Causality Then and Now: 
A1 Ghaziili and Quantum Theory 

Karen Harding 

Ate appearances deceiving? Do objects behave the way they do be- 
cause God wills it? Ate objects impetmanent and do they only exist be- 
cause they ate continuously created by God? According to a1 Ghazlli, the 
answers to all of these questions ate yes. Objects that appear to be 
permanent are not. Those relationships commonly tefemed to as causal 
are a result of God’s habits rather than because one event inevitably leads 
to another. God creates everything in the universe continuously; if He 
ceased to create it, it would no longer exist. 

These ideas seem oddly naive and unscientific to people living in the 
twentieth century. They seem at odds with the common conception of the 
physical world. Common sense says that the universe is made of teal 
objects that persist in time. Furthermore, the behavior of these objects is 
reasonable, logical, and predictable. The belief that the univetse is under- 
standable via logic and reason harkens back to Newton’s mechanical view 
of the universe and has provided one of the basic underpinnings of 
science for centuries. Although most people believe that the world is ac- 
cutately described by this sort of mechanical model, the appropriateness 
of such a model has been called into question by recent scientific 
advances, and in particular, by quantum theory. This theory implies that 
the physical world is actually very different from what a mechanical 
model would p d c t .  

Quantum theory seeks to explain the nature of physical entities and 
the way that they interact. It atose in the early part of the twentieth cen- 
tury in response to new scientific data that could not be incorporated suc- 
cessfully into the ptevailing mechanical view of the universe. Due largely 

Karen H d h g  is chair of the Department of Chemistry, Pierce College, Tacoma, Wash- 
ington. The author wishes to thank the National Endowment for the Humanities for partial 
funding of t h i s  research. 



166 The American Journal of Islamic Social Sciences 102 

to the theory's abstract, mathematical nature, there has been great dis- 
agreement over its correct physical interpretation ever since it was first 
proposed. The most widely accepted is the Copenhagen Interpretation. 
Similarities between this interpretation of quantum theory and the thought 
of al GhaiGli will be the focus of this paper. 

Initially, it might appear unlikely that there would be any significant 
similarities between the thought of a1 Ghaziili (eleventh century CE) and 
the ideas of quantum theory in the twentieth century. Although separated 
by culture as well as several centuries, many of the same ideas are incor- 
porated into these two bodies of thought. Important similarities a seen 
in the role of causality in the natural world, the nature of physical objects, 
and the extent to which the behavior of objects is predictable. 

Western thought has long made a distinction between the study of ob- 
jects and the study of God. Science is the study of objects and of natural 
phenomena; the study of God more properly belongs to philosophy or 
theology. There is, however, an increasing awareness that this separation 
raises difficulties of its own. Although many scientists would prefer to re- 
strict their research analysis to the study of the behavior of objects, quan- 
tum theory has caused many of them (as opposed to philosophers of 
science) to address questions about the metaphysics of science. The data 
supporting quantum theory is so strong that the theory cannot be ignored. 
Acceptance of the theory brings with it ideas that force many scientists 
to reexamine the ideas that underlie the scientific enterprise. 

The fact that scientific advances and emerging theories are prompting 
scientists to look at the metaphysics of science makes it less surprising 
to find that both a1 Ghadli and quantum theorists ask many of the same 
questions. This is not meant to imply that the questions asked are iden- 
tical in tone or context, or that there was ever a question of influence in 
any shape or form. What concerned a1 Ghaziili and his contemporaries 
were such questions as: "What is the role of God in everyday events?" 
or "How is it possible for miracles to occur?" Quantum physicists, on the 
other hand, a s k  "Is there a causal link between these two events?" or "To 
what extent is the behavior of physical objects predictable?" Even though 
the wording and the context of these questions are different, the under- 
lying questions are similar. In both cases, the questions revolve around 
the causes behind events in the natural world and the extent to which 
these events are predictable. Both ask whether one event causes another 
or whether events occur due to some other, outside force. 

