AlasTamarizAGT.dvi @ Applied General Topology c© Universidad Politécnica de Valencia Volume 9, No. 1, 2008 pp. 67-76 The Čech number of Cp(X) when X is an ordinal space Ofelia T. Alas and Ángel Tamariz-Mascarúa ∗ Abstract. The Čech number of a space Z, Č(Z), is the pseudochar- acter of Z in βZ. In this article we obtain, in ZF C and assuming SCH, some upper and lower bounds of the Čech number of spaces Cp(X) of realvalued continuous functions defined on an ordinal space X with the pointwise convergence topology. 2000 AMS Classification: 54C35, 54A25, 54F05 Keywords: Spaces of continuous functions, topology of pointwise conver- gence, Čech number, ordinal space 1. Notations and Basic results In this article, every space X is a Tychonoff space. The symbols ω (or N), R, I, Q and P stand for the set of natural numbers, the real numbers, the closed interval [0, 1], the rational numbers and the irrational numbers, respectively. Given two spaces X and Y , we denote by C(X, Y ) the set of all continuous functions from X to Y , and Cp(X, Y ) stands for C(X, Y ) equipped with the topology of pointwise convergence, that is, the topology in C(X, Y ) of subspace of the Tychonoff product Y X . The space Cp(X, R) is denoted by Cp(X). The restriction of a function f with domain X to A ⊂ X is denoted by f ↾ A. For a space X, βX is its Stone-Čech compactification. Recall that for X ⊂ Y , the pseudocharacter of X in Y is defined as Ψ(X, Y ) = min{|U| : U is a family of open sets in Y and X = ⋂ U}. Definition 1.1. (1) The Čech number of a space Z is Č(Z) = Ψ(Z, βZ). (2) The k-covering number of a space Z is kcov(Z) = min{|K| : K is a compact cover of Z}. ∗Research supported by Fapesp, CONACyT and UNAM. 68 O. T. Alas and Á. Tamariz-Mascarúa We have that (see Section 1 in [8]): Č(Z) = 1 if and only if Z is locally compact; Č(Z) ≤ ω if and only if Z is Čech-complete; Č(Z) = kcov(βZ \ Z); if Y is a closed subset of Z, then kcov(Y ) ≤ kcov(Z) and Č(Y ) ≤ Č(Z); if f : Z → Y is an onto continuous function, then kcov(Y ) ≤ kcov(Z); if f : Z → Y is perfect and onto, then kcov(Y ) = kcov(Z) and Č(Y ) = Č(Z); if bZ is a compactification of Z, then Č(Z) = Ψ(Z, bZ). We know that Č(Cp(X)) ≤ ℵ0 if and only if X is countable and discrete ([7]), and Č(Cp(X, I)) ≤ ℵ0 if and only if X is discrete ([9]). For a space X, ec(X) (the essential cardinality of X) is the smallest car- dinality of a closed and open subspace Y of X such that X \ Y is discrete. Observe that, for such a subspace Y of X, Č(Cp(X, I)) = Č(Cp(Y, I)). In [8] it was pointed out that ec(X) ≤ Č(Cp(X, I)) and Č(Cp(X)) = |X| · Č(Cp(X, I)) always hold. So, if X is discrete, Č(Cp(X)) = |X|, and if |X| = ec(X), Č(Cp(X)) = Č(Cp(X, I)). Consider in the set of functions from ω to ω, ωω, the partial order ≤∗ defined by f ≤∗ g if f (n) ≤ g(n) for all but finitely many n ∈ ω. A collection D of (ωω, ≤∗) is dominating if for every h ∈ ωω there is f ∈ D such that h ≤∗ f . As usual, we denote by d the cardinal number min{|D| : D is a dominating subset of ωω}. It is known that d = kcov(P) (see [3]); so