@ Appl. Gen. Topol. 22, no. 2 (2021), 461-481doi:10.4995/agt.2021.15610 © AGT, UPV, 2021 Quantale-valued Cauchy tower spaces and completeness Gunther Jäger a and T. M. G. Ahsanullah b a School of Mechanical Engineering, University of Applied Sciences Stralsund, 18435 Stralsund, Germany (gunther.jaeger@hochschule-stralsund.de) b Department of Mathematics, College of Science, King Saud University, Riyadh 11451, Saudi Arabia (tmga1@ksu.edu.sa) Communicated by J. Rodŕıguez-López Abstract Generalizing the concept of a probabilistic Cauchy space, we intro- duce quantale-valued Cauchy tower spaces. These spaces encompass quantale-valued metric spaces, quantale-valued uniform (convergence) tower spaces and quantale-valued convergence tower groups. For spe- cial choices of the quantale, classical and probabilistic metric spaces are covered and probabilistic and approach Cauchy spaces arise. We also study completeness and completion in this setting and establish a connection to the Cauchy completeness of a quantale-valued metric space. 2010 MSC: 54E15; 54A20; 54A40; 54E35; 54E70. Keywords: Cauchy space; quantale-valued metric space; quantale-valued uniform convergence tower space; completeness; completion; Cauchy completeness. 1. Introduction Cauchy spaces, axiomatized in [17], are a natural setting for studying com- pleteness and completion [32]. In the probabilistic case such spaces are intro- duced as certain “towers indexed by [0, 1]” by Richardson and Kent [33] and by Nusser [27]. The connection to probabilistic metric spaces [34], however, was not clarified there. In this paper, we generalize the approaches of [33, 27] Received 13 May 2021 – Accepted 06 August 2021 http://dx.doi.org/10.4995/agt.2021.15610 G. Jäger and T. M. G. Ahsanullah by allowing the index set to be a quantale. In this way, a quantale-valued metric space, in particular a probabilistic metric space, possesses a “natural” Cauchy structure, which then can in turn be used to study completeness and completion. Further examples include quantale-valued uniform convergence tower spaces and quantale-valued uniform spaces as well as quantale-valued convergence groups. We study the basic categorical properties of the category of quantale-valued Cauchy tower spaces and characterize those spaces that are quantale-valued metrical. Finally we discuss completeness and completion and we establish a connection with the Cauchy completeness [6] of a quantale-valued metric space. 2. Preliminaries Let L be a complete lattice with distinct top element ⊤ and bottom element ⊥. In L we can define the well-below relation α ✁ β if for all subsets D ⊆ L such that β ≤ ∨ D there is δ ∈ D such that α ≤ δ. Then α ≤ β whenever α ✁ β and, for a subset B ⊆ L, we have α ✁ ∨ β∈B β iff α ✁ β for some β ∈ B. Sometimes we consider also a weaker relation, the way-below relation, α ≪ β if for all directed subsets D ⊆ L such that β ≤ ∨ D there is δ ∈ D such that α ≤ δ. The properties of this relation are similar to the properties of the well- below relation, replacing arbitrary subsets by directed subsets. But we also have α ∨ β ≪ γ if α, β ≪ γ, [9]. A complete lattice is completely distributive, if and only if we have α = ∨ {β : β ✁ α} for any α ∈ L [31] and it is continuous if and only if we have α = ∨ {β : β ≪ α} for any α ∈ L, [9]. Clearly α ✁ β implies α ≪ β and hence every completely distributive lattice is also continuous. For more results on lattices we refer to [9]. Lemma 2.1. Let L be a continuous lattice. Then (1) ∨ δ≪α(δ ∗ δ) = α ∗ α. (2) If ǫ ≪ α ∗ α, then there is δ ≪ α such that ǫ ≪ δ ∗ δ. Proof. (1) We have ∨ δ≪α(δ ∗ δ) ≤ α ∗ α = ∨ δ≪α δ ∗ ∨ γ≪α γ = ∨ δ,γ≪α δ ∗ γ ≤ ∨ δ∨γ≪α(δ ∨ γ) ∗ (δ ∨ γ) ≤ ∨ η≪α(η ∗ η). (2) follows directly from (1) as the set {δ ∈ L : δ ≪ α} is directed. � The triple L = (L, ≤, ∗), where (L, ≤) is a complete lattice, is called a commutative and integral quantale if (L, ∗) is a commutative semigroup with the top element of L as the unit, and ∗ is distributive over arbitrary joins, i.e. if we have ( ∨ i∈J αi) ∗ β = ∨ i∈J(αi ∗ β) for all αi, β ∈ L, i ∈ J. In a quantale we can define an implication operator, α → β = ∨ {γ ∈ L : α ∗ γ ≤ β}, which can be characterized by γ ≤ α → β ⇐⇒ γ ∗ α ≤ β. A quantale is called divisible [11] if for β ≤ α there exists γ ∈ L such that β = α ∗ γ. In a divisible quantale we have ∨ δ✁α(δ ∗ δ) = α ∗ α, see [30]. Prominent examples of quantales are e.g. the unit interval [0, 1] with a left- continuous t-norm [34] or Lawvere’s quantale, the interval [0, ∞] with the op- posite order and addition α ∗ β = α + β (extended by α + ∞ = ∞ + α = ∞), © AGT, UPV, 2021 Appl. Gen. Topol. 