The object of this paper is to investigate the similarities that one en- 
countets between these two bodies of thought. The extent of the common- 
alities is striking. For example, both deny that the regularities in the be- 
havior of objects should be attributed to the existence of causal laws. 



Harding: Causality Then and Now 167 

Further, they agree that events in the world ate not strictly p d c t a b l e .  
Both accept the idea that unexpected, unpredictable things can and do 
occut. According to a1 GhaEli's explanation, God is omnipotent and in- 
volved in the worfd at every moment and can, therefore, cause anything 
to happen. The Copenhagen Interpretation of quantum thmty says that it 
is impossible to predict the exact behavior of an object based on physical 
laws. As a result, while one might expect a lead ball to fall when it is 
dropped, there is a d e f d t e  possibility that the ball will rise instead. 

The independent existence of teal objects is doubted by both a1 Gha- 
E l i  and the Copenhagen Interpretation. It is useful, therefore, to consider 
what is meant by the term "object." In everyday language, *object" refets 
to something that takes up space and has a set of properties that enables 
one to differentiate it from its sumundings. For example, an object such 
as a lead ball has certain properties that govern its behavior. Furthermore, 
it is assumed that these properties petsist and that the ball continues to 
behave according to the same set of laws over time. A lead ball falls 
when it is dropped because it is the nature of heavy objects to do so. 

In order to more fully discuss the similarities to which I have te- 
fetted, it is necessary for the reader to have some familiarity with al 
Ghadli's ideas as well as with some of the basic ideas of quantum 
theory. Providing this background is the function of the next portion of 
this paper. The final pottion highlights the similarities between a1 Gha- 
Eli's ideas and the Copenhagen Interpretation of quantum theory. 

A1 Ghaziili 

Abii Ham-d al GhazPli (1058-1 11 1 CE) was one of the most influ- 
ential thinkers of medieval Islam. Among his many writings, the primary 
soutce of information on his ideas about the nature of the physical world 
is the Tahdfit a1 Fallisifah (The Incoherence of the Philosophers) (a1 
GhaGli 1958). Of particular importance to this discussion is Problem 17, 
entitled "Refutation of Their Belief in the Impossibility of a Departure 
from the Natural Course of Events." Here, he addresses such questions as: 
What is the tole of God in everyday events?; How is it possible for 
miracles to occur?; and, Do objects have a nature that causes them to be- 
have in certain ways? 

This work was written to refute the claims of such philosophers as 
Ibn Sing (980-1037 CE, aka Avicenna) about how and why ~ t U r a 1  
events occur (ibid.). At the time a1 GhaEli wrote this book, Ibn S-EG 
and others believed that the physical world contained teal objects that 
were independent of one another. One event was thought to cause 
another, and objects were thought to possess an inherent "nature" that 



168 The American Journal of Islamic Social Sciences 102 

governed their behavior. These ideas were disputed by a1 Ghazlli, for he 
thought that such a completely causal world would limit the power of 
God. He was particularly concerned that the continuing interaction of God 
with everyday events be acknowledged. 

God's central role in everyday events is clearly seen in al Ghazlli's 
idea of continuous creation or, in other words, that everything in the uni- 
verse is created every moment. In order for an object to continue to exist, 
God must create it anew each moment. Objects, then, have nothing in 
their own nature that causes them to endure over time (Wolfson 1976). 
What we perceive as the continuing existence of an object is due to the 
fact that God has decided to create that object over and over again. For 
a1 GhazZli, a ball of lead that is seen testing on a table for a period of 
time only appears to persist in that behavior. In fact, it is continuously re- 
c m t e d  every moment by God. 

If the physical universe is created anew each moment, why is there 
any unifotmity to what is seen? Why is it that one particular object ap- 
pears to persist over time? For al Ghaziili, these conditions arise because 
it is God's "custom" to do the same things over and over again. God 
could, for example, choose to have a lead ball exist at one moment and 
not at the next. But it is His custom, once an object has been created, to 
continue to create it over and over again. Thus it is not the independent 
existence of an object that c a w s  it to persist. Rather, an object persists 
because it is God's custom to bring that same object into existence over 
and over again. 

