RodabaughAGT.dvi @ Applied General Topology c© Universidad Politécnica de Valencia Volume 9, No. 1, 2008 pp. 77-108 Functorial comparisons of bitopology with topology and the case for redundancy of bitopology in lattice-valued mathematics S. E. Rodabaugh ∗ Abstract. This paper studies various functors between (lattice- valued) topology and (lattice-valued) bitopology, including the ex- pected “doubling” functor Ed : L-Top → L-BiTop and the “cross” functor E× : L-BiTop → L 2-Top introduced in this paper, both of which are extremely well-behaved strict, concrete, full embeddings. Given the greater simplicity of lattice-valued topology vis-a-vis lattice- valued bitopology and the fact that the class of L2-Top’s is strictly smaller than the class of L-Top’s encompassing fixed-basis topology, the class of E×’s makes the case that lattice-valued bitopology is cat- egorically redundant. As a special application, traditional bitopology as represented by BiTop is (isomorphic in an extremely well-behaved way to) a strict subcategory of 4-Top, where 4 is the four element Boolean algebra; this makes the case that traditional bitopology is a special case of a much simpler fixed-basis topology. 2000 AMS Classification: Primary: 03E72, 54A10, 54A40, 54E55. Secondary: 06F07, 18A22, 18A30, 18A35, 18B30. Keywords: unital-semi-quantale, unital quantale, (fixed-basis) topology, (fixed-basis) bitopology, order-isomorphism, categorical (functorial) embed- ding, redundancy. 1. Introduction and preliminaries 1.1. Motivation. Bitopology has a long and distinguished history spanning five decades and a literature of some 700 papers [29] with traditional bitopology playing a wide range of roles in Baire spaces, homotopy and algebraic topology, generalizations of metric spaces, biframes, programming semantics, etc. ∗Support of Youngstown State University via a sabbatical for the 2005–2006 academic year is gratefully acknowledged. 78 S. E. Rodabaugh First defined and used in [31, 32, 3, 4], a bitopological space was originally defined as a triple ((X, T) , (X, S) , e) with (X, T) , (X, S) topological spaces and e : (X, T) → (X, S) a continuous bijection—cf. [3]. But if we set T ′ = {e→ (U ) : U ∈ T} , then T′ is a topology on X and the continuity of e insures that idX : (X, T ′) → (X, S) is continuous, i.e., that T′ ⊃ S. It is therefore not surprising that almost immediately [4] the original definition was replaced by the simpler, equivalent definition that a bitopological space is a triple (X, T, S) with T, S topologies on X with T ⊃ S, T being called the strong topology and S the weak topology. Even in the broader lattice-valued topology setting, this definition plays a categorical role (Proposition 3.5 below). Since a quasi-pseudo-metric p on a set X determines its conjugate quasi- pseudo-metric q, namely by q (x, y) = p (y, x) , quasi-pseudo-metrics necessarily occur in conjugate pairs which generate pairs of topologies that need not be related. Thus the definition of a traditional bitopological space was generalized in [22] to its modern form to be an ordered triple (X, T, S) with T, S topologies on X (and no relationship assumed between T and S). Further, a bicontinuous mapping f : (X, T1, T2) → (Y, S1, S2) is a mapping f : X → Y satisfying T1 ⊃ (f ←) → (S1) , T2 ⊃ (f ←) → (S2) , i.e., f : (X, T1) → (Y, S1) and f : (X, T2) → (Y, S2) are both continuous. With the composition and identities of Set, one has the category BiTop, which is a topological construct and hence strongly complete and strongly cocomplete along with many other properties. There is a voluminous literature for BiTop concerning separation, com- pactness, connectedness, completion, connections to uniform and quasi-uniform spaces, homotopy groups and algebraic topology, relationships to bilocales [2], a recently emerging role in programming semantics [25], etc. A significant part of the recent literature on bitopology is in lattice-valued mathematics [30, 27, 50, 51]. Letting L be a us-quantale (Subsection 1.2 below) and X a set, the triple (X, τ, σ) is an L-bitopological space if τ, σ are L-topologies on X (Subsection 1.5); and such spaces with L-bicontinuous mappings comprise the category L-BiTop. This category is a topological construct, strongly complete, strongly cocomplete, and so on. The schemum {L-BiTop : L ∈ |USQuant|} essentially includes BiTop via its functorial isomorph 2-BiTop. This paper studies functorial relationships between (lattice-valued) bitopol- ogy and (lattice-valued) topology in Sections 2–3. The expected functor Ed strictly embeds L-Top into L-BiTop, a functor we dub the “doubling” func- tor; and to fully study Ed, it is necessary to construct several functors from L-BiTop to L-Top whose relationships with Ed lead us to conclude that Ed is extremely well-behaved. But on the other hand, for each L ∈ |USQuant| , the direct product L2 ∈ |USQuant| and there is an embedding E× of L- BiTop into L2-Top (3.4.1) which is extremely well-behaved (Subsubsections 3.4.2, 3.4.3) if L is a u-quantale (Subsection 1.2) and a strict embedding if L Bitopology as topology 79 is consistent (Subsubsection 3.4.1). Given that this embedding is strict (for consistent L) and that the L2’s form a proper subclass of USQuant—which means (lattice-valued) bitopology is properly “contained” in the proper sub- class { L2-BiTop : L ∈ |USQuant| } of {L-Top : L ∈ |USQuant|} , it follows (lattice-valued) topology (twice) strictly generalizes bitopology. In Section 4 we summarize some metamathematical facts: given that lattice-valued topol- ogy is fundamentally simpler than lattice-valued bitopology—a membership lattice and one topology vis-a-vis a membership lattice and two topologies, it follows that topology and the class of embeddings E×’s make lattice-valued bitopology categorically redundant; and as a special application, traditional bitopology BiTop strictly embeds in an extremely well behaved way into 4- Top, the latter being lattice-valued topology based on the four-element Boolean algebra 4, so that traditional bitopology both is a strictly special case of the simpler lattice-valued topology and demonstrates the necessity of lattice-valued topology. On the other hand, this last fact points the way for bringing over into lattice-valued topology successful ideas from the extensive literature of traditional bitopology; in particular, traditional bicompactness mandates, via the embedding of BiTop into 4-Top, the compactness of [5] for lattice-valued topology (Corollary 4.7). 