22, no. 2 462 Quantale-valued Cauchy tower spaces and completeness see e.g. [7]. A further noteworthy example is the quantale of distance distri- bution functions. A distance distribution function ϕ : [0, ∞] −→ [0, 1], satisfies ϕ(x) = supy 0 there is n0 ∈ IN such that for all n, m ≥ n0 we have d(xn, xm)(t) > 1 − t. This definition employs the strong uniformity, i.e. the system of entourages generated by the sets U(t) = {(x, y) ∈ X × X : d(x, y)(t) > 1 − t}, t > 0. Equivalently, as is pointed out in [34], we can also use the system of entourages generated by the sets U(t, ǫ) = {(x, y) ∈ X × X : d(x, y)(t) > 1 − ǫ}, t, ǫ > 0. As in [16], using the quantale of distance distribution functions (∆+, ≤, ∗), we can see that the sets Bd(ϕ) = {(x, y) ∈ X × X : d(x, y) ✄ ϕ}, ϕ ✁ ǫ0 generate the same uniformity. From this we can deduce that a sequence (xn) is a strong Cauchy sequence in the probabilistic metric space (X, d) if and only if the generated filter is in Cdǫ0. Note that for a divisible quantale L, a symmetric L-metric space (X, d) and an idempotent element α ∈ L, in Proposition 4.10, (i) and (ii) are equivalent. In particular, for a frame L, we can characterize the L-Cauchy tower of a symmetric L-metric space by (ii) or by the equivalent statement (i) in Proposition 4.9. The following example shows that we cannot omit the idempotency here. Example 4.12. Let X = IR and L = ([0, ∞], ≥, +) be Lawvere’s quantale and d the usual metric on IR. We consider, for α > 0, the sequence xn = α 2 + 1 n if n is even and xn = − α 2 − 1 n if n is odd and denote F the filter generated by this sequence. Then ∨ F ∈F ∧ x,y∈F d(x, y) = inf k∈IN sup m,n≥k ∣ ∣ ∣ ∣ α 2 + 1 n − (− α 2 − 1 m ) ∣ ∣ ∣ ∣ = inf k∈IN ∣ ∣ ∣ ∣ α + 2 k ∣ ∣ ∣ ∣ = α and hence we have F ∈ Cdα. However, as ∨ x∈X ∨ F ∈F ∧ y∈F d(x, y) = inf x∈IR inf k∈IN sup m≥k (d(x, α 2 + 1 m ) ∨ d(x, − α 2 − 1 m )) = inf x∈IR ( ∣ ∣ ∣ x − α 2 ∣ ∣ ∣ ∨ ∣ ∣ ∣ x + α 2 ∣ ∣ ∣ ) = α 2 , we have ∨ x∈X ∨ x∈qd β (F) β = α 2 but F /∈ Cdα/2. Proposition 4.13. Let (X, d) ∈ |L-MET|. Then qC d α (F) ⊆ q d α(F) and if (X, d) is symmetric, we have qdα(F) ⊆ q Cd α∗α(F). Proof. Let first x ∈ qC d α (F). Then F∧ [x] ∈ C d α. Let ǫ✁ α. Then there is F ∈ F such that for all u, v ∈ F ∪ {x} we have d(u, v) ≥ ǫ. We conclude for u = x that d(x, v) ≥ ǫ for all v ∈ F and hence ∨ F ∈F ∧ y∈F d(x, y) ≥ ǫ. The complete distributivity implies x ∈ qdα(F). Let now (X, d) be symmetric and x ∈ qdα(F). Let ǫ ≪ α. Noting that the set D = { ∧ y∈F d(x, y) : F ∈ F} is directed, there is F ∈ F such that for all y ∈ F we have d(x, y) ≥ ǫ. Let u, v ∈ F ∪ {x}. We distinguish four cases. Case 1: u 6= x, v 6= x. Then d(x, u), d(x, v) ≥ ǫ and hence d(u, v) ≥ d(u, x) ∗ d(x, v) ≥ ǫ ∗ ǫ. © AGT, UPV, 2021 Appl. Gen. Topol. 22, no. 2 469 G. Jäger and T. M. G. Ahsanullah Case 2: u = x, v 6= x. Then d(u, v) = d(x, v) ≥ ǫ ≥ ǫ ∗ ǫ. Case 3: u 6= x, v = x. Similar to case 2. Case 4: u = v = x. Then d(u, v) = d(x, x) = ⊤ ≥ ǫ ∗ ǫ. Hence we have ∨ F ∈F ∧ u,v∈F ∪{x} d(u, v) ≥ ǫ∗ǫ and the continuity of L yields F ∧ [x] ∈ Cdα∗α, i.e. x ∈ q Cd α∗α(F). � Again, for idempotent α ∈ L, i.e. if α∗α = α, we have the equality qC d α (F) = qdα(F). In particular in a frame L, this equality is guaranteed for all α ∈ L. Example 4.14. We use Example 4.12 and show that α 4 ∈ qC d α (F). To this end, we consider the sequence (yn) = (x1, α 4 , x2, α 4 , x3, α 4 , ...), the generated filter of which is G = F ∧ [α 4 ]. We then have ∨ G∈G ∧ x,y∈G d(x, y) = inf k∈IN supm,n≥k |yn − ym| = α and hence we have F ∧ [ α 4 ] ∈ Cdα, i.e. α 4 ∈ qC d α (F) = q Cd α/2+α/2 (F). However, we see in a similar way that inf k∈IN supn≥k ∣ ∣ α 4 − xn ∣ ∣ = 3 4 α 6≤ α 2 , so that α 4 /∈ qd α/2 (F). So we have qC d α/2+α/2 (F) 6⊆ qdα(F). 5. Example: L-uniform convergence tower spaces and L-uniform tower spaces Definition 5.1 ([15]). A pair ( X, Λ = (Λα)α∈L ) , is called an L-uniform con- vergence tower space, if Λα ⊆ F(X × X), α ∈ L, satisfy the following: (LUCTS1) [(x, x)] ∈ Λα for all x ∈ X, α ∈ L; (LUCTS2) Φ ∈ Λα whenever Φ ≤ Ψ and Ψ ∈ Λα; (LUCTS3) Φ, Ψ ∈ Λα implies Φ ∧ Ψ ∈ Λα; (LUCTS4) Λβ ⊆ Λα whenever α ≤ β; (LUCTS5) Φ−1 ∈ Λα whenever Φ ∈ Λα; (LUCTS6) Φ ◦ Ψ ∈ Λα∗β whenever Φ ∈ Λα, Ψ ∈ Λβ and Φ ◦ Ψ exists; (LUCTS7) Λ⊥ = F(X × X). A mapping f : ( X, Λ ) −→ ( X′, Λ′ ) is called uniformly continuous if, for all Φ ∈ F(X × X), (f × f)(Φ) ∈ Λ′α, whenever Φ ∈ Λα. The category of L-uniform convergence tower spaces and uniformly continuous mappings is denoted by L-UCTS. If L = ([0, 1], ≤, ∗), then we obtain Nusser’s probabilistic uniform conver- gence spaces [26, 27]. For L = (∆+, ≤, ∗) we obtain the probabilistic uniform convergence spaces in [2]. For (X, Λ) ∈ |L-UCTS|, F ∈ F(X), x ∈ X and α ∈ L we define x ∈ qΛα(F) ⇐⇒ F × [x] ∈ Λα. It is not difficult to show that (X, qΛ = (qΛα)α∈L) ∈ |L-CTS| is an L-limit tower space. For (X, Λ) ∈ |L-UCTS| and α ∈ L, a filter F ∈ F(X) is called an α-Cauchy filter, written as F ∈ CΛα if and only if F × F ∈ Λα. © AGT, UPV, 2021 Appl. Gen. Topol. 