This idea of custom applies to the behavior, as well as to the exis- 
tence, of objects. For example, a lead ball falls when it is released. For 
al Ghaziili, God is responsible for creating this succession of events: 
release of the ball and a subsequently falling ball. In addition, it is His 
custom to create the same sequence of events over and over again. Ac- 
cording to Wolfson (1976), al Ghazili believed that 

ever since the creation of the world, whenever God creates cer- 
tain events in succession to other events, He creates in men the 
knowledge or the impression that, batring miracles, the same 
events will continue to be created by Him in the future in the 
same order of succession. 

Thus it is possible for us to predict the usual behavior of objects be- 
cause God MchooSes'' to do the same things over and over again. This 
should in no way be construed as limiting the choices that God has. He 
notmally follows His custom, but there is nothing that q u i r e s  that He 
do so (Mirza and Siddiqui 1986). Thus it is easy for a1 Ghazili to ex- 



H a r d i i :  Causality Then and Now 169 

plain miracles. Since God brings everything into existence, He can bring 
anything He chooses into existence at any time. He is just as able to 
bring about an unexpected event as He is to bring about an expected one. 
It is al Ghadli's conviction that just as the lead ball will usually fall 
when released, God is perfectly capable of causing it to tise instead if He 
so chooses. God's power is without limit, and human beings should not 
presume to limit their conception of what God is able to do. 

Things to which God's power extends include mysterious and 
wonderful facts. We have not obsetved all those mysteries and 
wonders. How, then, can it be ptoper on our part to deny their 
possibility, or p i t i v e l y  assert their impossibility? (a1 G W l i  
1958) 

An example used by al Ghadli to illustrate the power of God is that 
of placing a piece of cotton in a fire (ibid.). It is God's custom to allow 
the cotton to bum when it comes into contact with fire. But, a1 GhazZli 
argues, this does not mean that the fire causes the cotton to bum: it is 
God who is responsible for making the cotton bum when it is brought 
into the ptesence of fire. God is equally able to cause the cotton to not 
bum when in such a situation. 

We admit the possibility of a contact between the two which will 
not result in burning, as also we admit the possibility of the 
transformation of cotton into ashes without coming into contact 
with fire. (ibid.) 

The fact that God seldom causes this to happen is a result of His 
habit and has nothing to do with the nature of the fire or the nature of the 
cotton or even with the nature of the interaction of fire with cotton. 

It is God who is responsible for the resulting blackness of cotton 
when it comes into contact with fire. The fire is not the agent of the 
blackness. Fire and the burning of cotton arise together but, "observation 
only shows that one is with the other, not that it is by it and has no other 
causes than it" (ibid.). Therefote what we might perceive to be a causal 
connection is really only a comlation-"with does not equal "by." In the 
wotds of al G h a d l i  

. . . the connection between what ate believed to be the cause and 
the effect is not necessary . . . . If one follows the other, it is be- 
cause He has created them in that fashion, not because the con- 
nection in itself is necessary and indissoluble. (ibid.) 



170 The American Journal of Islamic Social Sciences 1 0 2  

Correlations between events can be readily observed, but since it is 
not possible to actually observe causal relationships, a1 Ghaziili argues 
that we a= not justified in supposing that they exist. 

For al G k l i ,  then, the world and all events are created by God 
every moment. God has complete freedom to create whatever He wishes 
at any time. Any uniformity or regularity of objects o r  of behavior is due 
to the fact that it is God’s custom to create the same things over and over 
again. Causality is not a principle that governs the world. 

The Copenhagen Interpretation 
of Quantum Theory 

In the early part of the twentieth century, in response to an increase 
in the number of conflicts between scientific data and the prevailing New- 
tonian view of the physical world, a new theory was developed. This new 
theory, known as quantum theory, describes the structure of the objects 
that make up the material world. In order to appreciate its significance, 
it is important to see how fundamentally different it is from a mechanical- 
Newtonian view. The world described by a mechanical model is com- 
posed of independently existing objects, each of which has a set of 
qualities that make that object what it is, The objects continue to exist 
over time based on their inherent properties. Objects persist until they 
undergo a change in response to the actions of an outside force. For ex- 
ample, a lead ball is an object and it continues to exist until it is 
destroyed by some outside force. It will fall when released because it is 
acted upon by an outside force (gravity). Furthermore, it is inherent in a 
lead ball to behave in this fashion. 