d = Č(Q). Moreover, ω1 ≤ d ≤ c, where c denotes the cardinality of R. We will denote a cardinal number τ with the discrete topology simply as τ ; so, the space τ κ is the Tychonoff product of κ copies of the discrete space τ . The cardinal number τ with the order topology will be symbolized by [0, τ ). In this article we will obtain some upper and lower bounds of Č(Cp(X, I)) when X is an ordinal space; so this article continues the efforts made in [1] and [8] in order to clarify the behavior of the number Č(Cp(X, I)) for several classes of spaces X. For notions and concepts not defined here the reader can consult [2] and [4]. 2. The Čech number of Cp(X) when X is an ordinal space For an ordinal number α, let us denote by [0, α) and [0, α] the set of ordinals < α and the set of ordinals ≤ α, respectively, with its order topology. Observe that for every ordinal number α ≤ ω, [0, α) is a discrete space, so, in this case, Č(Cp([0, α), I)) = 1. If ω < α < ω1, then [0, α) is a countable metrizable space, hence, by Theorem 7.4 in [1], Č(Cp([0, α), I)) = d. We will analyze the number Č(Cp([0, α), I)) for an arbitrary ordinal number α. We are going to use the following symbols: Notations 2.1. For each n < ω, we will denote as En the collection of intervals [0, 1/2n+1), (1/2n+2, 3/2n+2), (1/2n+1, 2/2n+1), (3/2n+2, 5/2n+2), ... ..., ((2n+2 − 2)/2n+2, (2n+2 − 1)/2n+2), ((2n+1 − 1)/2n+1, 1]. Observe that En is an irreducible open cover of [0, 1] and each element in En has diameter = 1/2n+1. For a set S and a point y ∈ S, we will use the symbol [yS]<ω in order to denote the collection of finite subsets of S containing y. The Čech number of Cp(X) when X is an ordinal space 69 Moreover, if γ and α are ordinal numbers with γ ≤ α, [γ, α] is the set of ordinal numbers λ which satisfy γ ≤ λ ≤ α. The expression α0 < α1 < ... < αn < ... ր γ will mean that the sequence (αn)n<ω of ordinal numbers is strictly increasing and converges to γ. Lemma 2.2. Let γ be an ordinal number such that there is ω < α0 < α1 < ... < αn < ... ր γ. Then Č(Cp([0, γ], I) ≤ Č(Cp([0, γ), I) · kcov(|γ| ω). Proof. For m < ω, F ∈ [γ[αm, γ]] <ω = {M ⊂ [αm, γ] : |M| < ℵ0 and γ ∈ M} and n < ω, define B(m, F, n) = ⋃ E∈En B(m, F, E) where B(m, F, E) = ∏ x∈[0,γ] Jx with Jx = E if x ∈ F , and Jx = I otherwise. (So, B(m, F, n) is open in I[0,γ].) Define B(m, n) = ⋂ {B(m, F, n) : F ∈ [γ[αm, γ]] <ω}. Observe that B(m, n) is the intersection of at most |γ| open sets B(m, F, n). Define G(n) = ⋃ m<ω B(m, n), and G = ⋂ n<ω G(n). Claim: G is the set of all functions g : [0, γ] → [0, 1] which are continuous at γ. Proof of the claim: Let g : [0, γ] → [0, 1] be continuous at γ. Given n < ω there is E ∈ En such that g(γ) ∈ E. Since g is continuous at γ, there is β < γ so that g(t) ∈ E if t ∈ [β, γ]. Fix m < ω so that β < αm. For every F ∈ [γ[αm, γ]] <ω we have that g ∈ B(m, F, E) ⊂ B(m, F, n); hence, g ∈ B(m, n) ⊂ G(n). We conclude that g belongs to G. Now, let h ∈ G. We are going to prove that h is continuous at γ. Assume the contrary, that is, there exist ǫ > 0 and a sequence t0 < t1 < ... < tn < ... ր γ such that (1) |f (tj ) − f (γ)| ≥ ǫ, for every j < ω. Fix n < ω such that 1/2n+1 < ǫ. Since h ∈ G, then h ∈ G(n) and there is m ≥ 0 such that h ∈ B(m, n). Choose tnp > αm and take F = {tnp , γ}. Thus h ∈ B(m, F, n), but if E ∈ En and h(γ) ∈ E, then h(tnp ) 6∈ E, which is a contradiction. So, the claim has been proved. Now, we have I[0,γ] \ G = ⋃ n<ω (I[0,γ] \ G(n)), and I[0,γ] \ G(n) = ⋂ m<ω ⋃ F ∈γ[αm,γ]ω (I[0,γ] \ B(m, F, n)). So I[0,γ] \ G(n)) is an F|γ|δ-set. By Corollary 3.4 in [8], kcov(I [0,γ] \ G(n)) ≤ kcov(|γ|ω). Hence, Č(G) = kcov(I[0,γ] \ G) ≤ ℵ0 · kcov(|γ| ω). Thus, it follows that Č(Cp([0, γ], I) ≤ Č(Cp([0, γ), I) · kcov(|γ| ω ). � 70 O. T. Alas and Á. Tamariz-Mascarúa Lemma 2.3. If γ < α, then Č(Cp([0, γ), I)) ≤ Č(Cp([0, α), I)). Proof. First case: γ = β + 1. In this case, [0, γ) = [0, β] and the function φ : [0, α) → [0, β] defined by φ(x) = x if x ≤ β and φ(x) = β if x > β is a quotient. So, φ# : Cp([0, β], I) → Cp([0, α), I) defined by φ #(f ) = f ◦φ, is a homeomorphism between Cp([0, β], I) and a closed subset of Cp([0, α), I) (see [2], pages 13,14). Then, in this case, Č(Cp([0, γ), I)) ≤ Č(Cp([0, α), I)). Now, in order to finish the proof of this Lemma, it is enough to show that for every limit ordinal number α, Č(Cp([0, α), I)) ≤ Č(Cp([0, α], I)). Let κ = cof (α), and α0 < α1 < ... < αλ < ... ր α with λ < κ. For each of these λ, we know, because of the proof of the first case, that κλ = Č(Cp([0, αλ], I)) ≤ Č(Cp([0, α], I)). Let, for each λ < κ, {V λ ξ : ξ < κλ} be a collection of open subsets of I[0,αλ] such that Cp([0, αλ], I) = ⋂ ξ<κλ V λξ . For each λ < κ and each ξ < κλ, we take W λ ξ = V λ ξ × I (αλ,α). Each W λξ is open in I[0,α) and ⋂ λ<κ ⋂ ξ<κλ W λξ = Cp([0, α), I)). Therefore, Č(Cp([0, α), I)) ≤ κ · sup{κλ : λ < κ} ≤ κ · Č(Cp([0, α], I)). But κ ≤ |α| = ec([0, α]) ≤ Č(Cp([0, α], I)). Then, Č(Cp([0, α), I)) ≤ Č(Cp([0, α], I)). � Lemma 2.4. Let α be a limit ordinal number > ω. Then Č(Cp([0, α), I)) = |α| · supγ<αČ(Cp([0, γ), I)). In particular, Č(Cp([0, α), I)) = supγ<αČ(Cp([0, γ), I)) if cof (α) < α. Proof. By Lemma 2.3, supγ<αČ(Cp([0, γ), I)) ≤ Č(Cp([0, α), I)), and, by Corol- lary 4.8 in [8], |α| ≤ Č(Cp([0, α), I)). For each γ < α, we write κγ instead of Č(Cp([0, γ), I)). Let {V γ λ : λ < κγ} be a collection of open sets in Iγ such that Cp([0, γ), I) = ⋂ λ<κγ V γ λ . Now we put W γ λ = V γ λ × I[γ,α)]. We have that W γ λ is open for every γ < α and every λ < γ, and Cp([0, α), I) = ⋂ γ<α ⋂ λ<κγ W γ λ . So, Č(Cp([0, α), I)) = |α| · supγ<αČ(Cp([0, γ), I)). � In order to prove the following result it is enough to mimic the prove of 5.12.