normative ideal. This ultimately derives from and perpetuates the myth that only modern, secular orders can ac- commodate falsehood and that tolerance and critique must remain modern, secular monopolies. Islam being neither modern nor secular, we should not even seriously expect it to rise to such a challenge. To be fair, I sin- cerely doubt that this is Professor Khalil’s consciously held position. But if a religiously grounded program as explicit in its commitment to toler- ance as is al-Ghâzalî’s Fayṣal al-Tafriqa bayna al-Islam wa al-zandaqa can be so thoroughly misapprehended and seamlessly appropriated to the lone cause of pursuing and policing truth, one can only wonder how con- scious one’s commitments to liberalism have to be for the storied prisms and historically driven presuppositions of the modern West to inform ‒ and inform thoroughly – one’s scholarly perspectives and interpretive thrusts. Endnotes 1. Atif Khalil, “Is an Intra-Islamic Theological Ecumenism Possible? A Response to Sherman Jackson,” The American Journal of Islamic So- cial Sciences 22:4 (2005): 84‒95. 2. Sherman A. Jackson, On the Boundaries of Theological Tolerance in Islam: Abū Ḥāmid al-Ghāzalīʼs Fayṣal al-Tafriqa bayna al-Islam wa al-zandaqa. (Karachi, India: Oxford University Press, 2002), 5. Empha- sis added here. 3. Nowhere is this perhaps more vividly demonstrated than in his moving autobiographical testimony in al-Munqidh min al-Ḍālal (Deliverance from Error). 4. See, incidentally, Jackson, On the Boundaries of Theological Tolerance in Islam, 54, where none other than the reputedly puritanical Tradition- alist Ibn Taymîya expresses a similar ecumenical attitude: “[A]nyone who considers this carefully will know that many of the people of un- disciplined passions and unsanctioned innovation (bida‘/s. bid‘a) may be ignorant, wrong-minded Believers who have simply veered away from some aspect of what the Prophet brought (mu’min mukhti’ dâll ‘an The American Journal of Islamic Social Sciences 28:4158 ba‘d mâ jâ’a bihi al-rasûl) just as they may be Hypocrites and Crypto- infidels who pretend to be other than what they are.” 5. I must beg the indulgence of contemporary Twelver Shiites here, as my aim is neither to endorse nor advertise al-Ghâzalîʼs invective but simply to highlight his deeper and more important point in the context of the present discussion. 6. Jackson, On the Boundaries of Theological Tolerance in Islam, 119‒29. 7. In a modern context, in other words, Fayṣal would not see it as its task to make a blanket judgment on whether or not modern science is a “le- gitimate” tradition or interpretive backdrop. Nor would its primary in- terest be in pronouncing which of the interpretations spawned by mod- ern science was substantively correct. Rather, Fayṣal’s focus would be on which interpretations generated by modern science is substantively wrong enough to take its proponent outside the fold of Islam. And in this context, any number of wrong scientifically based views might be tolerated even if not endorsed. 8. See Jackson, On the Boundaries of Theological Tolerance in Islam, 123. I do not wish to put too sharp a point on al-Ghâzalî’scritique of kalām. After all, he makes exceptions for those who need it to clear up doubt and for those who wish to learn it either to treat those beset with doubts or to beat back the attempts of adversaries who seek to undermine the doctrinal integrity of the faith. Still, he sees kalām as far from the ideal, normative or necessary backdrop or methodology for a proper let alone exclusively true reading of scripture. 9. Of course, notable differences in the historical, political and institution- al context in which they wrote underwrite obvious differences between the outlook, concerns, and approach of al-Ghāzalī and Locke. 10. Shockingly, Khalil states that the second part of my introduction merely deals with “the historical background of the work,” and that, as such, “This article is only a response to the first introduction” (94n3). Given that any number of issues directly germane to his critique are dealt with in the second part of the Introduction (for example, al-Ghâzalî’s critique of kalām, his view on the role and function of reason and its relation- ship to truth, the fact that theologians routinely disguise their eisegesis, etc.). I will leave it to the reader to determine the cost of this omission on Khalil’s part. 11. By “objective,” I mean simply equally available and accessible to all. 12. Speaking inter-religiously, this insight might go some way in explain- ing, at least in part, why Islam did not produce a Treaty of Westphalia and all that came in its train. Whereas European kings, magistrates and prelates may have been less willing or able to recognize any difference between tolerating and endorsing heresy or infidelity, this distinction Jackson: Not Truth But Tolerance 159 was woven into the very warp and woof of Islam, from the (now much maligned) accommodation of dhimmīs, to al-Ghāzalī’s’s Fayṣal, to the Ottoman Capitulations. 13. Which is not to say that belief is beyond the analytical function of rea- son. Reason, in other words, can look back on belief, but it cannot get fully behind it in order to push it into place. On this point, see, for example, R. M. Unger, Knowledge and Politics (New York: The Free Press, 1975), esp., 29‒62. 14. This is a paraphrase of Stanley Fish, “Postmodern Welfare: The Igno- rance of Our Warrior Intellectuals” Harper’s Magazine, July 2002. 15. As we saw, for example, with his depiction of the Shiite doctrine of oc- cultation. Again, for al-Ghâzalî, this doctrine was not relatively wrong; it was absolutely wrong, as he put it, “ a false, clearly absurd and ex- tremely abominable doctrine.” Yet, it did not constitute kufr and was thus not a justifiable basis for excluding Shiites from the pale of the faith. 