In addition, a mechanical view assumes the existence of natural laws 
that can predict the behavior of objects. If a ball is dropped from a height 
of ten feet, not only is it certain that it will fall, it is also possible to pre- 
dict exactly how fast it will be moving when it hits the ground and 
exactly where it will land. In such a world, there is no room for surprises 
or miracles, for every event has a rational explanation. 

Quantum theory arose as scientific data accumulated that could not 
be explained by this mechanical model (Crease and Mann 1986). An il- 
lustrative case is the behavior of electrons. Present in all physical objects, 
they, along with protons and neutrons, are the three so-called fundamental 
particles that make up all physical objects. When first discovered in 1897, 
electrons were assumed to be very small particles (i.e., objects with a 



Harding: Causality Then and Now 17 1 

definite size and a definable location in space'). Upon further study, how- 
ever, it was noted that although electrons sometimes behaved as if they 
were particles, at other times they behaved as if they were waves. As 
waves do not have a size or a position, a fundamental contradiction arose: 
how was it possible for an electron to be a particle and have a position 
and, at the same time, be a wave and not have a position? 

A further complication became apparent when it was learned that the 
behavior of the electron (i.e., as a particle or as a wave) depended not on 
the electron itself, but on the actions of an observer. It was found that if 
an observer set up an experiment to study the wave properties of an elec- 
tron, it would act like a wave. If, on the other hand, the experiment were 
set up to study particle properties, the electron would behave like a par- 
ticle. Thus, in some sense, an electron's nature is dependent upon the 
actions of the observer. 

Quantum theory was developed to address such problems. It is a 
highly abstract, mathematical theory that completely defines the behavior 
of such entities as electrons2 This theory has been widely accepted by 
scientists, for it is able to produce accurate predictions of b e h a ~ i o r . ~  Ever 
since the development of quantum theory, however, arguments have raged 
over the correct physical interpretation of such an abstract theory. The 
most widely accepted (although by no means the only potential) inter- 
pretation is known as the Copenhagen Interpretation, so named in honor 
of one of its founders and proponents: Niels Bohr, the director of the 
Copenhagen Institute of Theoretical  physic^.^ 

In quantum theory, the electron is formally and completely described 
by a wave function. This mathematical function precisely defines such 
properties of electrons as their energy. It does not, however, define the 
electron's exact location or its precise movements. According to quantum 
theory, it is not possible, even theoretically, to define these attributes. It 
is only possible to define the potential that an electron has of being found 
at a certain location. 

To make matters even more confusing, it appears that the electron 
does not actually exist at any one location until an observer interacts with 

'Size and pasition are attributes that we typically associate with objects. 

21t can also be applied to larger and more familiar objects, such as a lead ball, for this 
object is composed of electrons, protons, and neutrons. 

3As will be described in the following paragraphs, these predictions are quite different 
in scope and meaning from the predictions produced by a mechanical-Newtonian model. 

4Althoufih many descriptions of the Copenhagen Interpretation exist, the reader is re- 
fered to Helsenberg (1958). chapter 3. 



172 The American Journal of Islamic Social Sciences 1 0 2  

it. In other words, an electron is a particle that has a position only when 
an observer determines its position. Without this interaction, the electron 
does not have a position. Instead, it has the "potential" to behave in a 
number of different positions. It does not, however, exist at any one of 
these places until an observer interacts with it to determine its position. 
This is contrary to the behavior expected of particles. Quantum theory, 
when expanded to objects of familiar size, implies that objects have prop- 
erties that are very different from what one might expect. For example, 
it implies that a lead ball, if left on a table when everyone leaves the 
mom, does not exist in the way that one might expect. The lead ball has 
the potential to continue to exist on the table, but it also has the potential 
to exist in a number of other places as well. Further, it does not actually 
exist in any one place unless someone interacts with it (i.e., looks at it to 
see where it is). 