1.2. Lattice theoretics. A semi-quantale (L,≤,⊗) (s-quantale) is a com- plete lattice (L,≤) equipped with a binary operation ⊗ : L × L → L, with no additional assumptions, called a tensor product; an ordered semi-quantale (os-quantale) is an s-quantale in which ⊗ is isotone in both variables; a com- plete quasi-monoidal lattice (cqml) [20, 41] is an os-quantale for which ⊤ is an idempotent element for ⊗; a unital semi-quantale (us-quantale) is an s-quantale in which ⊗ has an identity element e ∈ L called the unit [33]—units are unique; a quantale is an s-quantale with ⊗ associative and distributing across arbitrary ∨ from both sides (implying ⊥ is a two-sided zero) [20, 33, 49]; and a unital quantale (u-quantale) is a us-quantale which is a quantale; and a strictly two-sided quantale (st-quantale) is a u-quantale for which e = ⊤ [20]. All quantales are os-quantales. The notions of s-quantales, os-quantales, and us-quantales are from [45, 46]. SQuant comprises all semi-quantales together with mappings preserving ⊗ and arbitrary ∨ ; OSQuant is the full subcategory of SQuant of all os- quantales; USQuant is a subcategory of SQuant comprising all us-quantales together with all mappings preserving arbitrary ∨ , ⊗, and e; Quant is the full subcategory of OSQuant of all quantales; and UQuant is the full subcategory of UOSQuant of all unital quantales. Note uos-quantales for which ⊗ = ∧ (binary) are semiframes and SFrm is the full subcategory of UOSQuant of all semiframes; and u-quantales for which ⊗ = ∧ (binary) are frames— in which case e = ⊤—and Frm is the full subcategory of UQuant of all frames. Semiframes equipped with an order-reversing involution are com- plete DeMorgan algebras; and s-quantales equipped with a semi-polarity 80 S. E. Rodabaugh [16] (∀α, β ∈ L, α ≤ β ⇒ β′ ≤ α′ and α ≤ (α′) ′ ) are complete semi- DeMorgan s-quantales. Throughout this paper, the requirement of us-quantale [u-quantale] can be relaxed to s-quantale [quantale, resp.] if one wishes to consider the relationships between q-topology and q-bitopology ([46] and Subsection 1.5 below). Justifying the above lattice-theoretic notions is a wealth of examples (see [17, 20, 21, 23, 33, 35, 39, 40, 41, 44, 46] and their references). The lattice 2 = {⊥,⊤} with ⊥ 6= ⊤; and a lattice is consistent if it contains 2 and inconsistent if it is singleton (with ⊥ = ⊤). 1.3. Powerset operators. Let X ∈ |Set| and L ∈ |SQuant|. Then LX is the L-powerset of X of all L-subsets of X. The constant L-subset member of LX having value α is denoted α. All order-theoretic operations (e.g., ∨ , ∧ ) and algebraic operations (e.g., ⊗) on L lift point-wise to LX and are denoted by the same symbols. In the case L ∈ |USQuant| , the unit e lifts to the constant map e, which is the unit of ⊗ as lifted to LX . The operator ℘∅ : |Set| → |Set| is useful in this paper, where ℘∅ (X) denotes the poset of all the nonempty subsets of X. Let L ∈ |SQuant| , X, Y ∈ |Set| , and f : X → Y be in Set. Then the standard (traditional) image and preimage operators f→ : ℘ (X) → ℘ (Y ) , f← : ℘ (X) ← ℘ (Y ) are f→ (A) = {f (x) ∈ Y : x ∈ A} , f← (B) = {x ∈ X : f (x) ∈ B} , and the Zadeh image and preimage operators f→L : L X → LY , f←L : L X ← LY [53] are f→L (a) (y) = ∨ {a (x) : x ∈ f← ({y})} , f←L (b) = b ◦ f. If L is understood, it may be dropped providing the context distinguishes these operators from the traditional operators. It is observed that f→ and f← are naturally isomorphic to f→2 and f ← 2 , resp. It is well-known [36, 37, 39, 40, 46] that each f←L preserves arbitrary ∨ , arbitrary ∧ , ⊗, and all constant maps, as well as the unit e if L ∈ |USQuant|; each f→L preserves arbitrary ∨ ; f→ ⊣ f←, f→L ⊣ f ← L ; f→ and f→L are left-inverses [right-inverses] of f ← and f←L , resp., if f is sur- jective [injective, resp.]; and f→, f←, f→L , f ← L are all order-isomorphisms if and only if f is a bijection. Powerset operators and the powerset theories underlying lattice-valued math- ematics are studied extensively in [6, 14, 7, 8, 15, 10, 11, 36, 37, 39, 40, 46]. 1.4. Category theoretics. The main reference for categorical notions is [1], to which we refer the reader for various properties of functors as well as various versions of the Adjoint Functor Theorem and related notions. The proving of functorial adjunctions is done via lifting (or major) and naturality (or minor) diagrams in the manner of [28, 36, 37, 41]. Bitopology as topology 81 1.5. Topology and bitopology. Given L ∈ |USQuant|, the category L-Top comprises objects of the form (X, τ ), where τ ⊂ LX is closed under arbitrary ∨ and binary ⊗ and contains e—so that τ is a sub-us-quantale of LX , together with morphisms f : (X, τ ) → (Y, σ), where f : X → Y is a function and τ ⊃ (f←L ) → (σ) , namely f←L (v) ∈ τ for each v ∈ σ. The objects (X, τ ) are called L-topological spaces and τ is an L-topology on X comprising L-subsets of X; and the morphisms f are called L-continuous. Cf. [20, 41, 46]. Similarly, the category L-BiTop comprises objects of the form (X, τ, σ) , where τ, σ are L-topologies on X, together with morphisms f : (X, τ1, τ2) → (Y, σ1, σ2), where f : X → Y is a function and τ1 ⊃ (f ← L ) → (σ1) , τ2 ⊃ (f ← L ) → (σ2) . The objects (X, τ, σ) are called L-bitopological spaces and (τ, σ) is an L- bitopology on X; and the morphisms f are called L-bicontinuous. If the L is clear in context, it may be dropped from the labels. As noted in Subsection 1.1, the traditional category BiTop is isomorphic to 2-BiTop (cf. 3.25 below) and embeds into each L-BiTop, and similarly Top is isomorphic to 2-Top and embeds into each L-Top. Each of L-Top and L-BiTop has the base L of the category fixed and so is part of fixed-basis (lattice-valued) topology and fixed-basis (lattice-valued) bitopology, resp. The disciplines of fixed-basis topology and fixed-basis bitopol- ogy are encompassed by the respective classes {L-Top : L ∈ |USQuant|} , {L-BiTop : L ∈ |USQuant|} . Both L-Top and L-BiTop are topological over Set and have small fi- bres, hence are [co]complete and [co]well-powered, and hence are strongly [co]complete with many other nice properties (see 3.36 and its proof below). The categorical product for L-Top is given in, or adapted from, [12, 52] (cf. [20, 41]) and for {(Xγ , τγ ) : γ ∈ Γ} denoted by   ∏ γ ∈Γ (Xγ , τγ ) ,{πγ}γ ∈Γ   , ∏ γ ∈Γ (Xγ , τγ ) ≡ (×γ ∈ΓXγ , Πγ ∈Γτγ ) , where {πγ : γ ∈ Γ} are the projections. The binary L-topological product for two spaces (X, τ ) , (Y, σ) is denoted (X, τ ) Π (Y, σ) or (X × Y, τ Π σ) with pro- jections {π1, π2}. The categorical product for L-BiTop for {(Xγ , τγ ) : γ ∈ Γ} is   ∏ γ ∈Γ (Xγ , τγ , σγ ) ,{πγ}γ ∈Γ   , ∏ γ ∈Γ (Xγ , τγ , σγ ) ≡ (×γ ∈ΓXγ , Πγ ∈Γτγ , Πγ ∈Γσγ ) , where Πγ ∈Γτγ , Πγ ∈Γσγ are the L-topological product topologies in each slot and the projections are as above. 