16. This is what routinely dogs religious students in the secular Western academy. There they are taught, directly or indirectly, that they can only know what they can prove; and the only acceptable proof of anything is rational proof! Compare, this, however, with the myriad sources of valid knowledge and belief adumbrated by al-Ghâzalî above (and else- where in Fayṣal). Of course, even al-Ghâzalî would agree that reason is the only (or most likely means) of negotiating the validity of one’s beliefs in the public square. But a more honest and sympathetic position for the academy to assume would be to acknowledge more explicitly the difference between what we can know (or justifiably believe) and what we can prove rationally ‒ and that one’s inability to prove the ex- istence of X on rational grounds is not the same as proving that X does not exist. 17. Speaking against the pretensions of such rationalist fundamentalism, al-Ghâzalî insists in another context: “You have erred in stating that rea- son (al-‘aql) is a motivator (dâ‘in). Nay reason is only a guide (hâdin), while impulses and motives (al-bawâ‘ith wa al-dawâ‘î) issue from the self (al-nafs) based on information provided by reason.” Al-Mustasfâ min ‘ilm al-usûl , 2 vols. (Cairo, Egypt: al-Amîrîyah Press, 1322/1904), 1: 61. For a fuller treatment of this point, see my, “The Alchemy of Domination? Some Ash‘arite Responses to Mu‘tazilite Ethics,” Inter- national Journal of Middle East Studies, no. 31 (1999): 185‒201. 18. Indeed, among the oft-repeated themes in the Qur’ān is that reflected in such verses as, “Then you will be returned to the Knower of the seen and the unseen, whereupon He will inform you concerning that about which you differed” (9:94). See also: 3:55, 5:48, 6:164, 16: 92, and pas- sim. The American Journal of Islamic Social Sciences 28:4160 19. Nor did I say, or imply, pace Khalil, that, just because a doctrine is grounded in human thought and is thus not historically transcendent, it can never be true. 20. Again, Khalil thoroughly misses the point when he argues that, “mind- less assent” “may have been the position of a small number of Muslims in history, the ‘we-believe-without-asking-how’ group, but this is not al-Ghâzalî’s position as he articulates it, for example, while defending the theological enterprise in the second section of Qawâ‘id al-‘Aqâ’id (The Principles of the Creed), the second book of his Iḥyâ’ ‘Ulûm al- Dîn” (89). First, the issue is not at all one of assent but of the degree to which such assent can be imposed on others as a normative duty. Second, al-Ghazâlî’s Iḥyâ’ is a very different book from his Fayṣal. Richard M. Frank in Al-Ghazālī and the Ash‘arite School (Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 1994) and others have noted the palpable evolution in al-Ghâzalî’s thought, which should warn us against assum- ing that all of his works are tied together by a common aim. Third, in Fayṣal, al-Ghâzalî directly – at least in part ‒ contradicts this view of Khalil: “[I]t had to occur to them that there were groups of uncivilized Arabs during the time of the Prophet* and the Companions, may God be pleased with them, who were steeped in idol-worship and who de- voted no attention at all to systematic proofs (‘ilm al-daîl) – and even if they had devoted attention to this they would have not understood it – who in the end were adjudged (by the Prophet and the Companions) to be Muslims.” Jackson, On the Boundaries of Theological Tolerance in Islam , 120‒21. See also p. 122 for a similar statement. 21. I never said, incidentally, pace Khalil, that the Hanbalites were “Process Theologians” (87). 22. Jackson, On the Boundaries of Theological Tolerance in Islam, 12‒13. 23. See, for example, the conclusion in the second part of the introduction to On the Boundaries of Theological Tolerance in Islam, 66‒68 for a confirmation of this. 24. Ibn Manẓūr, Lisân al-‘arab, 6 vols. (Cairo, Egypt: Dâr al-Ma‘ârif, n.d.), vol. 5, 3412‒13. 25. And we might recall that the falāsifah (Muslim Neoplatonic philoso- phers) are the only ones he explicitly places outside the boundaries of tolerance that he defines in this text. 26. Most notably perhaps the assertion that: “Some of the dilemmas he [Jackson] encounters in his attempt to formulate a coherent theory of theological diversity seem to lie in his use of diverse and conflicting strains of thought, which range from al-Ghazâlî and African studies to Christian theology and postmodernism. It was perhaps only inevitable that a project that synthesized ideas from such a wide range of disparate sources would encounter its own incoherencies – interestingly, the same Jackson: Not Truth But Tolerance 161 dilemma al-Ghazâlî’s own writings face” (92). Let me just add here that it seems strange then that Khalil would criticize me for not adding yet another “strain of thought” in the person no less of Muḥyī al-Dīn Ibn ‘Arabī! On another note, I would also address, inter alia, Khalil’s tendency toward what appears to be an unstoried, sola scriptura of sorts that all but ignores the spontaneous understandings of the Prophet’s generation and their (real or purported) ideological heirs ‒ leaving rea- son as the sole determinant of the kinds of normative meanings that can be legitimately derived from or read into scripture. 27. In this regard, see, for example, my “Jihad: Between Law, Fact and Ori- entalism,” Mélanges de l’Université Saint-Joseph 62 (2009): 133‒48, where I discuss the views of Patricia Crone on jihad as a legal institu- tion. 28. On this point see my, “The Beginning of History? Between Islamic Law and the Nation-State,” Oxford Handbook of Islam and Politics, ed. J. Esposito and E. Shahin (New York: Oxford University Press, forthcom- ing), where I discuss the views of Abdullahi an-Na‘īm on Islam and the secular state; see also my “Legal Pluralism Between Islam and the Na- tion-State: Between Medieval Romanticism and Modern Pragmatism,” Fordham International Law Journal, vol. 24 (2007), 101‒109.