22, no. 2 470 Quantale-valued Cauchy tower spaces and completeness Proposition 5.2. Let (X, Λ) ∈ |L-UCTS|. Then (X, CΛ) ∈ |L-ChyTS|. Proof. (LChyTS1) Since for all x ∈ X and α ∈ L, [x] × [x] ∈ Λα, we have [x] ∈ CΛα . (LChyTS2) Let G ≥ F with F ∈ CΛα . Then F×F ∈ Λα and hence, by (LUCTS2), G × G ∈ Λα, i.e. G ∈ C Λ α . (LChyTS3) Let α ≤ β and F ∈ CΛβ . Then F × F ∈ Λβ, then by (LUCTS4), F × F ∈ Λα which in turn yields F ∈ C Λ α . (LChyTS4) Follows at once from the definition. (LChyTS5) Let α, β ∈ L, and let F ∈ CΛα and G ∈ C Λ β such that F ∨ G exists. Then F × F ∈ Λα and G × G ∈ Λβ. Then F × G = (F × G) ◦ (F × G) ∈ Λα∗β. Also, G × F ∈ Λα∗β. Since (F ∧ G) × (F ∧ G) = (F × F) ∧ (F × G) ∧ (G × F) ∧ (G × G) ∈ Λα∗β, this implies F ∧ G ∈ CΛα∗β. � Proposition 5.3. Let (X, Λ) ∈ |L-UCTS|. Then qC Λ α (F) ⊆ q Λ α(F) ⊆ q CΛ α∗α(F). Proof. Let x ∈ qC Λ α (F), then F∧[x] ∈ C Λ α . This implies that (F∧[x])×(F∧[x]) ∈ Λα. As (F ∧ [x]) × (F ∧ [x]) ≤ F × [x], (LUCTS2) implies x ∈ q Λ α(F). If x ∈ qΛα(F), then F × [x] ∈ Λα and with (LUCTS5) then also [x] × F = (F×[x])−1 ∈ Λα. From (LUCTS6) we obtain F×F = (F×[x])◦([x]×F) ∈ Λα∗α. This yields with (LUCTS3) (F ∧ [x]) × (F ∧ [x]) = (F × F) ∧ (F × [x]) ∧ ([x] × F) ∧ ([x] × [x]) ∈ Λα∗α. Thus, F ∧ [x] ∈ C Λ α∗α which means x ∈ q CΛ α∗α(F). � Again, for idempotent α ∈ L, we have equality, qC Λ α (F) = q Λ α(F). In partic- ular this is the case if L is a frame. Definition 5.4 ([15]). Let L = (L, ≤, ∗) be a quantale. A pair ( X, U ) with U = (Uα)α∈L a family of filters on X × X is called an L-uniform tower space if for all α ∈ L the following holds: (LUTS1) Uα ≤ [∆] with [∆] = ∧ x∈X[(x, x)]; (LUTS2) Uα ≤ (Uα) −1; (LUTS3) Uα∗β ≤ Uα ◦ Uβ; (LUTS4) Uα ≤ Uβ whenever α ≤ β; (LUTS5) U⊥ = ∧ F(X × X); (LUTS6) U∨ A ≤ ∨ α∈A Uα whenever ∅ 6= A ⊆ L. A mapping f : ( X, U ) −→ ( X′, U′ ) is called uniformly continuous if U′α ≤ (f × f)(Uα) for all α ∈ L. The category with objects all L-uniform tower spaces and uniformly continuous mappings as morphisms is denoted by L-UTS. If L = ([0, 1], ≤, ∗) with a t-norm ∗, then we obtain Florescu’s probabilistic uniform spaces [8], for L = (∆+, ≤, ∗) we obtain the probabilistic uniform spaces in [2]. For Lawvere’s quantale an L-uniform tower space is an approach uniform space [23]. © AGT, UPV, 2021 Appl. Gen. Topol. 22, no. 2 471 G. Jäger and T. M. G. Ahsanullah For ( X, U = (Uα)α∈L ) ∈ |L − UTS| and α ∈ L, a filter F ∈ F(X) is called an α-Cauchy filter written as F ∈ CUα if and only if F × F ≥ Uα. Lemma 5.5. Let (X, U) ∈ |L-UTS|. Then (X, CU) ∈ |L-ChyTS|. Proof. (LChyTS1) Clearly by (LUTS1), Uα ≤ [x]×[x], implies [x] ∈ C U α , for all x ∈ X and α ∈ L. (LChyTS2) Let F, G ∈ F(X) with F ≤ G, and F ∈ CUα . Then F × F ≥ Uα but then G × G ≥ Uα, which in turn implies G ∈ C U α . (LChyTS3) Let α ≤ β and F ∈ CUβ , implying F × F ≥ Uβ. But then Uβ ≥ Uα by (LUTS4) for α ≤ β. So, F × F ≥ Uα which gives F ∈ C U α . The condition (LChyTS4) is trivially true. Finally, we check the condition (LChyTS5): let F ∈ CUα and G ∈ CUβ such that F ∨ G exists. Then F × F ≥ Uα and G × G ≥ Uβ. Then (F× F)◦ (G × G) ≥ Uα ◦ Uβ which in view of the condition (LUTS3) yields that F×G = (F×F)◦(G×G) ≥ Uα∗β. This means that F×G ≥ Uα∗β. Furthermore, note that we also have: G×F ≥ Uα∗β, F×F ≥ Uα∗β, and G×G ≥ Uα∗β; this is due to the condition (LUTS5) and the fact that α ∗ β ≤ α, β. Hence we arrive at the following: (F ∧ G) × (F ∧ G) = (F × F) ∧ G × G) ∧ (F × G) ∧ (G × F) ≥ Uα∗β, that is, (F ∧ G) × (F ∧ G) ≥ Uα∗β which in turn implies that F ∧ G ∈ C U α∗β. � Given an L-metric space (X, d) we define Λdα ⊆ F(X × X) for α ∈ L, by [15] Φ ∈ Λdα ⇐⇒ ∨ F ∈Φ ∧ (x,y)∈F d(x, y) ≥ α. Theorem 5.6. The L-Cauchy tower space (X, Cd) of an L-metric space (X, d) is the same as the L-Cauchy tower space (X, CΛ d ) induced by the L-uniform convergence tower space (X, Λd) of an L-metric space. That is, Cd = CΛ d . Proof. This follows from ∨ H∈F×F ∧ (x,y)∈H d(x, y) = ∨ F ∈F ∧ x,y∈F d(x, y) for F ∈ F(X), as the sets F × F with F ∈ F are a basis of F × F. � For an L-metric space (X, d) we define Uǫ = {(x, y) ∈ X ×X : d(x, y) ≫ ǫ}. For ǫ ≪ α, these sets form the basis of a filter Udα and we have U d α = ∧ Φ∈Λdα Φ, see [15]. We call (X, Ud) the L-uniform tower space induced by the L-metric space (X, d). Proposition 5.7. Let (X, d) ∈ |L-MET|. Then CU d α = C d α for all α ∈ L. Proof. Let F ∈ CU d α . Then F×F ∈ U d α and for all ǫ ≪ α there is F ∈ F such that F × F ⊆ Uǫ. Hence for all ǫ ≪ α there is F ∈ F such that ∧ x,y∈F d(x, y) ≥ ǫ. This implies ∧ x,y∈F d(x, y) ≥ α from which we conclude F ∈ C d α. Conversely, we note that the set { ∧ x,y∈F d(x, y) : F ∈ F} is directed. If F ∈ Cdα, then ∨ F ∈F ∧ x,y∈F d(x, y) ≥ α. Hence, for ǫ ≪ α there is F ∈ F such that for all x, y ∈ F we have d(x, y) ≫ ǫ. This means F × F ⊆ Uǫ and we have F × F ≥ Udα. � © AGT, UPV, 2021 Appl. Gen. Topol. 