82 S. E. Rodabaugh An L-topology τ is weakly stratified [20] if {α : α ∈ L} ⊂ τ , non- stratified if it is not weakly stratified, and anti-stratified [9, 35] if {α : α ∈ L, α ∈ τ} = {⊥, e} ; so a weakly stratified topology contains all constant L-subsets, while an anti- stratified topology contains precisely the constant L-subsets ⊥ and e (which are the same if L is inconsistent with ⊥ = ⊤). An L-topological space is weakly stratified [anti-stratified] if its topology is weakly stratified [anti-stratified], and an L-bitopological space is weakly stratified [anti-stratified] if both topologies are weakly stratified [anti-stratified]. The inclusionist position that the axioms of a fixed-basis topology must allow for all types of stratification has recently received additional, emphatic confirmations from both lattice-valued frames [35] and topological systems in domain theory [9]. The following definition and proposition are needed in this paper. Definition 1.1. Let X be a set and let L be a us-quantale. Then the L- topological fibre, respectively, L-bitopological fibre on X is L-T (X) ≡ { τ ⊂ LX : (X, τ ) ∈ |L-Top| } , L-BT (X) ≡ {(τ, σ) : (X, τ, σ) ∈ |L-BiTop|} . Proposition 1.2. Let X be a set, let L be a us-quantale, and recall ℘∅ from Subsection 1.3. (1) L-T (X) is a complete meet subsemilattice of ℘ ( LX ) ; and since each L-topology is nonempty, L-T (X) ⊂ ℘∅ ( LX ) . (2) L-BT (X), ordered coordinate-wise by inclusion, is a complete meet subsemilattice of ℘ ( LX ) ×℘ ( LX ) ; and further, L-BT (X) ⊂ ℘∅ ( LX ) × ℘∅ ( LX ) . Proof. The first part of (1) is well-known, and the second part of (1) is trivial. Now (2) follows from (1) since L-BT (X) = L-T (X) × L-T (X) ⊂ ℘∅ ( LX ) × ℘∅ ( LX ) . � Finally, we need the notion of a subbase of an L-topology τ on X [41]. We say σ ⊂ LX is a subbase of τ , written τ = 〈〈σ〉〉 , if τ = ⋂ {τ′ ∈ L-T (X) : σ ⊂ τ′} , the right-hand side always existing by Proposition 1.2(1), and we say β ⊂ LX is a base of τ , written τ = 〈β〉 , if ∀u ∈ τ, ∃Bu ⊂ β, u = ∨ Bu. One can always pass from a subbase σ to a topology τ through a base β in the traditional way, written τ = 〈β〉 = 〈〈σ〉〉 , if and only if ⊗ is associative and distributes across arbitrary ∨ , i.e., if and only if L is a u-quantale. Bitopology as topology 83 2. Functorial interpretations of topology as bitopology For each us-quantale L, this section records a simple (and expected) “dou- bling” embedding Ed : L-Top → L-BiTop. The behavior of Ed w.r.t. limits and colimits—it preserves, reflects, detects both—is examined completely in Subsections 3.1–3.2 below. It emerges that Ed is an extremely well-behaved embedding. Proposition 2.1. Let L be a us-quantale. Define Ed : L-Top → L-BiTop by the following correspondences: Ed (X, τ ) = (X, τ, τ ) , Ed (f ) = f. Then Ed is a concrete, full, strict embedding; and so L-Top is isomorphic to a full subcategory of L-BiTop. Proof. All details are straightforward. � 3. Functorial interpretations of bitopology as topology This section records several interpretations of bitopology as topology, the most important of which would seem to be the extremely well-behaved embed- ding E× of Subsection 3.4. 3.1. Fl, Fr, F∧ : L-BiTop → L-Top and behavior of Ed : L-Top → L- BiTop w.r.t. limits. This subsection constructs the concrete, faithful, full forgetful functors—the “left-forgetful” functor Fl : L-BiTop → L-Top and the “right-forgetful” Fr : L-BiTop → L-Top—as well as the concrete, faithful “meet” functor F∧ : L-BiTop → L-Top and shows F∧ is the left-adjoint of Ed of the previous section and that each of Fl, Fr is a left-adjoint of Ed under certain restrictions. Proposition 3.1. Let L be a us-quantale and define Fl, Fr : L-BiTop → L- Top as follows: Fl (X, τ, σ) = (X, τ ) , Fl (f ) = f, Fr (X, τ, σ) = (X, σ) , Fr (f ) = f. Then each of Fl, Fr is a concrete, faithful, full, object-surjective functor, but need not be an embedding. Proof. We comment only on Fl. Trivially, Fl is a concrete, faithful, object- surjective functor. As for fullness, let f : (X, τ ) → (Y, σ) in L-Top; then f : (X, τ, τ ) → (Y, σ, σ) is L-bicontinuous, so is in L-BiTop, and maps to f : (X, τ ) → (Y, σ). Now suppose that either [|X| ≥ 1 and |L| ≥ 3] or [|X| ≥ 2 and |L| ≥ 2]; then ∃τ, σ ∈ L-T (X) with τ 6= σ, so that Fl (X, τ, σ) = (X, τ ) = Fl (X, τ, τ ), and hence Fl does not inject objects and is not an embedding. � Proposition 3.2. Let L be a us-quantale and define F∧ : L-BiTop → L-Top as follows: F∧ (X, τ, σ) = (X, τ ∩ σ) , F∧ (f ) = f. 84 S. E. Rodabaugh Then F∧ is a concrete, faithful, object-surjective functor, but need not be full nor an embedding. Proof. Since L-Top has complete fibres, F∧ is well-defined on objects. Now let f : (X, τ1, τ2) → (Y, σ1, σ2) be L-bicontinuous. Since the image operator of the Zadeh preimage operator preserves ⊂, it follows τ1 ⊃ (f ← L ) → (σ1) , τ2 ⊃ (f ← L ) → (σ2) ⇒ τ1 ∩ τ2 ⊃ (f ← L ) → (σ1) ∩ (f ← L ) → (σ2) ⊃ (f ← L ) → (σ1 ∩ σ2) , so that f : (X, τ1 ∩ τ2) → (Y, σ1∩σ2) is L-continuous. Immediately, F∧ is a concrete, faithful functor which surjects objects. Now let L be a complete DeMorgan algebra (with ⊗ = ∧ (binary)) and consider each of the L-bitopological spaces (R (L) , τl (L) , τl (L)) and (R (L) , τl (L) , τ (L)) , where R (L) is the L-fuzzy real line, τl (L) is the left-hand L-topology on R (L) determined by the Lt operators and τ (L) is the standard L-topology on R (L) [43]. Then (R (L) , τl (L) , τl (L)) 6= (R (L) , τl (L) , τ (L)) and F∧ (R (L) , τl (L) , τl (L)) = (R (L) , τl (L)) = (R (L) , τl (L) ∩ τ (L)) = F∧ (R (L) , τl (L) , τ (L)) , showing that F∧ does not inject objects, so is not an embedding. Now letting