This idea of potentials is crucial to quantum theory. To more fulty 
understand this, it is useful to discuss the structure of an atom. Protons 
and neutrons reside in the nucleus at the center of an atom, while elec- 
trons are found outside this nucleus. Although it is impossible to predict 
exactly where outside the nucleus an electron will be found, it is known 
that the electron has a very high probability of being found close to the 
nucleus. It has a much lower, but still definable, probability of being 
found far from the nucleus. It is not possibte to predict exactly where an 
electron will be found when an observer looks for it, because it has the 
potential to be anywhere in the universe. It is, however, possible to pre- 
dict with a very high degree of accuracy the probability of finding an 
electron at any particular location (Heisenberg 1962). Although an elec- 
tron has no definable location prior to an observer interacting with it, 
there is a high probability that when its location is determined, it will be 
very close to the nucleus. ?here is a much lower probability associated 
with finding the electron far from the nucleus. 

To take a concrete example, consider a brick wall. This wall is a 
solid object made of atoms held together by the interactions of their 
electrons. If, at one instant of time, all of the electrons were exhibiting 
very improbable behavior (i.e., were far away from their nucleus), there 
would be nothing holding the wall together and it would therefore cease 
to exist. In other words, there is a high probability that the electrons will 
be close to the nucleus and that the wall will behave normally. If one 
attempts to walk through this wall, there is a very high probability that 
one will be stopped by the wall. However, there is still a small (but, 
according to quantum theory, real) probability that, when attempting to 



H a d i n g :  Causality Then and Now 173 

walk through a wall, all of the electtons will be behaving in such a way 
that one can walk through the wall unscathed? 

The concept of probability is related to one of the most surprising as- 
pects of quantum theory: the Heisenberg Uncertainty Principle. Suggested 
by Heisenberg in 1927, it states that there is a mathematical limit to what 
can be known about an object, and that cettain attributes of an electron 
are so fundamentally connected to one another that the knowledge of one 
affects knowledge of the other (Davies 1989). Two such attributes are 
position and momentum, the latter of which is based on the ditection of 
motion and the velocity of a particle. According to the Uncertainty Prin- 
ciple, the mote that is known about the momentum of a particle, the less 
it is possible to know about its position. For example, if the speed and 
ditection (momentum) of an electron are precisely known, it is impossible 
to determine where the electron is located (Bohr 1934). If, on the other 
hand, the exact location of an electron is known, nothing whatsoever can 
be learned about its momentum. 

What, then, is the nature of an object in a quantum world? An object, 
as described by quantum theory, does not have an existence independent 
of an observer’s interaction with it. The set of qualities that adhere to an 
object depend on the way that an observer intetacts with that obje& In 
addition, it is not possible to predict exactly what an object will do in any 
given instance, but only to predict the probability of any particular oc- 
currence. Furthermore, since one attribute seems to influence another, 
there is a strict limit to what can be known about an object. This Uncer- 
tainty Principle limits the individual’s ability to understand the world 
tationally. Even though these ideas of quantum theory are not easy to 
accept, scientists have come to believe them because, when quantum 
theory is applied, it gives accutate, testable predictions about the proba- 
bility of any occurrence. 

Similarities 

As can be seen from the foregoing, there ate many similarities be- 
tween the ideas of a1 Ghadli and the Copenhagen Intetptetation of 
quantum theory. For example, consider the nature of objects in the world. 
It was a1 GhazZli’s belief that all things ate created by God and, in order 
for them to endure, it is necessary for God to create them continuously. 

%e mechanical-Newtonian model, in contrast, states very clearly that no matter how 
many times one walks into the wall, one will never walk t h u g h  it unscathed. Quantum 
theory states that although the chances of doing so are exceedmgly mall, they are still 
real and, moreover, can be calculated exactly. 