22, no. 2 472 Quantale-valued Cauchy tower spaces and completeness 6. Example: L-limit tower groups Let (X, ·) be a group with identity element e ∈ X and let F, G, H ∈ F(X). We define F⊙G as the filter with filter basis {F ·G : F ∈ F, G ∈ G} and F−1 as the filter with filter basis {F −1 : F ∈ F}. Then, for F, G, H ∈ F(X) and x, y ∈ X, the following properties are easily verified: F ⊙ F−1 ≤ [e]; [x] ⊙ [x]−1 = [e]; [x−1] = [x]−1; [x · y] = [x] · [y]; (F ⊙ G) ⊙ H = F ⊙ (G ⊙ H); (F−1)−1 = F; (F ⊙ G)−1 = G−1 ⊙ F−1; [e] ⊙ F = F ⊙ [e] = F; (F ∧ G)−1 = F−1 ∧ G−1 and (F ∧ G) ⊙ H = (F ⊙ H) ∧ (G ⊙ H). Definition 6.1. Let L = (L, ≤, ∗) be a quantale, and (X, ·) be a group with identity e. Then a triple (X, ·, q = (qα)α∈L) is called an L-convergence tower group (respectively, an L-limit tower group) if the following conditions are ful- filled: (LCTG) If (X, q) is an L-convergence tower space (resp. an L-limit tower space) (LCTGM) x ∈ qα(F), y ∈ qβ(G) implies xy ∈ qα∗β (F ⊙ G), for all F, G ∈ F(X), for all α, β ∈ L, and x, y ∈ X; (LCTGI) x ∈ qα(F) implies x −1 ∈ qα(F −1), for all F ∈ F(X), x ∈ X and α ∈ L. The category of all L-convergence tower groups and continuous group homo- morphisms is denoted by L-CTGrp (respectively, the category of all L-limit tower groups and continuous group homomorphisms is denoted by L-LIMGrp.) If L = {0, 1}, then we obtain classical convergence groups [28]. If L = ([0, 1], ≤, ∗) with a continuous t-norm ∗, then we get probabilistic convergence group under a t-norm in the sense of [13]. If L = ([0, ∞], ≥, +), then a left- continuous L-convergence tower group is an approach group [24]. If L = (∆+, ≤ , ∗), we obtain a probabilistic convergence group in the definition of [3]. For (X, ·, q) ∈ |L − LIMTGrp|, a filter F ∈ F(X) is called an α-Cauchy filter, written F ∈ Cqα, if and only if e ∈ qα ( F −1 ⊙ F ) . Proposition 6.2. Let (X, ·, q) ∈ |L-LIMGrp|. Then ( X, Cq ) ∈ |L-ChyTS|. Proof. (LChyTS1) Since e ∈ qα([x] −1 ⊙ [x]) implies [x] ∈ Cqα. (LChyTS2) Let F ≤ G with F ∈ Cqα. This implies e ∈ qα ( F −1 ⊙ F ) . But then e ∈ qα ( G −1 ⊙ G ) which gives G ∈ Cqα. (LChyTS3) Let α, β ∈ L with α ≤ β and F ∈ C q β. Then e ∈ qβ ( F −1 ⊙ F ) implies e ∈ qα ( F −1 ⊙ F ) . Hence F ∈ Cqα. (LChyTS4) Obvious. (LChyTS5) Let F ∈ Cα and G ∈ C q β such that F ∨ G exists. It is not difficult to prove that F ⊙ G−1 ≤ [e]. As e ∈ qα ( F −1 ⊙ F ) and e ∈ qβ ( G −1 ⊙ G ) , we obtain with condition (LCTGM) e = ee ∈ qα∗β ( F −1 ⊙ F ⊙ G−1 ⊙ G ) which implies that e ∈ qα∗β ( F −1 ⊙ G ) . Similarly, we can get e ∈ qα∗β ( G −1 ⊙ F ) . Since (F ∧ G)−1 ⊙ (F ∧ G) = (F−1 ∧ G−1) ⊙ (F ∧ G) = (F−1 ⊙ F) ∧ (F−1 ⊙ G) ∧ (G−1 ⊙ F) ∧ (G−1 ⊙ G), © AGT, UPV, 2021 Appl. Gen. Topol. 22, no. 2 473 G. Jäger and T. M. G. Ahsanullah we conclude from condition (LCTS5) e ∈ qα∗β ( (F ∧ G)−1 ⊙ (F ∧ G) ) . Hence F ∧ G ∈ C q α∗β. � Definition 6.3 ([14]). A triple (X, ·, d) is called an L-metric group if d is invariant, i.e., d(x, y) = d(xz, yz) = d(zx, zy) for all x, y, z ∈ X. A group homomorphism f : (X, ·) −→ (X′, ·′) between the L-metric groups (X, ·, d) and (X′, ·′, d′) is called an L-METGrp-morphism if it is an L-MET-morphism between (X, d) and (X′d′). The category of L-metric groups is denoted by L-METGrp. Lemma 6.4. Let (X, ·, d) be a symmetric L-metric group. Then (X, ·, qd) is an L-convergence tower group. Proof. We need to show the conditions (LCTGM) and (LCTGI). For (LCTGM), let x ∈ qdα(F) and y ∈ q d β(G). For ǫ ✁ α and δ ✁ β, there is F ∈ F and G ∈ G such that for all u ∈ F and for all v ∈ G we have d(x, u) ≥ ǫ and d(y, v) ≥ δ. Then d(e, x−1u) ≥ ǫ and d(yv−1, e) ≥ δ and hence d(yv−1, x−1u) ≥ ǫ ∗ δ. This implies d(xy, uv) ≥ ǫ ∗ δ for all u ∈ F, v ∈ G and hence d(xy, h) ≥ ǫ ∗ δ for all h ∈ F ⊙ G. Therefore ∨ H∈F⊙G ∧ h∈H d(xy, h) ≥ ǫ ∗ δ and from the complete distributivity we obtain xy ∈ qdα∗β(F ⊙ G). (LCTGI) follows with the symmetry from d(x, y) = d(xy−1, e) = d(y−1, x−1). � Proposition 6.5. Let (X, d) ba a symmetric L-metric group. Then Cdα = C qd α for all α ∈ L. Proof. F ∈ Cq d α is equivalent to ∨ F ∈F ∧ x,y∈F d(e, x −1y) ≥ α, which is, by the invariance of the L-metric, equivalent to ∨ F ∈F ∧ x,y∈F d(x, y) ≥ α, i.e. equivalent to F ∈ Cdα. � 7. Completeness and completion Following [33, 27] we call (X, C) ∈ |L-ChyTS| complete if for all α ∈ L, F ∈ Cα implies the existence of x ∈ X such that F ∧ [x] ∈ Cα. With this definition, the “point of convergence” x = x(F, α) not only de- pends on the filter F but may also depend on the “level” α ∈ L. In the left-continuous case, we can omit this extra dependency. Proposition 7.1. Let (X, C) ∈ |L-ChyTS| be left-continuous. Then (X, C) is complete if for all F ∈ F(X) there is x = x(F) such that for all α ∈ L, F ∈ Cα implies F ∧ [x] ∈ Cα. Proof. Let F ∈ F(X) and define A = {α ∈ L : F ∈ Cα} and δ = ∨ A. By left-continuity F ∈ Cδ and hence there is x = x(F, δ) such that F ∧ [x] ∈ Cδ. If F ∈ Cα, then α ≤ δ and hence F ∧ [x] ∈ Cδ ⊆ Cα and we can choose x for each α. � The following examples show that the left-continuity is essential. © AGT, UPV, 2021 Appl. Gen. Topol. 22, no. 2 474 Quantale-valued Cauchy tower spaces and completeness Example 7.2. Let L = {⊥, α, β, ⊤} with α, β incomparable, ∗ = ∧ and let X be an infinite set. There is an ultrafilter U ∈ U(X) with U 6≥ [x] for all x ∈ X. We fix x0, y0 ∈ X with x0 6= y0 and define an L-Cauchy tower as follows. We let C⊥ = F(X), F ∈ Cα iff F ≥ U ∧ [x0] or if F = [x] for some x ∈ X. Similarly, F ∈ Cβ iff F ≥ U∧ [y0] or F = [x] for some x ∈ X, and finally F ∈ C⊤ if F = [x] for some x ∈ X. We only show (LChyTS5) as the other axioms are easy. Let F ∈ Cγ, G ∈ Cδ and F ∨ G exist. We distinguish three cases. Case 1: γ = α, δ = β. Then α ∧ β = ⊥ and hence F ∧ G ∈ Cα∧β. Case 2: F, G ∈ Cα. If F = [x] and G = [y] then x = y because F ∨ G exists and hence F ∧ G = [x] ∈ Cα. If F = [x] and G = U ∧ [x0], then [x] ∨ (U ∧ [x0]) exists. If x 6= x0 we define F = X \ {x}. Then either F ∈ U or its complement F c ∈ U and also F ∈ [x0]. If F ∈ U then F ∈ U ∧ [x0] and hence also F ∈ [x] ∨ (U ∧ [x0]), in contradiction to F c ∈ [x] and F ∩ F c = ∅. If F /∈ U then F c ∈ U and hence U = [x], again a contradiction. We conclude x = x0, i.e. F = [x0] and G = U ∧ [x0] and therefore F ∧ G = G ∈ Cα = Cα∧α. Case 3: F, G ∈ Cβ. This is similar. We note that (X, C) is complete but since we have U ∈ Cα, U ∈ Cβ and U /∈ Cα∨β = C⊤, it is not left-continuous. Clearly, U ∈ Cα and U ∧ [x0] ∈ Cα. Likewise, U ∈ Cβ and U ∧ [y0] ∈ Cβ. As we have seen above U ∧ [x] ∈ Cα implies x = x0 and hence in particular U ∧ [y0] /∈ Cα. This shows that the point of convergence for U is different for α and β. Example 7.3. We consider X = [0, ∞) and Lawvere’s quantale L = ([0, ∞], ≥ , +). Again we choose an ultrafilter U ∈ U(X) with U 6= [x] for all x ∈ [0, ∞). We define C∞ = F(X) and for α < ∞ we define F ∈ Cα if F = [x] for some x ∈ X or if F ≥ U ∧ [x] for some 0 < x < α. Then ([0, ∞), C) is an L-Cauchy tower space. We again only show (LChyTS5). Let F ∈ Cα, G ∈ Cβ and let F∨G exist. The case F = [x] and G = [y] implies x = y and then F∧G = [x] ∈ Cα∧β. If F = [x] and G ≥ U ∧ [y] with 0 < y < β implies again x = y and we obtain F∧G = G ∈ Cβ ⊆ Cα+β. It remains the case G ≥ U∧[x], G ≥ U∧[y]. If x = y, trivially F ∧ G ∈ Cα+β. If x 6= y, then we choose two sets F1, F2 ⊆ [0, 1] with non-empty and finite complement and F1 ∩ F2 = ∅ such that x ∈ F1, y ∈ F2. Then F2 ∈ U ∧ [x], as F2 ∈ [x] and if F2 /∈ U, then the complement F c 2 ∈ U and as F c2 is a finite set, then U = [z] for z ∈ F c 2 . Similarly, F1 ∈ U ∧ [y]. As H = (U ∧ [x]) ∨ (U ∧ [y]) exists, we get the contradiction ∅ = F1 ∩ F2 ∈ H. As U ∈ Cα for all 0 < α but U /∈ C0 we see that ([0, ∞), C) is not left- continuous. Clearly, the space is complete. However, the point of convergence varies with the level α: We have U ∈ Cα for all 0 < α < ∞. We fix α ∈ (0, ∞). Then there is x with 0 < x < α such that U ∧ [x] ∈ Cα. For β with 0 < β < x, however, U ∧ [x] /∈ Cβ, because U ∧ [x] 6≥ U ∧ [y] for x 6= y. Hence we cannot choose for each level the same point of convergence for U. We note that for (X, d) ∈ |L-MET|, the space (X, Cd) is left-continuous. © AGT, UPV, 2021 Appl. Gen. Topol. 