f : R (L) → R (L) be idR(L), we have f : F∧ (R (L) , τl (L) , τ (L)) → F∧ (R (L) , τ (L) , τl (L)) is L-continuous, but f : (R (L) , τl (L) , τ (L)) → (R (L) , τ (L) , τl (L)) cannot be L-bicontinuous (because of the first slot). The concreteness of F∧ implies there exists no g ∈ L-BiTop with F∧ (g) = f , so F∧ is not full. � Theorem 3.3. Let L be a us-quantale. Then F∧ ⊣ Ed, this adjunction is a monocoreflection, and F∧ takes L-BiTop to a monocoreflective subcategory of L-Top. On the other hand, Ed ⊣/ F∧. Proof. Let (X, τ1, τ2) ∈ |L-BiTop| , choose η = id : (X, τ1, τ2) → EdF∧ (X, τ1, τ2) = (X, τ1 ∩ τ2, τ1 ∩ τ2) , and note η is an L-continuous injection. Now let (Y, σ) ∈ |L-Top| , suppose f : (X, τ1, τ2) → Ed (Y, σ) = (Y, σ, σ) is L-bicontinuous, and note τ1 ⊃ (f ← L ) → (σ) , τ2 ⊃ (f ← L ) → (σ) ⇒ τ1 ∩ τ2 ⊃ (f ← L ) → (σ) , making f : F∧ (X, τ1, τ2) = (X, τ1 ∩ τ2) → (Y, σ) L-continuous. Then f = f is the unique choice making f = f ◦ η. The naturality diagram now follows by concreteness as do the other claims concerning F∧ ⊣ Ed. Finally, given F∨ of Subsection 3.2 and Ed ⊣ F∨ of 3.9 below, Ed ⊣/ F∧ since F∧ ≇ F∨ and right-adjoints are essentially unique. � Bitopology as topology 85 Definition 3.4. L-BiTop (⊂) [L-BiTop (⊃)] is the full subcategory of L- BiTop of all spaces (X, τ, σ) in which τ ⊂ σ [τ ⊃ σ]. Note BiTop (⊂) and BiTop (⊃) (essentially setting L = 2) express the original sense of traditional bitopology [3, 4]. Proposition 3.5. Let L be a us-quantale. Then Fl |L-BiTop(⊂) = F∧|L-BiTop(⊂), Fr |L-BiTop(⊃) = F∧|L-BiTop(⊃). Hence Fl |L-BiTop(⊂) ⊣ Ed and Fr |L-BiTop(⊃) ⊣ Ed, but Ed ⊣/ Fl |L-BiTop(⊂) and Ed ⊣/ Fr |L-BiTop(⊃). Proof. The restricted forgetful functors obviously coincide with the meet func- tor. Observing that Ed maps into each of L-BiTop (⊂) and L-BiTop (⊃), the claimed adjunctions are then immediate from 3.3. The claimed non-adjunctions follow from 3.10 below. � Corollary 3.6. Let L be a us-quantale. The following hold: (1) Ed preserves all strong limits and F∧ preserves all strong colimits. (2) Fl preserves the strong colimits of L-BiTop (⊂), Fr preserves the strong colimits of L-BiTop (⊃), and Ed preserves strong limits into each of L-BiTop (⊂) and L-BiTop (⊃). Proposition 3.7. For each us-quantale L, Ed : L-Top → L-BiTop reflects and detects all limits and hence lifts all limits and is transportable. Proof. The details are straightforward using 3.6 and Proposition 13.34 [1]. � 3.2. F∨ : L-BiTop → L-Top and behavior of Ed : L-Top → L-BiTop w.r.t. colimits. This subsection constructs the concrete, faithful “join” func- tor F∨ : L-BiTop → L-Top and shows it is the right-adjoint of Ed of the previous section. Proposition 3.8. Let L be a us-quantale and define F∨ : L-BiTop → L-Top as follows: F∨ (X, τ, σ) = (X, τ ∨ σ) , F∨ (f ) = f, where τ ∨ σ = 〈〈τ ∪ σ〉〉 Then F∨ is a concrete, faithful, object-surjective functor, but need not be full nor an embedding. Proof. Since L-Top has complete fibres, F∨ is well-defined on objects. Now let f : (X, τ1, τ2) → (Y, σ1, σ2) be L-bicontinuous. Since the image operator of the Zadeh preimage operator preserves unions, then τ1 ⊃ (f ← L ) → (σ1) , τ2 ⊃ (f ← L ) → (σ2) ⇒ τ1 ∨ τ2 ⊃ τ1 ∪ τ2 ⊃ (f ← L ) → (σ1) ∪ (f ← L ) → (σ2) = (f ← L ) → (σ1 ∪ σ2) , 86 S. E. Rodabaugh so that f : (X, τ1 ∨ τ2) → (Y, σ1 ∨ σ2) is L-subbasic continuous. By Theorem 3.2.6 of [41] as restricted to the fixed-basis case and then adapted to the us- quantalic case, f : (X, τ1 ∨ τ2) → (Y, σ1 ∨ σ2) is L-continuous. Immediately, F∨ is a concrete, faithful functor which surjects objects. Now let L be a complete DeMorgan algebra (with ⊗ = ∧ (binary)) and con- sider each of the L-bitopological spaces (R (L) , τl (L) , τr (L)) and (R (L) , τ (L) , τ (L)) , where R (L) is the L-fuzzy real line, τl (L) is the left-hand L-topology on R (L) determined by the Lt operators, τr (L) is the left-hand L- topology on R (L) determined by the Rt operators, and τ (L) is the standard L-topology on R (L) [43]. Then (R (L) , τl (L) , τr (L)) 6= (R (L) , τ (L) , τ (L)) and F∨ (R (L) , τl (L) , τr (L)) = (R (L) , τl (L) ∨ τr (L)) = (R (L) , τ (L)) = F∨ (R (L) , τ (L) , τ (L)) , showing that F∨ does not inject objects, so is not an embedding. Now letting f : R (L) → R (L) be idR(L), we have f : F∨ (R (L) , τl (L) , τr (L)) → F∨ (R (L) , τr (L) , τl (L)) is L-continuous, but f : (R (L) , τl (L) , τr (L)) → (R (L) , τr (L) , τl (L)) cannot be L-bicontinuous. The concreteness of F∨ implies there exists no g ∈ L-BiTop with F∨ (g) = f , so F∨ is not full. � Theorem 3.9. Let L be a us-quantale. Then Ed ⊣ F∨, this adjunction is an isoreflection, and F∨ takes L-BiTop to an isoreflective subcategory of L-Top. On the other hand, F∨ ⊣/ Ed. Proof. Let (X, τ ) ∈ |L-Top| , choose η = id : (X, τ ) → F∨Ed (X, τ ) = (X, τ ∨ τ ) = (X, τ ) , and note η is an L-homeomorphism. Now let (Y, σ1, σ2) ∈ |L-BiTop| , suppose f : (X, τ ) → F∨ (Y, σ1, σ2) = (Y, σ1 ∨ σ2) is L-continuous, and note τ ⊃ (f←L ) → (σ1 ∨ σ2) ⊃ (f ← L ) → (σ1 ∪ σ2) ⊃ (f ← L ) → (σ1) , (f ← L ) → (σ2) , making f : Ed (X, τ ) = (X, τ, τ ) → (Y, σ1, σ2) L-bicontinuous. Then f = f is the unique choice making f = f ◦ η. The naturality diagram now follows by concreteness, as do the other claims concerning Ed ⊣ F∨. Finally, given F∧ of Subsection 3.1 and F∧ ⊣ Ed of 3.3 above, F∨ ⊣/ Ed since F∧ ≇ F∨ and left-adjoints are essentially unique. � Corollary 3.10. Let L be a us-quantale. The following hold: (1) Ed preserves all strong colimits and F∨ preserves all strong limits. (2) Ed ⊣/ Fl |L-BiTop(⊂) and Ed ⊣/ Fr |L-BiTop(⊃), and hence Ed ⊣/ Fl and Ed ⊣/ Fr. Bitopology as topology 87 Proof. (1) is immediate. As for (2), it is clear that Fl |L-BiTop(⊂), Fr |L-BiTop(⊃) ≇ F∨ |L-BiTop(⊂), F∨ |L-BiTop(⊃), resp., implying Ed ⊣/ Fl |L-BiTop(⊂) and Ed ⊣/ Fr |L-BiTop(⊃) by the essential uniqueness of the right-adjoint in 3.9; and hence Ed ⊣/ Fl and Ed ⊣/ Fr. � Proposition 3.11. For each us-quantale L, Ed : L-Top → L-BiTop reflects and detects all colimits. Proof. The details are straightforward. � 3.3. FΠ : L-BiTop → L-Top. This subsection constructs the non-concrete, faithful “product” functor FΠ : L-BiTop → L-Top which, when appropriately restricted, is an embedding. It need not preserve finite products and hence lacks a left-adjoint. Proposition 3.12. Let L be a us-quantale and define FΠ : L-BiTop → L-Top as follows: FΠ (X, τ, σ) = (X × X, τ Π σ) , FΠ (f ) = f × f, where τ Π σ is the L-product topology on X × X (Subsection 1.5). Then FΠ is a non-concrete, faithful functor which need not be full nor object-surjective nor an embedding. Proof. Immediately FΠ is well-defined on objects. Let f : (X, τ1, τ2) → (Y, σ1, σ2) be L-bicontinuous and let v ∈ σ1 Π σ2 be a subbasic open set of the form (π1) ← L (s1) with s1 ∈ σ1. Then given (x1, x2) ∈ X × X, (f × f ) ← L (v) (x1, x2) = (π1) ← L (s1) (f (x1) , f (x2)) = s1 (π1 (f (x1) , f (x2))) = s1 (f (x1)) = f←L (s1) (x1) = f←L (s1) (π1 (x1, x2)) = (π1) ← L (f←L (s1)) (x1, x2) , so that (f × f ) ← L (v) = (π1) ← L (f←L (s1)) ∈ τ1 Π τ2; and similarly, if v is a sub- basic open set of the form (π2) ← L (s2) with s2 ∈ σ2, (f × f ) ← L (v) ∈ τ1 Π τ2. So FΠ (f ) : FΠ (X, τ1, τ2) → FΠ (Y, σ1, σ2) is L-subbasic continuous and hence L-continuous (cf. Theorem 3.2.6 of [41]). It is easy to show FΠ preserves com- position and identities—and so is a functor—and is faithful and need not be full nor object-surjective. To see that FΠ need not inject objects, let L = {⊥, α, β,⊤} be a chain with ⊗ = ∧ (binary), X = {x} , τ1 = {⊥, α,⊤} , and τ2 = { ⊥, β,⊤ } . Then (X, τ1, τ2) 6= (X, τ2, τ1) , yet FΠ (X, τ1, τ2) = FΠ (X, τ2, τ1). � Proposition 3.13. FΠ does not preserve binary products and hence has no left-adjoint. Proof. Let (X, τ1, τ2) , (Y, σ1, σ2) be given with X 6= Y . Then the carrier set of FΠ [(X, τ1, τ2) Π (Y, σ1, σ2)] is (X × Y ) × (X × Y ) and the carrier set of FΠ (X, τ1, τ2) Π FΠ (Y, σ1, σ2) is (X × X)×(Y × Y ), clearly not the same. � 88 S. E. Rodabaugh Definition 3.14. Letting L be a us-quantale, L-NBiTop is the full subcategory of all spaces (X, τ, σ) satisfying the condition that each open L-subset u 6= ⊥ in each of τ, σ is L-normalized, i.e., has the property that ∨ x∈X u (x) = e. If L is an st-quantale, then the notion of L-normalized subsets coincides with the usual notion, namely ∨ x∈X u (x) = ⊤. Theorem 3.15. Let L be a u-quantale. Then FΠ |L-NBiTop : L-NBiTop → L- Top is an embedding. This embedding does not preserve binary products and hence has no left-adjoint. Proof. Because of 3.12, it suffices to show FΠ as restricted injects objects. For two distinct objects, let us consider (X, τ1, σ) 6= (X, τ2, σ) with τ1 6= τ2; all other cases are similar and left to the reader. Suppose W.L.O.G. there is u ∈ τ1 − τ2 and assume τ1 Π σ = τ2 Π σ on X × X. Then setting ⊠ ≡⊗◦×, ∃ {uγ ⊠ vγ}γ ∈Γ ⊂ τ2 Π σ such that (π1) ← L (u) = ∨ γ ∈Γ (uγ ⊠ vγ ) . Applying the surjectivity of π1 and properties of Zadeh image operators (Sub- section 1.3), we obtain the contradiction u = (π1) → L ((π1) ← L (u)) = (π1) → L   ∨ γ ∈Γ (uγ ⊠ vγ )   = ∨ γ ∈Γ ((π1) → L (uγ ⊠ vγ )) = ∨ γ ∈Γ uγ ∈ τ2, where we have used the fact, for each γ ∈ Γ and each x ∈ X, that (π1) → L (uγ ⊠ vγ ) (x) = ∨ y ∈X (uγ ⊠ vγ ) (x, y) = ∨ y ∈X (uγ (x) ⊗ vγ (y)) = uγ (x) ⊗ ∨ y ∈X vγ (y) = uγ (x) ⊗ e = uγ (x) . Bitopology as topology 89 The non-preservation of products follow for the restricted functor as in the proof of 3.13. � Corollary 3.16. FΠ ◦ Gχ : BiTop → Top is an embedding. This embedding does not preserve binary products and hence has no left-adjoint. Proof. The first statement is a corollary of 3.15 as follows: given any non-empty subset A of set X, χA : X → 2 is normalized; 2-NBiTop = 2-BiTop; and Gχ : BiTop → 2-BiTop is a categorical isomorphism. The non-preservation of products follows for the composite functor as in the proof of 3.13. � Remark 3.17. Corollary 3.16 furnishes an embedding of BiTop into Top; but this is not enough to say that Top may be categorically regarded as a generalization of BiTop since FΠ ◦ Gχ is not sufficiently well-behaved. This motivates the search for a better behaved embedding of bitopology into topol- ogy conducted in the next subsection. 3.4. E× : L-BiTop → L 2-Top. This subsection constructs the concrete, full, strict “cross” embedding E× : L-BiTop → L 2-Top, establishes its behavior w.r.t. limits and colimits—for appropriate L, E× preserves both and detects and reflects the former, and shows that E× is essentially neutral w.r.t. strati- fication issues. It follows that E× is an extremely well-behaved embedding. 3.4.1. Construction of E× : L-BiTop → L 2-Top. Proposition 3.18 (cf. [16]). Let X be a set. (1) For each set L the mapping ϕX : L X × LX → ( L2 )X given by ϕX (a1, a2) = a1 × a2, i.e., ϕX (a1, a2) (x) = (a1 (x) , a2 (x)) is a bijection with inverse mapping ϕ−1 X : LX × LX ← ( L2 )X given by ϕ−1 X (a) = (π1 ◦ a, π2 ◦ a) , where π1, π2 are the projections from L 2 to L. (2) If L is a poset, then ϕX is an order-isomorphism. (3) If L is a semi-DeMorgan s-quantale, then ϕX preserves semi-complements. (4) If L is an [u]s-quantale, then ϕX is an [u]s-quantalic isomorphism (i.e., ϕX also preserves tensor products [and the unit]). Proof. The details of (1)−(3) are the same as, or analogous to, those of Lemma 4.4.1 of [16]. The details of (4) are straightforward. � Corollary 3.19. ϕ→X : ℘ ( LX × LX ) → ℘ ( ( L2 )X ) is an order-isomorphism. Proof. This is immediate from 3.18(1) using Subsection 1.3. � Proposition 3.20. Let A, B be nonempty sets. Then ζ : ℘∅ (A) × ℘∅ (B) → ℘∅ (A × B) given by ζ (C, D) = C × D is an order-isomorphism onto its image, i.e., an order-embedding. 90 S. E. Rodabaugh Proof. Clearly ζ is well-defined. As for injectivity, let (C1, D1) 6= (C2, D2). Then there are several cases, and a typical case is C1 6= C2, D1 = D2. Then W.L.O.G. there is x ∈ C1 − C2. Since D1 = D2 6= ∅, there is y ∈ D1 = D2. So (x, y) ∈ (C1 × D1) − (C2 × D2) ; hence ζ (C1, D1) 6= ζ (C2, D2). Since all orderings in question are coordinate-wise, it follows that both ζ and ζ−1 (on Im (ζ)) are isotone. � Proposition 3.21. Let X be a set, L be a us-quantale, and ζ denote any restriction of the ζ of 3.20. (1) ζ : ℘∅ ( LX ) ×℘∅ ( LX ) → ℘∅ ( LX × LX ) is an order-isomorphism onto its image. (2) ζ : L-BT (X) → ℘∅ ( LX × LX ) is an order-isomorphism onto its im- age. Proof. Conjoin Proposition 1.2 and 3.20. � Lemma 3.22. Let X be a set and L be a us-quantale, and put E× : L-BT (X) → L 2-T (X) by E× = ϕ → X ◦ ζ. Then E× is an order-isomorphism onto its image. Proof. It must be first verified that E× actually maps into L 2-T (X). Let (τ1, τ2) ∈ L-BT (X). Then τ1, τ2 are L-topologies on X and hence