174 The American Journal of Islamic Social Sciences 10:2 

There are no attributes inherent in the objects themselves, for any quali- 
ties or attributes that might be associated with an object are only the re- 
sult of God's actions. For example, a lead ball does not have an inherent 
property of "heaviness," for "heaviness'' is not a result of the lead in the 
ball. Rather, it is the result of God causing the ball to fall when dropped 
and causing the concept of "heaviness" to arise in the mind of the indi- 
vidual observing the event. The presence of lead in the ball is not what 
causes the ball to fall; it is the action of God that causes the ball to act 
as it does. It is also the action of God that causes the individual to inter- 
pret this behavior as "heaviness." 

Like al Ghadli, the Copenhagen Interpretation questions whether 
objects have any inherent qualities. For example, an electron has neither 
meaningful size nor a position until an observer interacts with it. All it 
has is the abstract mathematical description known as a wave function. 
This defines the properties of an electron once it is interacted with, but 
it also implies that an electron has no inherent properties prior to this in- 
teraction. Since larger objects, such as lead balls, are made up of elec- 
trons (along with protons and neutrons), quantum theory implies that a 
lead ball has no inherent properties that cause it to act as it does. Any 
properties exhibited by a lead ball arise from the interaction of the lead 
ball and the observer and are not properties inherent in the lead ball itself. 

This lack of properties adhering to objects calls into question the very 
existence of objects. It would be al Ghadli's contention that objects have 
no existence independent of God because He is responsible for creating 
each object every moment. Were it not for God, the object would not 
exist at all. Similarly, the Copenhagen Interpretation says that an object 
has no existence independent of an observer. If no observer is present, the 
object has no attributes and cannot be said to exist.6 For al Ghadli, then, 
God is responsible for the existence of objects as well as for all of the 
properties that adhere to them. In quantum theory, it is the observer who 
causes the object to have specific properties. Although al GhazZli sees 
the source of properties as the actions of God and quantum theory sees 
properties arising as a result of an interaction with an observer, the dis- 
agreement over exactly how properties arise is much less profound than 
the basic agreement that the properties are not inherent in the object 
itself. 

Another area of agreement is found in the interpretations of causality 
and the predictability of events. If events in the world are causally con- 
nected, it is possible, if enough is known about initial conditions, to pre- 

T o  sa that an object exists but has no attributes contradicts the common under- 
standing d t h e  term "object" as described in the introduction to this paper. 



Hardihg: Causality Then and Now 175 

dict the exact course of future events. However, both al G M i  and the 
Copenhagen Interpretation deny that events am causally connected to this 
extent. They also deny that events are completely predictable. In the 
words of al G W l i ,  causal relationships are impossible because God 
creates everything at every moment, Everything that happens depends on 
decisions made by God. There may be a correlation between two events, 
such as the presence of fire and the burning of cotton, but that correlation 
does not imply a causal relation. The Copenhagen Interpretation also 
questions the existence of causal links between events, based on the fact 
that objects in the world are made up of entities (i.e., electrons) that do 
not themselves behave according to cause/effect relationships. In the Co- 
penhagen Interpretation, causal relationships are not meaningful at the 
subatomic level because there are no "objects" there in the normal sense 
of the term. Electrons have only the potential to do certain things and do 
not manifest any of these potentials unless interacted with. If objects have 
only potentials and no attributes, it is meaningless to say that the objects 
themselves can interact causally. 

Although al Ghazili and the Copenhagen Interpretation question 
causality, neither denies that regularities exist in nature. These regularities 
are, according to al Ghazili, attributed to God's "custom" (Qur'an 
33:62). It is God's custom to correlate the presence of fire with the burn- 
ing of cotton. But since God is omnipotent, He could, if He chose, pre- 
vent the cotton from burning in the presence of fire. The probability of 
cotton not burning when placed in fire is small, because it is not God's 
custom to not allow it to bum in such a situation. The Copenhagen Inter- 
pretation also acknowledges that regularities are seen in the physical 
world. These regularities are due to the fact that some events have higher 
probabilities of occurring than others. Events are therefore predictable, but 
only in a general way. For example, an electron has a high probability of 
being found in a position close to the nucleus. This high probability is 
similar, in many respects, to al Ghazili's concept of "custom." It is pos- 
sible to predict where the electron will probably be found, but impossible 
to predict exactly where it will be found. Similarly, it is possible to pre- 
dict that cotton will probably turn black when it is placed in fire, but it 
impossible to say that it will always turn black in the presence of fire. 