22, no. 2 475 G. Jäger and T. M. G. Ahsanullah Proposition 7.4. Let (Xj, Cj) be complete L-Cauchy tower spaces for all j ∈ J. Then the product space ( ∏ j∈J Xj, π-C) is also complete. Proof. Let F ∈ (π-C)α. Then, for all j ∈ J, prj(F) ∈ C j α. By completeness there is, for each j ∈ J, a point xj ∈ Xj such that prj(F) ∧ [xj] ∈ C j α. Hence with x = (xj)j∈J , then for all j ∈ J, prj(F ∧ [x]) = prj(F) ∧ [prj(x)] = prj(F) ∧ [xj] ∈ C j α which implies F ∧ [x] ∈ (π-C)α. � Remark 7.5 (Completeness in L-UTS). We define for an L-uniform convergence tower space (X, U) the underlying L-convergence tower qU by x ∈ qUα (F) ⇐⇒ F×[x] ≥ Uα. Noting that (F∧[x])×(F∧[x]) = (F×F)∧(F×[x])∧(F×[x]) −1 ∧ [(x, x)] and F×F = (F×[x])◦([x]×F) we immediately obtain x ∈ qC U α (F) ⇐⇒ x ∈ qUα∗α(F). For the definition of completeness however, we can use either L-convergence tower, i.e. if we define (X, U) complete if (X, CU) is complete, then this is equivalent to demanding that F × F ≥ Uα implies F × [x] ≥ Uα for some x ∈ X. Remark 7.6 (Completeness in L-UCTS.). Similarly, if we define in L-UCTS that a space (X, Λ) is complete if (X, CΛ) is complete, then this is equivalent to F × F ∈ Λα implies F × [x] ∈ Λα for some x ∈ X. Let (X, C) be a non-complete L-Cauchy tower space. We call a pair ((X′, C′), κ) with a complete L-Cauchy tower space (X′, C′) and an initial and injective mapping κ : (X, C) −→ (X′, C′) such that κ(X) is dense in (X′, C′), a completion of (X, C). Here, a set A ⊆ X is called dense in (X, C) if for all x ∈ X there is F ∈ F(X) such that A ∈ F and F ∧ [x] ∈ C⊤ and a mapping κ : (X, C) −→ (X′, C′) is initial if F ∈ Cα if and only if κ(F) ∈ C ′ α. In the sequel, we describe a completion construction which goes back to [18] and [27]. The proofs in [27] can simply be adapted, replacing the quantale L = ([0, 1], ≤, ∗) with a continuous t-norm ∗ on [0, 1] by an arbitrary quantale. For this reason, they are not presented. We consider a non-complete L-Cauchy tower space (X, C) and define NC = {F ∈ F(X) : F ∈ C⊤, F ∧ [x] /∈ C⊤∀x ∈ X}. Furthermore, we consider the following equivalence relation on C⊤: F ∼ G ⇐⇒ F ∧ G ∈ C⊤ and we denote the equivalence class of F ∈ C⊤ by 〈F〉 = {G ∈ C⊤ : F ∼ G}. We define X∗ = {〈[x]〉 : x ∈ X} ∪ {〈F〉 : F ∈ NC} and denote the inclusion mapping ιX = ι : X −→ X ∗, x 7−→ ι(x) = 〈[x]〉. We note that if (X, C) is a T1-space, then ι is an injection. In fact, if ι(x) = ι(y), then [x] ∧ [y] ∈ C⊤ and by (T1) then x = y. Let Φ ∈ F(X∗) and let α 6= ⊥. We define Φ ∈ C∗α if there is F ∈ Cα such that Φ ≥ ι(F) or if there is F ∈ Cα and there are F1, ..., Fn ∈ NC such that F ∨ Fi exists for all i = 1, ..., n and Φ ≥ ι(F) ∧ ∧n i=1[〈Fi〉]. Furthermore, we put C∗⊥ = F(X). We will consider the completion axiom (LCA): for all F ∈ Cα with F ∧ [x] /∈ Cα for all x ∈ X, there is V ∈ NC such that F ∧ V ∈ Cα. © AGT, UPV, 2021 Appl. Gen. Topol. 22, no. 2 476 Quantale-valued Cauchy tower spaces and completeness Then ((X∗, C∗), ι) is a completion of (X, C) if (LCA) is true. We can say more. Proposition 7.7 ([27, 18]). Let (X, C) ∈ |L-ChyTS|. Then (X, C) has a com- pletion if and only if it satisfies (LCA). For the completion ((X∗, C∗), ι), the following universal property is true. Theorem 7.8 ([27, 18]). Let (X, C), (Y, D) ∈ |L-ChyTS| and let f : X −→ Y be Cauchy-continuous. Then there exists a Cauchy-continuous mapping f∗ : (X∗, C∗) −→ (Y ∗, D∗) such that the following diagram commutes: (X, C) f −→ (Y, D) ιX ↓ ↓ ιY (X∗, C∗) f∗ −→ (Y ∗, D∗) Corollary 7.9 ([27]). Let (X, C), (Y, D) ∈ |L-ChyTS| and let (X, C) satisfy (LCA) and let (Y, D) be a complete T1-space. If f : X −→ Y is Cauchy- continuous then there is a unique Cauchy-continuous extension f∗ : (X∗, C∗) −→ (Y, D) such that f∗ ◦ ι = f. It is at present not clear if for an L-metric space (X, d) the completion (X, (Cd)∗) is again L-metrical, i.e. if there is an L-metric e in X∗ such that (Cd)∗α = C e α for all α ∈ L. We can, however, show the one half of the axiom (LChyM). Proposition 7.10. Let (X, d) ∈ |L-MET|. If Φ ∈ (Cd)∗α then for all ǫ ✁ α there is φǫ ∈ Φ such that for all x ∗, y∗ ∈ φǫ we have [x ∗] ∧ [y∗] ∈ (Cd)∗ǫ. Proof. Let Φ ∈ (Cd)∗α. Then there are F ∈ C d α and F1, ..., Fn ∈ NC such that F ∨ Fk exists for k = 1, ..., n, n ≥ 0, and Φ ≥ ι(F) ∧n k=1[〈Fk〉]. Let ǫ ✁ α. By the axiom (LChyM) there is Fǫ ∈ F such that for all x, y ∈ Fǫ we have [x] ∧ [x] ∈ Cdǫ . We define φǫ = ι(Fǫ) ∪ {〈F1〉, ..., 〈Fn〉} ∈ Φ. Let x ∗, y∗ ∈ φǫ. We distinguish three cases. Case 1: x∗, y∗ ∈ ι(Fǫ). Then x ∗ = ι(x), y∗ = ι(y) for x, y ∈ Fǫ and as [x] ∧ [y] ∈ Cdǫ we conclude [x ∗] ∧ [y∗] = ι([x] ∧ [y]) ∈ (Cd)∗ǫ. Case 2: x∗ = 〈Fk〉, y ∗ = 〈Fl〉. Then trivially [〈Fk〉] ∧ [〈Fl〉] ≥ ι(F) ∧ ∧n k=1[〈Fk〉] and hence [x ∗] ∧ [y∗] ∈ (Cd)∗ǫ . Case 3: x∗ = 〈[x]〉 ∈ ι(Fǫ), y ∗ = 〈Fk〉. We have [Fǫ] = {G ⊆ X : Fǫ ⊆ G} ≤ F and [Fǫ] ≤ [x] as x ∈ Fǫ. As F ∨ Fk exists therefore also F ∨ [Fǫ] exists. Moreover, we have ∨ G∈[Fǫ] ∧ u,v∈G d(u, v) ≥ ∧ u,v∈Fǫ d(u, v) ≥ ǫ as d(u, v) ≥ ǫ is equivalent to [u] ∧ [v] ∈ Cdǫ . This shows [Fǫ] ∈ C d ǫ . We conclude [x∗] ∧ [y∗] = ι([x]) ∧ [〈Fk〉] ≥ ι([Fǫ]) ∧ [〈Fk〉], i.e. [x ∗] ∧ [y∗] ∈ (Cd)∗ǫ. � 8. The L-metric case: Cauchy completeness We follow concepts and notations introduced in [6], see also [10]. Let (X, d) ∈ |L-MET|. A mapping Φ : X −→ L is an order ideal if d(y, x) ∗ Φ(x) ≤ Φ(y) for all x, y ∈ X. It is called an order filter if Φ(x) ∗ d(x, y) ≤ Φ(y) for all x, y ∈ X. © AGT, UPV, 2021 Appl. Gen. Topol. 