sub-us- quantales of LX . It is straightforward to check that as direct products, ζ (τ1, τ2) = τ1 × τ2 ⊂ L X × LX and τ1 × τ2 is a sub-us-quantale of L X × LX . It follows E× (τ1, τ2) = ϕ → X (ζ (τ1, τ2)) = ϕ → X (τ1 × τ2) ⊂ ℘ ( ( L2 )X ) and that E× (τ1, τ2) is a sub-us-quantale of ( L2 )X , namely an L2-topology on X. Hence E× (τ1, τ2) ∈ L 2-T (X). The remaining claims concerning E× follow from 3.19 and 3.21. � Theorem 3.23. Let L be a us-quantale, let f ∈ L-BiTop ((X, τ1, τ2) , (Y, σ1, σ2)) , and put E× (X, τ1, τ2) = (X, E× (τ1, τ2)) , E× (f ) = f. Then E× : L-BiTop → L 2-Top is a concrete, full embedding; and hence L-BiTop is concretely isomorphic to a full subcategory of L2-Top. Further, if L is consistent, E× is a strict embedding (not a functorial isomorphism). Proof. It is immediate from 3.22 that E× is well-defined at the object-level into L2-Top. It must be now checked that E× is well-defined at the morphism-level, i.e., that f : (X, τ1, τ2) → (Y, σ1, σ2) is L-bicontinuous implies f : (X, E× (τ1, τ2)) → (Y, E× (σ1, σ2)) is L 2-continuous. To that end, let v ∈ E× (σ1, σ2) = ϕ → Y (σ1 × σ2) . Bitopology as topology 91 Then ∃ (v1, v2) ∈ σ1 × σ2 with v = ϕY (v1, v2) . Now let x ∈ X. Then f←L (v) (x) = v (f (x)) = ϕY (v1, v2) (f (x)) = (v1 (f (x)) , v2 (f (x))) = (f←L (v1) (x) , f ← L (v2) (x)) . Since f is L-bicontinuous, u1 ≡ f ← L (v1) ∈ τ1, u2 ≡ f ← L (v2) ∈ τ2; and so choosing u = ϕX (u1, u2) ∈ E× (τ1, τ2) , we have f←L (v) = u, finishing the proof that f is L2-continuous. Since E× is concrete (with respect to the usual forgetful functors), it is im- mediate that E× is a functor and that E× injects hom-sets. To verify that E× is full, we show that f : (X, E× (τ1, τ2)) → (Y, E× (σ1, σ2)) is L 2-continuous im- plies f : (X, τ1, τ2) → (Y, σ1, σ2) is L-bicontinuous. Let v ∈ σ1 and note ⊥∈ σ2. Then (v,⊥) ∈ σ1×σ2, so that ϕY (v,⊥) ∈ E× (σ1, σ2). Hence f ← L (ϕY (v,⊥)) ∈ E× (τ1, τ2) by the L 2-continuity of f . It follows ∃u ∈ E× (τ1, τ2) , and hence ∃ (u1, u2) ∈ τ1 × τ2, such that f←L (ϕY (v,⊥)) = u = ϕX (u1, u2) . Now let x ∈ X. Then (u1 (x) , u2 (x)) = ϕX (u1, u2) (x) = f←L (ϕY (v,⊥)) (x) = (v (f (x)) ,⊥) = (f←L (v) (x) ,⊥) , so that u1 (x) = f ← L (v) (x) . It follows f ← L (v) = u1 ∈ τ1. Similarly, it can be shown that if v ∈ σ2, then f ← L (v) ∈ τ2. Hence f is L-bicontinuous. For E× to be an embedding, it remains to show that E× injects objects. To that end let (X, τ1, τ2) 6= (Y, σ1, σ2) . If X 6= Y, we are done. So suppose that X = Y and that (τ1, τ2) 6= (σ1, σ2). Then immediately by 3.22, E× (τ1, τ2) 6= E× (σ1, σ2) . It follows that E× (X, τ1, τ2) 6= E× (Y, σ1, σ2) . Finally, the strictness of E×, when L is consistent, follows from 3.24 below. � Many more properties of E× are developed in the next three subsections which show that it is an extremely well-behaved embedding. 92 S. E. Rodabaugh Counterexample 3.24. If E× were to surject objects, then E× would be a functorial isomorphism. This however is usually not the case. Let L be any consistent us-quantale, note L ⊃ 2 = {⊥, e}, and consider the L2-topological space (X, τ ) with X nonempty and τ the indiscrete L2-topology τ = { (⊥,⊥), (e, e) } . Suppose a space (X, E× (τ1, τ2)) from the image of E× is (X, τ ). This forces ϕ→X (τ1 × τ2) = E× (τ1, τ2) = τ. Noting {⊥, e}⊂ τ1, {⊥, e}⊂ τ2, it follows ϕX (⊥, e) ∈ ϕ → X (τ1 × τ2) , ϕX (⊥, e) = (⊥, e) /∈ τ, a contradiction. Hence the space (X, τ ) is not in the image of E×. Hence, for consistent L it is the case that E× is not a functorial isomorphism, but a strict embedding. This justifies examining E×’s behavior w.r.t. limits and colimits in the next Subsubsections 3.4.2–3.4.3 as well as characterizing ∣ ∣E→× (L-BiTop) ∣ ∣ in 3.28. Corollary 3.25. Let 4 be the 4-element Boolean algebra {⊥, α, β,⊤}with ⊗ = ∧ (binary). Then the traditional category BiTop of bitopological spaces and bicontinuous maps concretely, fully, strictly embeds into 4-Top as a full monocoreflective subcategory that is closed under all limits and colimits. Proof. Consider the bitopological version Gχ : BiTop → 2-BiTop of the cha- racteristic functor given by Gχ (T) = {χU : U ∈ T} , Gχ (S) = {χV : V ∈ S} , Gχ (X, T, S) = (X, Gχ (T) , Gχ (S)) , Gχ (f ) = f. Then this bitopological Gχ is a concrete functorial isomorphism. Now clearly by the direct product of us-quantales, 22 ∼= 4, so by 3.23 and 3.24, 2-BiTop concretely, fully, strictly embeds into 4-Top. Hence via the composition E× ◦ Gχ : BiTop →֒ 4-Top, BiTop concretely, fully, strictly embeds into 4-Top. For the monoreflectivity claim, see 3.26 below; and the claim regarding limits and colimits follows from Subsubsections 3.4.2–3.4.3 below, the limit claim needing the observation that 4 is a u-quantale with ⊗ = ∧. � Bitopology as topology 93 3.4.2. Behavior of E× : L-BiTop → L 2-Top w.r.t. colimits. Since for all consistent L the full concrete embedding E× is not a functorial isomorphism, but only a strict embedding, it is worthwhile to investigate its behavior w.r.t. limits and colimits. This subsection shows for any us-quantale L that the embedding E× has a right-adjoint—and hence preserves colimits. The next subsection then shows step by step for L a u-quantale that the Special Adjoint Functor Theorem constructs for E× a left-adjoint—and hence E× preserves limits; and further the next subsection shows for any us-quantale L that the embedding E× reflects and detects all limits and is transportable. Therefore, this subsection—in concert with the preceding and subsequent subsections— shows that E× is an extremely well-behaved embedding. Theorem 3.26 (E× ⊣ Fπ). Let L be a us-quantale and put the “projection” functor Fπ : L-BiTop ← L 2-Top as follows: Fπ (X, τ ) = (X, Fπ (τ )) , Fπ (f ) = f, where the fibre level of Fπ Fπ (τ ) = (π1 ◦ τ ≡{π1 ◦ u : u ∈ τ} , π2 ◦ τ ≡{π2 ◦ u : u ∈ τ}) uses the projections π1, π2 : L × L → L for the us-quantalic (direct) product. Then the following hold: (1) Fπ is a concrete embedding which is not full and does not lift limits. (2) E× ⊣ Fπ , so E× preserves all strong colimits and Fπ preserves all strong limits. (3) Fπ need not detect limits nor be transportable. (4) Fπ ◦ E× = IdL-BiTop. (5) L-BiTop is isomorphic (via E×) to a full monocoreflective subcategory of L2-Top. (6) L2-Top is isomorphic (via Fπ) to an isoreflective subcategory of L-BiTop. Proof. Ad(1). Since us-quantalic projections preserve arbitrary joins, the ten- sor, and the unit, it follows that Fπ (τ ) ∈ L-BT (X); and hence (X, Fπ (τ )) ∈ |L-BiTop| and Fπ is well-defined at the object level. As for morphisms, let f : (X, τ ) → (Y, σ) be L2-continuous in L2-Top. Then, given v ∈ σ, the identities f←L (π1 ◦ v) = π1 ◦ f ← L (v) , f ← L (π2 ◦ v) = π2 ◦ f ← L (v) are easily checked and immediately imply that f : (X, Fπ (τ )) → (Y, Fπ (σ)) is L-bicontinuous in L-BiTop. Now by the concreteness of Fπ, it is immediately a concrete and faithful functor. To show that Fπ is an embedding, it remains to check that Fπ injects objects: but if u, v : X → L 2 are distinct, there exists x ∈ X such that W.L.O.G. π1 (u (x)) 6= π1 (v (x)) ; which implies that if τ 6= σ as L2-topologies on X, then Fπ (τ ) 6= Fπ (σ) as L-bitopologies on X, showing that Fπ injects objects. 