(c) in [5]. Lemma 2.5. If α is an ordinal number with cof (α) > ω and f ∈ Cp([0, α), I)), then there is γ0 < α for which f ↾ [γ0, α) is a constant function. Lemma 2.6. If α is an ordinal number with cofinality > ω, then Č(Cp([0, α], I)) = Č(Cp([0, α), I)). Proof. Let κ = Č(Cp([0, α), I)). There are open sets Vλ (λ < κ) in I [0,α) such that Cp([0, α), I) = ⋂ λ<κ Vλ. For each λ < κ, we take Wλ = Vλ × I {α}. Each Wλ is open in I [0,α] and ⋂ λ<κ Wλ = {f : [0, α] → I | f ↾ [0, α) ∈ Cp([0, α), I)}. For each (γ, ξ, E) ∈ α×α×En, we take B(γ, ξ, E) = ∏ λ≤α Jλ where Jλ = E if λ ∈ {ξ + γ, α}, and Jλ = I otherwise. Let B(γ, ξ, n) = ⋃ E∈En B(γ, ξ, E). The Čech number of Cp(X) when X is an ordinal space 71 Finally, we define B(γ) = ⋃ ξ<α B(γ, ξ, n), which is an open subset of I[0,α]. We denote by M the set ⋂ λ<κ Wλ ∩ ⋂ γ<α B(γ). We are going to prove that Cp([0, α], I) = M . Let f ∈ Cp([0, α], I). We know that f ∈ ⋂ λ<κ Wλ, so we only have to prove that f ∈ ⋂ γ<α B(γ). For n < ω, there is E ∈ En such that f (α) ∈ E. Since f ∈ C([0, α], I), there are γ0 < α and r0 ∈ I such that f (λ) = r0 if γ0 ≤ λ < α. Let χ < α such that χ + γ ≥ γ0. Thus, f ∈ B(γ, χ, n) ⊂ B(γ). Therefore, Cp([0, α], I) ⊂ M . Take an element f of M . Since f ∈ ⋂ λ<α Wλ, f is continuous at every γ < α, thus f ↾ [γ0, α) = r0 for a γ0 < α and an r0 ∈ I. For each n < ω, and each γ ≥ γ0, f ∈ B(γ, ξ, n) for some ξ < α. Then, |r0 − f (α)| = |f (γ + ξ) − f (α)| < 1/2 n. But, these relations hold for every n. So, f (α) must be equal to r0, and this means that f is continuous at every point. Therefore, Č(Cp([0, α], I)) ≤ |α| · Č(Cp([0, α), I)). Since Č(Cp([0, α), I)) ≥ ec([0, α)) = |α|, Č(Cp([0, α], I)) ≤ Č(Cp([0, α), I)). Finally, Lemma 2.3 gives us the inequality Č(Cp([0, α), I)) ≤ Č(Cp([0, α], I)). � Theorem 2.7. For every ordinal number α > ω, |α| · d ≤ Č(Cp([0, α), I)) ≤ kcov(|α| ω ). Proof. Because of Theorem 7.4 in [1], Corollary 4.8 in [8] and Lemma 2.3 above, |α| · d ≤ Č(Cp([0, α), I)). Now, if ω < α < ω1, we have that Č(Cp([0, α), I)) ≤ kcov(|α| ω ) because of Corollary 4.2 in [1]. We are going to finish the proof by induction. Assume that the inequality Č(Cp([0, γ), I)) ≤ kcov(|γ| ω ) holds for every ω < γ < α. By Lemma 2.4 and inductive hypothesis, if α is a limit ordinal, then Č(Cp([0, α), I)) ≤ |α| · supγ<αkcov(|γ| ω) ≤ kcov(|α|ω ). If α = γ0+2, then Č(Cp([0, α), I)) = Č(Cp([0, γ0+1), I)) ≤ kcov(|γ0+1| ω) = kcov(|α|ω ). Now assume that α = γ0 + 1, γ0 is a limit and cof (γ0) = ω. We know by Lemma 2.2 that Č(Cp([0, γ0 + 1), I)) ≤ Č(Cp([0, γ0), I) · kcov(|γ0| ω). So, by inductive hypothesis we obtain what is required. The last possible case: α = γ0 + 1, γ0 is limit and cof (γ0) > ω. By Lemma 2.6, we have Č(Cp([0, γ0 + 1), I)) = |α| · Č(Cp([0, γ0), I). By inductive hypothesis, Č(Cp([0, γ0), I) ≤ kcov(|α| ω ). Since |α| ≤ kcov(|α|ω ), we conclude that Č(Cp([0, α), I)) ≤ kcov(|α| ω ). � As a consequence of Proposition 3.6 in [8] (see Proposition 2.11, below) and the previous Theorem, we obtain: Corollary 2.8. For an ordinal number ω < α < ωω, Č(Cp([0, α), I)) = |α| · d. 72 O. T. Alas and Á. Tamariz-Mascarúa In particular, we have: Corollary 2.9. Č(Cp([0, ω1), I)) = Č(Cp([0, ω1], I)) = d. By using similar techniques to those used throughout this section we can also prove the following result. Corollary 2.10. For every ordinal number α > ω and every 1 ≤ n < ω, |α| · d ≤ Č(Cp([0, α) n, I)) ≤ kcov(|α|ω ). For a generalized linearly ordered topological space X, χ(X) ≤ ec(X), so χ(X) ≤ Č(Cp(X, I)), where χ(X) is the character of X. This is not the case for every topological space, even if X is a countable EG-space, as was pointed out by O. Okunev to the authors. Indeed, let X be a countable dense subset of Cp(I). We have that χ(X) = χ(Cp(I)) = c and Č(Cp(X, I)) = d. So, it is consistent with ZF C that there is a countable EG-space X with χ(X) > Č(Cp(X, I)). One is tempted to think that for every linearly ordered space X, the relation Č(Cp(X, I)) ≤ kcov(χ(X) ω) is plausible. But this illusion vanishes quickly; in fact, when d < 2ω and X is the doble arrow, then X has countable character and ec(X) = |X| = 2ω. Hence, Č(Cp(X, I)) ≥ 2 ω > d = kcov(χ(X)ω) (compare with Theorem 2.7, above, and Corollary 7.7 in [1]). In [8] the following was remarked: Proposition 2.11. (1) For every cardinal number ω ≤ τ < ωω, kcov(τ ω ) = τ · d, (2) for every cardinal τ ≥ λ, kcov((τ +)λ) = τ + · kcov(τ λ), and, (3) if cf (τ ) > λ, then kcov(τ λ) = τ · sup{kcov(µλ) : µ < τ}. Lemma 2.12. For every cardinal number κ with cof (κ) = ω, we have that kcov(κω) > κ. Proof. Let {Kλ : λ < κ} be a collection of compact subsets of κ ω. Let α0 < α1 < ... < αn < ... be an strictly increasing sequence of cardinal numbers converging to κ. We are going to prove that ⋃ λ<κ Kλ is a proper subset of κω. Denote by πn : κ ω → κ the n-projection. Since πn is continuous and Kλ is compact, πn(Kλ) is a compact subset of the discrete space κ, so, it is finite. Thus, we have that | ⋃ λ<αn πn(Kλ)| ≤ αn < κ for each n < ω. Hence, for every n < ω, we can take ξn ∈ κ \ ⋃ λ<αn πn(Kλ). Consider the point ξ = (ξn)n<ω of κω. We claim that ξ 6∈ ⋃ λ<κ Kλ. Indeed, assume that ξ ∈ Kλ0 . There is n < ω such that λ0 < αn. So, ξn ∈ ⋃ λ<αn πn(Kλ) which is not possible. � Recall that the Singular Cardinals Hypothesis (SCH) is the assertion: For every singular cardinal number κ, if 2cof (κ) < κ, then κcof (κ) = κ+. A proposition, apparently weaker than SCH, is: “for every cardinal number κ with cof (κ) = ω, if 2ω < κ, then κω = κ+.” But this last assertion is equivalent to SCH as was settled by Silver (see [6], Theorem 23). The Čech number of Cp(X) when X is an ordinal space 73 Proposition 2.13. If we assume SCH and c ≤ (ωω) +, and if τ is an infinite cardinal number, then (∗) kcov(τ ω ) =    τ · d if ω ≤ τ < ωω τ if τ > ωω and cof (τ ) > ω τ + if τ > ω and cof (τ ) = ω Proof. Our proposition is true for every ω ≤ τ < ωω because of (1) in Propo- sition 2.11. Assume now that κ ≥ ωω and that (∗) holds for every τ < κ. We are going to prove the assertion for κ. Case 1: cof (κ) = ω. By Lemma 2.12, kcov(κω) > κ. On the other hand, kcov(κω) ≤ κω. First two subcases: Either c < ωω or κ > ωω. In both subcases, we can apply SCH and conclude that kcov(κω) = κ+. Third subcase: c = (ωω) + and κ = ωω. In this case we have kcov((ωω ) ω) ≤ (ωω) ω ≤ cω = c = (ωω) +. Moreover, by Lemma 2.12, (ωω) + ≤ kcov((ωω ) ω). Therefore, kcov((ωω ) ω) = (ωω) +. Case 2: cof (κ) > ω. By Proposition 2.11 (3), kcov(κω) = κ · sup{kcov(µω) : ω ≤ µ < κ}. By inductive hypothesis we have that for each µ < κ (∗∗) kcov(µω ) =    µ · d if ω ≤ µ < ωω µ if µ > ωω and cof (µ) > ω µ+ if µ > ω and cof (µ) = ω First subcase: κ is a limit cardinal. For every µ < κ, kcov(µω ) < κ (be- cause of (∗∗) and because we assumed that κ > (ωω) + ≥ c ≥ d); and so sup{kcov(µω) : µ < κ} = κ. Thus, kcov(κω ) = κ. Second subcase: Assume now that κ = µ+0 . In this case, by Proposition 2.11, kcov(κω) = κ·kcov(µω0 ). Because of (∗∗) and because µ0 ≥ ωω, kcov(µ0) ω ≤ κ. We conclude that kcov(κω) = κ. � Proposition 2.14. Let κ be a cardinal number with cof (κ) = ω. Then Č(Cp([0, κ], I)) > κ. Proof. Let 0 = α0 < α1 < · · · < αn < . . . be a strictly increasing sequence of cardinal numbers converging to κ. Assume that {Vλ : λ < κ} is a collection of open sets in I[0,κ] which satisfies Cp([0, κ], I) ⊂ ⋂ λ<κ Vλ. We are going to prove that ⋂ λ<κ Vλ contains a function h : [0, κ] → I which is not continuous. In order to construct h, we are going to define, by induction, the following sequences: 74 O. T. Alas and Á. Tamariz-Mascarúa (i) elements t0, . . . , tn, ... which belong to [0, κ] such that (1) 0 = t0 < t1 < · · · < tn < . . . , (2) ti ≥ αi for each 0 ≤ i < ω, (3) each ti is an isolated ordinal, and (4) κ = lim(tn); (ii) subsets G0, ..., Gn, ... ⊂ [0, κ] with |Gi| ≤ αi for every i < ω, and such that each function which equals 0 in Gi and 1 in {t0, ..., ti} belongs to ⋂ λ<αi Vλ for every 0 ≤ i < ω and ( ⋃ n Gn) ∩ {t0, ..., tn, ...} = ∅; (iii) functions f0, f1, ..., fn, ... such that f0 ≡ 0, and fi is the characteristic function defined by {t0, ..., ti−1} for each 0 < i < ω. Let f0 be the constant function equal to 0. Assume that we have already defined t0, ..., ts−1, G0, ..., Gs−1 and f0, ..., fs−1. We now choose an isolated point ts ∈ [αs, κ] \ G0 ∪ ... ∪ Gs−1 (this is possible because |G0 ∪ ... ∪ Gs−1| < κ). Consider the characteristic function defined by {t0, ..., ts−1, ts}, fs. This function is continuous, so it belongs to ⋂ λ<αs Vλ. For each λ < αs, there is a canonical open set Asλ of the form [fs; x s 1, ..., x s ns(λ) ; 1/ms(λ)] = {f ∈ I[0,κ] : |fs(x s i ) − f (x s i )| < 1/m s(λ) ∀ 1 ≤ i ≤ ns(λ)} satisfying fs ∈ A s λ ⊂ Vλ. For each λ < αs we take F s λ = {x s 1, ..., x s ns(λ) }. Put Gs = ⋃ λ<αs F sλ \ {t0, ..., ts}. It happens that {f ∈ I[0,κ] : f (x) = 0 ∀ x ∈ Gs and f (ti) = 1 ∀ 0 ≤ i ≤ s} is a subset of ⋂ λ<αs Vλ. This finishes the inductive construction of the required sequences. Now, consider the function h : [0, κ] → [0, 1] defined by h(x) = 0 if x 6∈ {t0, ..., tn, ...}, and h(tn) = 1 for every n < ω. This function h is not continuous at κ because h(κ) = 0, κ = lim(tn), and h(tn) = 1 for all n < ω. Now, take λ0 ∈ κ. There exists l < ω such that λ0 < αl. Since h is equal to 0 in Gl and 1 in {t0, ..., tl}, then h ∈ ⋂ λ<αl Vλ. Therefore, h ∈ Vλ0 . So, Cp([0, κ], I) is not equal to ⋂ λ<κ Vλ. This means that Č(Cp([0, κ], I)) > κ. � Theorem 2.15. SCH + c ≤ (ωω) + implies: Č(Cp([0, α), I)) =                    1 if α ≤ ω |α| · d if α > ω and ω ≤ |α| < ωω |α| if |α| > ωω and cof (|α|) > ω |α| if cof (|α|) = ω and α is a cardinal number > ωω |α| if |α| = ωω and d < (ωω) + |α|+ if cof (|α|) = ω, |α| > ωω, α is not a cardinal number |α|+ if |α| = ωω and d = (ωω) + Proof. If α ≤ ω, Cp([0, α), I) = I [0,α), so Č(Cp([0, α), I)) = 1. If α > ω and ω ≤ |α| < ωω, we obtain our result because of Theorem 2.7 and Proposition 2.13. If |α| > ωω and cof (|α|) > ω, by Theorem 2.7 and Proposition 2.13, |α| · d = |α| ≤ Č(Cp([0, α), I)) ≤ kcov(|α| ω ) = |α|. The Čech number of Cp(X) when X is an ordinal space 75 If cof (|α|) = ω and α is a cardinal number > ωω, by Lemma 2.4, Č(Cp([0, α), I)) = |α| · supγ<αČ(Cp([0, γ), I)). The number α is a limit ordinal and for every γ < α, Č(Cp([0, γ), I)) ≤ |γ| + · d. Since d ≤ (ωω) + < |α|, then Č(Cp([0, α), I)) = |α|. By Lemma 2.4 and Theorem 2.7, if |α| = ωω, then ωω · d ≤ Č(Cp([0, α), I)) = |α| · supγ<αČ(Cp([0, γ), I)) ≤ |α| · supγ<α(|γ| + · d). Thus, if |α| = ωω and d < (ωω) +, Č(Cp([0, α), I)) = |α|. Assume now that cof (|α|) = ω, |α| > ωω and α is not a cardinal number. There exists a cardinal number κ such that κ = |α| and [0, α) = [0, κ]⊕[κ+1, α). So, Č(Cp([0, α), I)) = Č(Cp([0, κ], I)) · Č(Cp([κ + 1, α), I)) = Č(Cp([0, κ], I)) (see Proposition 1.10 in [8] and Lemma 2.3). By Theorem 2.7 and Proposition 2.14, κ · d ≤ Č(Cp([0, κ], I)) ≤ κ +. Being κ a cardinal number > ωω with cofinality ω, it must be > (ωω) +; so κ > d and, then, κ ≤ Č(Cp([0, κ], I)) ≤ κ +. Now we use Proposition 2.14, and conclude that Č(Cp([0, α), I)) = κ + = |α|+. Finally, assume that |α| = ωω and d = (ωω) +. By Theorems 2.7 and Propo- sition 2.13 we have |α| · d ≤ Č(Cp([0, α), I)) ≤ kcov(|α| ω ) = (ωω ) +. And we conclude: Č(Cp([0, α), I)) = |α| +. � References [1] O. T. Alas and Á. Tamariz-Mascarúa, On the C̆ech number of Cp(X), II Q & A in General Topology 24 (2006), 31–49. [2] A. V. Arkhangel’skii, Topological Function Spaces, Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1992. [3] E. van Douwen, The integers and topology, in Handbook of Set-Theoretic Topology, North-Holland, 1984, Amsterdam–New-York–Oxford, 111–167. [4] R. Engelking, General topology, PWN, Warszawa, 1977. [5] L. Gillman and M. Jerison, Rings of Continuous Functions, Springer-Verlag, New-York- Heidelberg-Berlin, 1976. [6] T. Jech, Set Theory, Academic Press, New-York-San Francisco-London, 1978. [7] D. J. Lutzer and R. A. McCoy, Category in function spaces, I, Pacific J. Math. 90 (1980), 145–168. [8] O. Okunev and A. Tamariz-Mascarúa, On the C̆ech number of Cp(X), Topology Appl. 137 (2004), 237–249. [9] V. V. Tkachuk, Decomposition of Cp(X) into a countable union of subspaces with “good” properties implies “good” properties of Cp(X), Trans. Moscow Math. Soc. 55 (1994), 239–248. 76 O. T. Alas and Á. Tamariz-Mascarúa Received August 2006 Accepted February 2007 Ofelia T. Alas (alas@ime.usp.br) Universidade de São Paulo, Caixa Postal 66281, CEP 05311-970, São Paulo, Brasil. Ángel Tamariz-Mascarúa (atamariz@servidor.unam.mx) Departamento de Matemáticas, Facultad de Ciencias, Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México, Ciudad Universitaria, México D.F. 04510, México.