22, no. 2 477 G. Jäger and T. M. G. Ahsanullah Clearly, d(y, x) ≤ Φ(x) → Φ(y) and using the L-metric dL : L × L −→ L defined by dL(α, β) = α → β for α, β ∈ L, we see that an order ideal is an L-metric morphism from (X, dop) to (L, dL) and similarly, an L-order filter is an L-metric morphism from (X, d) to (L, dL). The following lemmas give important examples. Lemma 8.1 ([6]). Let (X, d) be an L-metric space and a ∈ X. Then ↓ (a) defined by ↓ (a)(x) = d(x, a) is an order ideal and ↑ (a) defined by ↑ (a)(x) = d(a, x) is an order filter. Lemma 8.2. Let (X, d) be an L-metric space and let F be a filter on X. Then Φ : X −→ L, defined by Φ(x) = ∨ F ∈F ∧ y∈F d(x, y) is an order ideal and Ψ : X −→ L defined by Ψ(x) = ∨ F ∈F ∧ y∈F d(y, x) is an order filter. Proof. We only show the first case. We have for x, y ∈ X d(y, x) ∗ Φ(x) = d(y, x) ∗ ∨ F ∈F ∧ z∈F d(x, z) = ∨ F ∈F d(y, x) ∗ ∧ z∈F d(x, z) ≤ ∨ F ∈F ∧ z∈F d(y, x) ∗ d(x, z) ≤ ∨ F ∈F ∧ z∈F d(y, z) = Φ(y). � Definition 8.3 ([6]). Let (X, d) be an L-metric space and let Φ : X −→ L be an order ideal and Ψ : X −→ L be an order filter. The pair (Φ, Ψ) is called a cut on X (1) ⊤ = ∨ x∈X Φ(x) ∗ Ψ(x); (2) Φ(x) ∗ Ψ(y) ≤ d(x, y) for all x, y ∈ X. We note that for a given a ∈ X, the pair (↓ (a), ↑ (a)) is a cut on X. Proposition 8.4. Let (X, d) be an L-metric space and let F ∈ Cd⊤. Then (Φ, Ψ) as defined in Lemma 8.2 is a cut on X. Proof. Let ǫ ≪ ⊤ and choose δ ≪ ⊤ such that ǫ ≪ δ ∗ δ. Then δ ≪ ⊤ = ∨ F ∈F ∧ x,y∈F d(x, y) and hence there is F ∈ F such that for all x, y ∈ F we have d(x, y) ≫ δ and d(y, x) ≫ δ. We conclude for all x ∈ F ǫ ≪ δ ∗ δ ≤ ∧ y∈F d(x, y) ∗ ∧ y∈F d(y, x) ≤ ∨ F ∈F ∧ y∈F d(x, y) ∗ ∨ F ∈F ∧ y∈F d(y, x) = Φ(x) ∗ Ψ(x). Hence ǫ ≪ ∨ x∈X Φ(x) ∗ Ψ(x) and taking the join for all ǫ ≪ ⊤ we obtain ⊤ = ∨ x∈X Φ(x) ∗ Ψ(x). Moreover, we have Φ(x) ∗ Ψ(y) = ∨ F ∈F ∧ z∈F d(x, z) ∗ ∨ G∈F ∧ z∈G d(z, y) ≤ ∨ F,G∈F ∧ z∈F ∩G d(x, z) ∗ d(z, y) ≤ d(x, y). © AGT, UPV, 2021 Appl. Gen. Topol. 22, no. 2 478 Quantale-valued Cauchy tower spaces and completeness Hence (Φ, Ψ) is a cut on X. � We call a symmetric L-metric space (X, d) complete if for F ∈ Cd⊤ there is a ∈ X such that a ∈ qd⊤(F). From Proposition 4.3 we know that q d ⊤(F) = q Cd ⊤ (F) and hence the completeness of (X, d) is the completeness of the Cauchy space (X, Cd⊤). Clearly, the requirement that (X, C d) is complete is stronger. We shall now establish a relation to the concept of Cauchy completeness of an L-metric space as defined by Lawvere [19], see also [6]. Definition 8.5. Let (X, d) be an L-metric space. Then (X, d) is called Cauchy complete if for all cuts (Φ, Ψ) there is a ∈ X that represents the cut (Φ, Ψ) in the sense that Φ =↓ (a) and Ψ =↑ (a). Theorem 8.6. Let (X, d) be a symmetric L-metric space. Then (X, d) is complete if and only if (X, d) is Cauchy complete. Proof. Let (X, d) be Cauchy complete and let F ∈ Cd⊤. We consider the order ideal Φ and the order filter Ψ defined in Lemma 8.2. From Proposition 8.4 we see that (Φ, Ψ) is a cut on X. By assumption, there is a ∈ X such that Φ(x) = d(x, a) for all x ∈ X and Ψ(x) = d(a, x) for all x ∈ X. Then ⊤ = Ψ(a) ≤ ∨ F ∈F ∧ z∈F d(z, a). which means that a ∈ q d ⊤(F) and (X, d) is complete. Conversely, let (X, d) be complete and let (Φ, Ψ) be a cut. For ǫ ≪ ⊤ we define Fǫ = {x ∈ : Φ(x)∗Ψ(x) ≫ ǫ}. From ⊤ = ∨ x∈X Φ(x)∗Ψ(x) we conclude that Fǫ 6= ∅ and hence {Fǫ : ǫ ≪ ⊤} is a basis for a filter F. We show that F ∈ Cd⊤. Let ǫ ≪ ⊤ and choose δ ≪ ⊤ such that ǫ ≪ δ ∗ δ. For all x, y ∈ Fδ we then have δ ∗ δ ≤ Φ(x) ∗ Ψ(x) ∗ Φ(y) ∗ Ψ(y) ≤ Φ(x) ∗ Ψ(y) ≤ d(x, y), and hence ǫ ≪ δ ∗ δ ≤ ∨ F ∈F ∧ x,y∈F d(x, y). Taking the join over all ǫ ≪ ⊤ yields F ∈ Cd⊤. Hence there is a ∈ X such that a ∈ qd⊤(F). We note that this means ⊤ = ∨ ǫ≪⊤ ∧ z∈Fǫ d(z, a) and, Ψ : (X, d) −→ (L, dL) being an L − MET-morphism, this yields ⊤ = ∨ ǫ≪⊤ ∧ z∈Fǫ (Ψ(z) → Ψ(a)) = ∨ ǫ≪α (( ∨ z∈Fǫ Ψ(z)) → Ψ(a)). For δ ≪ ⊤ there is ǫδ ≪ ⊤ such that δ ∗ ∨ z∈Fǫδ Ψ(z) ≤ Ψ(a). © AGT, UPV, 2021 Appl. Gen. Topol. 22, no. 2 479 G. Jäger and T. M. G. Ahsanullah As ǫδ ≤ ǫδ ∨ δ ≪ ⊤ we have Fǫδ∨δ ⊆ Fǫδ and hence δ ∗ ∨ z∈Fǫδ∨δ Ψ(z) ≤ Ψ(a). For z ∈ Fǫδ∨δ we know Ψ(z) ≥ Φ(z)∗Ψ(z) ≥ ǫδ ∨δ ≥ δ and we conclude δ ∗δ ≤ Ψ(a). Taking the join over all δ ≪ ⊤ we obtain ⊤ = Ψ(a). Similarly we can show ⊤ = Φ(a). Φ being an order ideal implies d(x, a) = d(x, a) ∗ Φ(a) ≤ Φ(x) for all x ∈ X and from Φ(x) = Φ(x) ∗ Ψ(a) ≤ d(x, a) we obtain Φ(x) = d(x, a) for all x ∈ X. Hence Φ =↓ (a). Similarly we can show Ψ =↑ (a) and hence a ∈ X represents the cut (Φ, Ψ) and (X, d) is Cauchy complete. � References [1] J. Adámek, H. Herrlich and G. E. Strecker, Abstract and Concrete Categories, Wiley, New York, 1989. [2] T. M. G. Ahsanullah and G. Jäger, Probabilistic uniform convergence spaces redefined, Acta Math. Hungarica 146 (2015), 376–390. [3] T. M. G. Ahsanullah and G. Jäger, Probabilistic uniformization and probabilistic metrization of probabilistic convergence groups, Math. Slovaca 67 (2017), 985–1000. [4] P. Brock and D. C. Kent, Approach spaces, limit tower spaces, and probabilistic con- vergence spaces, Appl. Cat. Structures 5 (1997), 99–110. [5] H. R. Fischer, Limesräume, Math. Ann. 137 (1959), 269–303. [6] R. C. Flagg, Completeness in continuity spaces, in: Category Theory 1991, CMS Conf. Proc. 13 (1992), 183–199. [7] R. C. Flagg, Quantales and continuity spaces, Algebra Univers. 37 (1997), 257–276. [8] L. C. Florescu, Probabilistic convergence structures, Aequationes Math. 38 (1989), 123– 145. [9] G. Gierz, K. H. Hofmann, K. Keimel, J. D. Lawson, M. W. Mislove and D. S. Scott, Continuous lattices and domains, Cambridge University Press, 2003. [10] D. Hofmann and C. D. Reis, Probabilistic metric spaces as enriched categories, Fuzzy Sets and Systems 210 (2013), 1–21. [11] U. Höhle, Commutative, residuated l-monoids, in: Non-classical logics and their appli- cations to fuzzy subsets (U. Höhle, E. P. Klement, eds.), Kluwer, Dordrecht 1995, pp. 53–106. [12] G. Jäger, A convergence theory for probabilistic metric spaces, Quaest. Math. 38 (2015), 587–599. [13] G. Jäger and T. M. G. Ahsanullah, Probabilistic limit groups under a t-norm, Topology Proceedings 44 (2014), 59–74. [14] G. Jäger and T. M. G. Ahsanullah, Characterization of quantale-valued metric spaces and quantale-valued partial metric spaces by convergence, Applied Gen. Topology 19, no. 1 (2018), 129–144. [15] G. Jäger, Quantale-valued uniform convergence towers for quantale-valued metric spaces, Hacettepe J. Math. Stat. 48, no. 5 (2019), 1443–1453. [16] G. Jäger, The Wijsman structure of a quantale-valued metric space, Iranian J. Fuzzy Systems 17, no. 1 (2020), 171–184. [17] H. H. Keller, Die Limes-Uniformisierbarkeit der Limesräume, Math. Ann. 176 (1968), 334–341. [18] D. C. Kent and G. D. Richardson, Completions of probabilistic Cauchy spaces, Math. Japonica 48, no. 3 (1998), 399–407. © AGT, UPV, 2021 Appl. Gen. Topol. 22, no. 2 480 Quantale-valued Cauchy tower spaces and completeness [19] F. W. Lawvere, Metric spaces, generalized logic, and closed categories, Rendiconti del Seminario Matematico e Fisico di Milano 43 (1973), 135–166. Reprinted in: Reprints in Theory and Applications of Categories 1 (2002), 1–37. [20] R. Lowen, Index Analysis, Springer, London, Heidelberg, New York, Dordrecht 2015. [21] R. Lowen and Y. J. Lee, Approach theory in merotopic, Cauchy and convergence spaces. I, Acta Math. Hungarica 83, no. 3 (1999), 189–207. [22] R. Lowen and Y. J. Lee, Approach theory in merotopic, Cauchy and convergence spaces. II, Acta Math. Hungarica 83, no. 3 (1999), 209–229. [23] R. Lowen and B. Windels, On the quantification of uniform properties, Comment. Math. Univ. Carolin. 38, no. 4 (1997), 749–759. [24] R. Lowen and B. Windels, Approach groups, Rocky Mountain J. Math. 30, no. 3 (2000), 1057–1073. [25] J. Minkler, G. Minkler and G. Richardson, Subcategories of filter tower spaces, Appl. Categ. Structures 9 (2001), 369–379. [26] H. Nusser, A generalization of probabilistic uniform spaces, Appl. Categ. Structures 10 (2002), 81–98. [27] H. Nusser, Completion of probabilistic uniform limit spaces, Quaest. Math. 26 (2003), 125–140. [28] G. Preuß , Seminuniform convergence spaces, Math. Japonica 41, no. 3 (1995), 465–491. [29] G. Preuß , Foundations of topology. An approach to convenient topology, Kluwer Aca- demic Publishers, Dordrecht, 2002. [30] Q. Pu and D. Zhang, Preordered sets valued in a GL-monoid, Fuzzy Sets and Systems 187 (2012), 1–32. [31] G. N. Raney, A subdirect-union representation for completely distributive complete lattices, Proc. Amer. Math. Soc. 4 (1953), 518–512. [32] E. E. Reed, Completion of uniform convergence spaces, Math. Ann. 194 (1971), 83–108. [33] G. D. Richardson and D. C. Kent, Probabilistic convergence spaces, J. Austral. Math. Soc. (Series A) 61 (1996), 400–420. [34] B. Schweizer and A. Sklar, Probabilistic Metric Spaces, North Holland, New York, 1983. © AGT, UPV, 2021 Appl. Gen. Topol. 22, no. 2 481