94 S. E. Rodabaugh To see that Fπ need not be full, let L = 2, write the Boolean algebra L 2 = 4 as {(⊥,⊥) , (⊥,⊤) , (⊤,⊥) , (⊤,⊤)}, let X = {x} , and choose τ = { (⊥,⊥), (⊤,⊤) } , σ = { (⊥,⊥), (⊥,⊤), (⊤,⊥), (⊤,⊤) } . Then it follows idX : (X, τ ) → (X, σ) is not L 2-continuous (since σ is not a subset of τ ). Now π1 ◦ (⊥,⊥) = π1 ◦ (⊥,⊤) = ⊥, π1 ◦ (⊤,⊥) = π1 ◦ (⊤,⊤) = ⊤, π2 ◦ (⊥,⊥) = π2 ◦ (⊤,⊥) = ⊥, π2 ◦ (⊥,⊤) = π2 ◦ (⊤,⊤) = ⊤, so that Fπ (τ ) = (π1 ◦ τ, π2 ◦ τ ) = ({⊥,⊤} , {⊥,⊤}) = (π1 ◦ σ, π2 ◦ σ) = Fπ (σ) , implying idX : (X, Fπ (τ )) → (X, Fπ (σ)) is L-bicontinuous. The concreteness of Fπ implies there exists no g ∈ L-Top with Fπ (g) = idX , so Fπ is not full. To see that Fπ need not lift limits, let the diagram in L 2-Top be the space (X, σ) of the preceding paragraph. Then the image of this diagram is the space (X, Fπ (σ)) in L-BiTop. Now the space (X, Fπ (τ )), together with the arrow idX : (X, Fπ (τ )) → (X, Fπ (σ)), is a limit of the diagram (X, Fπ (σ)): any L-bicontinuous f : (Z, υ1, υ2) → (X, Fπ (σ)) trivially factors uniquely through idX . But as seen in the preceding paragraph, there is no g ∈ L-Top with Fπ (g) = idX , which means there is no limiting cone of (X, σ) in L 2-Top which Fπ carries over to the limit idX : (X, Fπ (τ )) → (X, Fπ (σ)) in L-BiTop. Hence Fπ need not lift limits. Ad(2). Let (X, τ1, τ2) ∈ |L-BiTop| be given. Then FπE× (X, τ1, τ2) = Fπ (X, ϕ → X (τ1 × τ2)) ≡ (X, τ̂1, τ̂2) , where it follows that τ̂1 = {π1 ◦ ϕX (u, v) : u ∈ τ1, v ∈ τ2} , τ̂2 = {π1 ◦ ϕX (u, v) : u ∈ τ1, v ∈ τ2} . We choose the right unit η to be the identity mapping id : X → X. Then for each x ∈ X, (π1 ◦ ϕX (u, v)) (x) = π1 (u (x) , v (x)) = u (x) , (π2 ◦ ϕX (u, v)) (x) = π2 (u (x) , v (x)) = v (x) , which immediately gives the L-bicontinuity of η. For universality of the lifting, let (X, τ ) ∈ ∣ ∣L2-Top ∣ ∣ be given, along with an L-bicontinuous map f : (X, τ1, τ2) → (X, Fπ (τ )). Choosing f̄ = f , we now check f̄ : E× (X, τ1, τ2) → (X, τ ) is an L-continuous map from E× (X, τ1, τ2) to (X, τ ) by letting v ∈ τ and x ∈ X. Then the L-bicontinuity of f implies f←L (π1 ◦ u) ∈ τ1, f ← L (π2 ◦ u) ∈ τ2, Bitopology as topology 95 from which it follows ϕX (f ← L (π1 ◦ u) ∈ τ1, f ← L (π2 ◦ u) ∈ τ2) ∈ ϕ → X (τ1 × τ2) . Further, we note f←L (u) (x) = u (f (x)) = (π1 (u (x)) , π2 (u (x))) = (f←L (π1 ◦ u) (x) , f ← L (π2 ◦ u) (x)) = ϕX (f ← L (π1 ◦ u) ∈ τ1, f ← L (π2 ◦ u) ∈ τ2) (x) . Finally, it is immediate that f̄ is the unique L-continuous map from E× (X, τ1, τ2) to (X, τ ) such that f = f̄ ◦ η, completing the universality of the lifting. The naturality diagram now follows by concreteness. Ad(3). This is an immediate consequence of (1), (2), and Proposition 13.34 [1]. Ad(4). Since τ̂1 = τ1, τ̂2 = τ2 in the proof of (2), it is immediate that Fπ ◦ E× = IdL-BiTop. Ad(5). Using Fπ ◦E× = IdL-BiTop, the components of the left unit (counit) of E× ⊣ Fπ furnish the needed monocoreflection arrows to L 2-topological spaces from the E× image of L-BiTop. Ad(6). Using Fπ ◦ E× = IdL-BiTop, the components of the right unit of E× ⊣ Fπ furnish the needed isocoreflection arrows to L-bitopological spaces from the Fπ image of L 2-Top. � Remark 3.27. We collect some facts concerning E×, Fπ , and their fibre- dependent constructions, where L is a us-quantale: (1) Fπ ⊣/ E× if L is consistent. This is a consequence of 3.24. (2) E× ⊣ Fπ need not be a categorical equivalence. This follows from (1). (3) For each (X, τ1, τ2) ∈ |L-BiTop| , FπE× (τ1, τ2) = Fπ (ϕ → X (τ1 × τ2)) = (π1 ◦ ϕ → X (τ1 × τ2) , π2 ◦ ϕ → X (τ1 × τ2)) = (τ1, τ2) . (4) For each (X, τ ) ∈ ∣ ∣L2-Top ∣ ∣ , “E× (Fπ (τ )) = ϕ → X ((π1 ◦ τ ) × (π2 ◦ τ )) ⊃ τ ” always holds; but for L consistent, “E× (Fπ (τ )) = ϕ → X ((π1 ◦ τ ) × (π2 ◦ τ )) ⊂ τ ” need not hold. The latter statement is another version of (1). Theorem 3.28 (characterization of ∣ ∣E→× (L-BiTop) ∣ ∣). Let L be a us-quantale and (X, τ ) ∈ ∣ ∣L2-Top ∣ ∣. Then (X, τ ) ∈ ∣ ∣E→× (L-BiTop) ∣ ∣ if and only if E× (Fπ (τ )) = τ , i.e., both inequalities of 3.27(4) hold. 96 S. E. Rodabaugh 3.4.3. Behavior of E× : L-BiTop → L 2-Top w.r.t. limits. The question of a left-adjoint for E× is open for general us-quantales L; and it is our conjecture is that for general us-quantales L, E× would not preserve products or intersections and hence would not have a left-adjoint. But on the other hand, this section shows E× has a left-adjoint (and therefore preserves all limits) for L any u- quantale. We point out that our proof of this left-adjoint is existential (via the Special Adjoint Functor Theorem) and not constructive; and it is an additional open question whether there is a direct construction of this left adjoint not essentially factoring through our proof. It is further proved that E× reflects and detects limits and is transportable. Lemma 3.29 (preservation of products). For each u-quantale L, E× : L- BiTop → L2-Top preserves arbitrary (small) products. Sublemma 3.30. Let L be a u-quantale and suppose X is a set and τ1, τ2 are L-topologies on X with respective subbases σ1, σ2, namely τ1 = 〈〈σ1〉〉 , τ2 = 〈〈σ2〉〉 , such that {⊥, e}⊂ σ1 ∩ σ2. Then (*) ϕ→X (τ1 × τ2) = 〈〈ϕ → X (σ1 × σ2)〉〉 . Proof. To see that “⊃” holds in (*), note that σ1 × σ2 ⊂ τ1 × τ2, ϕ→X (σ1 × σ2) ⊂ ϕ → X (τ1 × τ2) , 〈〈ϕ→X (σ1 × σ2)〉〉⊂ ϕ → X (τ1 × τ2) . For “⊂” in (*), we first invoke the associativity of ⊗ and its infinite distribu- tivity over ∨ to write members of τ1, τ2 as joins of tensor products of members of σ1, σ2, respectively. More