If these ideas are applied to a large object such as a lead ball, we find 
that the lead ball will tend to fall when it is released. But there is also the 
probability that it will rise. The chances of the latter, as defined by quan- 
tum theory, are very small but are still definably real. It is not possible 
to predict exactly what the lead ball will do in any given instance: it 
might rise or it might fall. It is only possible to say that the probability 
of it falling is much higher than the probability of it rising. 



176 The American Journal of Islamic Social Sciences 102 

If a quantum theorist and al GhazZli were to see a lead ball being re- 
leased and then rising instead of falling, there would be many similarities 
in their explanations. For a1 Ghaziili, it would have risen because God 
chose, in this case, not to follow His custom of making it fall. We seldom 
see this happem, because God normally does follow His custom. There is, 
however, nothing to insist that God must cause the ball to fall, for He has 
complete freedom to do whatever He wishes. A quantum theorist who 
witnessed the same event would painstakingly and exhaustively work to 
eliminate all other potential scientific explanations. Once this arduous task 
was completed and no rational expianation remained, the rising of the 
lead ball would be explained by stating that an event for which the proba- 
bility is exceedingly small (but still real) had been seen. 

Conclusion 

Although separated by culture and by nearly ten centuries, the 
similarities between a1 Ghazdi and the Copenhagen Interpretation are re- 
markable. In both cases, and contrary to common sense, objects are 
viewed as having no inherent properties and no independent existence. In 
order for an object to exist, it must be brought into being either by God 
(a1 Ghazili) or by an observer (the Copenhagen Interpretation). 

In addition, the world is not entirely predictable. For al Ghadli, God 
has the ability to make anything happen whenever He chooses. In general, 
the world functions in a predictable manner, but a miraculous event can 
occur at any moment. All it takes for a miracle to occur is for God to not 
follow His "custom." The quantum world is very similar. Lead balls fall 
when released because the probability of their behaving in that way is 
very high. It is, however, very possible that the lead ball may "miracu- 
lously" rise rather than fall when released. Although the probability of 
such an event is very small, such an event is, nonetheless, still possible. 

Both a1 G k i i l i  in the eleventh century and quantum theory in the 
twentieth century imply that the world is very different from what com- 
mon sense would lead one to believe. The appearance of objects is de- 
ceiving. Objects do not have an independent existence, as one has come 
to expect. Objects B T ~  c w t e d  each moment, either by God or by an act 
of observation. Furthermore, it is not possible, even in principle, to pre- 
dict the exact behavior of objects, but only the probability of occurrences. 
Such a view of the physical world is, then, both new and old. 



H a r d i i :  Causality Then and Now 177 

References 

Bohr, Niels. "The Atomic Theory and the Fundamental Principles Under- 
lying the Description of Natwe." In Atomic meory and the Descrip- 
tion of Nature. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1934. 

Crease, Robert P. and Charles C. Mann. The Second Creation. New 
York: Macmillan Co., 1986. 

Davies, Paul. The New Physics. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University 
Press, 1989. 

A1 Ghazzili, Abii H5mid. The Incoherence of the Philosophers (Tahiifut 
a1 Falkifah), translated by S. A. Kamali. Lahore: Pakistan Philosoph- 
ical Society, 1958. 

Heisenberg, Werner. Physics and Philosophy. New Yo& Harper and 
Row, 1958. 

----_ . On Modern Physics. New York: Collier Books, 1962. 
Mim, Mohammad, and Mohammad I. Siddiqi. Muslim Contributions to 

Wolfson, Harry A. The Philosophy ofthe Kalam. Cambridge, MA: Har- 
Science. Lahore: Kazi Publications, 1986. 

vard University Press, 1976.