precisely, consider these typical members ∨ α∈A1   ⊗ β ∈B1 uαβ   , ∨ α∈A2   ⊗ β ∈B2 vαβ   of τ1, τ2, respectively, where A1, A2 are arbitrary indexing sets, B1, B2 are ar- bitrary finite indexing sets, each uαβ ∈ σ1, each vαβ ∈ σ2, and where W.L.O.G. we assume A1 ∩ A2 = ∅ = B1 ∩ B2. Next, we augment the uαβ ’s and vαβ ’s as follows, using the assumption that {⊥, e}⊂ σ1 ∩ σ2: α ∈ A1, β ∈ B2, uαβ ≡ e, α ∈ A2, β ∈ B1 ∪ B2, uαβ ≡⊥, α ∈ A2, β ∈ B1, vαβ ≡ e, α ∈ A1, β ∈ B1 ∪ B2, vαβ ≡⊥. Bitopology as topology 97 It follows that as maps from X to L that ∨ α∈A1 ∪A2   ⊗ β ∈B1 ∪B2 uαβ   = ∨ α∈A1   ⊗ β ∈B1 uαβ   , ∨ α∈A1 ∪A2   ⊗ β ∈B1 ∪B2 vαβ   = ∨ α∈A2   ⊗ β ∈B2 vαβ   . We thus have that a typical member   ∨ α∈A1   ⊗ β ∈B1 uαβ   , ∨ α∈A2   ⊗ β ∈B2 vαβ     of τ1 × τ2 may be rewritten as   ∨ α∈A1 ∪A2   ⊗ β ∈B1 ∪B2 uαβ   , ∨ α∈A1 ∪A2   ⊗ β ∈B1 ∪B2 vαβ     = ∨ α∈A1 ∪A2   ⊗ β ∈B1 ∪B2 (uαβ , vαβ )   , the latter being the form of a typical member of 〈〈σ1 × σ2〉〉 . To complete the proof of “⊂”, we invoke the fact that ϕ→X is an order-isomorphism preserving all tensor products (3.18(4)) to conclude that ϕ→X (τ1 × τ2) ⊂ ϕ → X 〈〈σ1 × σ2〉〉 = 〈〈ϕ → X (σ1 × σ2)〉〉 . � Proof of 3.29. Recall the categorical products in L-BiTop use the categorical product of L-Top in each slot as well as the usual projections for the morphisms of the product (Subsection 1.5), and let {(Xγ , (τ γ 1 , τ γ 2 ))}γ ∈Γ ⊂ |L-BiTop|. Because of the concreteness of E×, the validity of E×   ∏ γ ∈Γ (Xγ , (τ γ 1 , τ γ 2 )) ,{πγ}γ ∈Γ   =   ∏ γ ∈Γ E× (Xγ , (τ γ 1 , τ γ 2 )) ,{πγ}γ ∈Γ   holds if and only if we have the equality of topologies (**) ϕ→×γ ∈ ΓXγ (Πγ ∈Γ τ γ 1 × Πγ ∈Γ τ γ 2 ) = Πγ ∈Γ ϕ → Xγ (τ γ 1 × τ γ 2 ) , where “×” denotes as usual the direct product of us-quantales. For convenience, “LHS” and “RHS” respectively denote the left-hand side and right-hand side of (**). Let a subbasic open subset W be given from RHS. Then W may be written as follows: W = (πβ ) ← L ( ϕXβ ( t β 1 , t β 2 )) , 98 S. E. Rodabaugh where ( t β 1 , t β 2 ) ∈ τ β 1 × τ β 2 for a fixed index β ∈ Γ. Given {xγ}γ ∈Γ ∈×γ ∈ΓXγ , then W ( {xγ}γ ∈Γ ) = ϕXβ ( t β 1 , t β 2 )( πβ ( {xγ}γ ∈Γ )) = ϕXβ ( t β 1 , t β 2 ) (xβ ) = ( t β 1 (xβ ) , t β 2 (xβ ) ) = ([ (πβ ) ← L ( t β 1 )]( {xγ}γ ∈Γ ) , [ (πβ ) ← L ( t β 2 )]( {xγ}γ ∈Γ )) . This shows W is in LHS, LHS contains a subbasis of RHS, and so LHS contains RHS. For the reverse direction, let Z be in LHS. Then ∃ (u1, u2) ∈ Πγ ∈Γ τ γ 1 × Πγ ∈Γ τ γ 2 with Z = ϕ×γ ∈ ΓXγ (u1, u2) . Since the τ γ 1 ’s and τ γ 2 ’s contain {⊥, e} and since these L-subsets are preserved by the Zadeh preimage operators of all the projection maps, the usual subbasis for each of Πγ ∈Γ τ γ 1 and Πγ ∈Γ τ γ 2 contains {⊥, e}. Thus 3.30 applies to say it suffices to let u1, u2 be subbasic in their respective L-product topologies ∏ γ ∈Γ τ γ 1 , ∏ γ ∈Γ τ γ 2 ; so we may write u1 = (πα) ← L (tα1 ) , u2 = (πβ ) ← L ( t β 2 ) , where tα1 ∈ τ α 1 , t β 2 ∈ τ β 2 for fixed indices α, β ∈ Γ. Let {xγ}γ ∈Γ ∈ ×γ ∈ΓXγ . Then recalling that L has a unit e for ⊗ and that e is the corresponding unit for ⊗ lifted to LX , we have Z ( {xγ}γ ∈Γ ) = ϕ×γ ∈ ΓXγ (u1, u2) ( {xγ}γ ∈Γ ) = ( u1 ( {xγ}γ ∈Γ ) , u2 ( {xγ}γ ∈Γ )) = ( (πα) ← L (tα1 ) ( {xγ}γ ∈Γ ) , (πβ ) ← L ( t β 2 )( {xγ}γ ∈Γ )) = ( tα1 ( πα ( {xγ}γ ∈Γ )) , t β 2 ( πβ ( {xγ}γ ∈Γ ))) = ( tα1 (xα) , t β 2 (xβ ) ) = ( tα1 (xα) ⊗ e, e ⊗ t β 2 (xβ ) ) = (tα1 (xα) , e (xα)) ⊗ ( e (xβ ) , t β 2 (xβ ) ) = ( [(πα) ← L (ϕXα (t α 1 , e))]⊗ [ (πβ ) ← L ( ϕXβ ( e, t β 2 ))] ) ( {xγ}γ ∈Γ ) , the last line being the evaluation at {xγ}γ ∈Γ by a tensor of open subsets of RHS and hence of an open subset of RHS. Thus Z is in RHS, so LHS is contained in RHS, completing the proof of the theorem. 2 Lemma 3.31. For each us-quantale L, E× : L-BiTop → L 2-Top preserves equalizers. Bitopology as topology 99 Sublemma 3.32. Let L be a us-quantale, (X, τ, σ) ∈ |L-BiTop| , Z ⊂ X, and τ (Z) , σ (Z) , E× (τ, σ) (Z)be the L-subspace topologies on Z given by τ (Z) = { u |Z : u ∈ τ } , σ (Z) = { v |Z : v ∈ σ } , E× (τ, σ) (Z) = ϕ → X (τ × σ) (Z) (cf. [41]). Then E× (τ, σ) (Z) = E× (τ (Z) , σ (Z)) . Restated, E× respects subspace topologies. Proof. Let u ∈ τ, v ∈ σ, z ∈ Z. Then ϕX (u, v) |Z (z) = (u (z) , v (z)) = ( u |Z (z) , v |Z (z) ) = ϕX ( u |Z , v |Z ) (z) . This implies E× (τ, σ) (Z) = ϕ → X (τ × σ) (Z) = ϕ → X (τ (Z) × σ (Z)) = E× (τ (Z) , σ (Z)) . � Proof of 3.31. A categorical proof based upon the concreteness of E×, F and FπE× = IdL-BiTop (3.26) does not work since it would generally require that E×Fπ (τ ) ⊂ τ , which need not be true by (3.27(4)). It is necessary to look at the actual construction of equalizers in each of L-BiTop and L2-Top and show that E× carries the former into the latter. It can be checked that the equalizer of f, g : (X, τ1, τ2) ⇉ (Y, σ1, σ2) in L-BiTop is given by ((Z, τ1 (Z) , τ2 (Z)) , →֒) , where Z = {x ∈ X : f (x) = g (x)} , and that the equalizer of f, g : E× (X, τ1, τ2) ⇉ E× (Y, σ1, σ2) in L 2-Top is given by ((Z, E× (τ1, τ2) (Z)) , →֒) using the same Z. Because of the concrete- ness of E×, the issue is whether E× (τ1, τ2) (Z) is the same as E× (τ1 (Z) , τ2 (Z)), and this is settled in 3.32. 2 Corollary 3.33. For each u-quantale L, E× : L-BiTop → L 2-Top preserves all small limits. In particular, for each frame L, E× preserves all small limits. Proof. It is not difficult to show that L-BiTop is topological over Set w.r.t. the usual forgetful functor; and since Set is complete, it follows that L-BiTop is complete (Theorem 21.16 [1]). Conjoin 3.29 and 3.31 to get that E× preserves equalizers and (all) products; and then apply Proposition 13.4 [1] to finish the proof. � Lemma 3.34. For each u-quantale L, E× : L-BiTop → L 2-Top preserves all intersections. Proof. As in the proof of 3.31, it is necessary to look at the actual construction of intersections in each of L-BiTop and L2-Top and show that E× carries the former into the latter. Since this is trivially the case if the indexing class of the intersection is empty, we assume sequens that the indexing class is nonempty. 100 S. E. Rodabaugh To describe intersections in L-BiTop, let {((Xγ , τ γ 1 , τ γ 2 ) , mγ )}γ ∈Γ be a class of subobjects of (Y, σ1, σ2)—by the well-poweredness of L-BiTop (Subsection 1.5), this class is not proper, i.e., we may take Γ as a set; form the product ( (×γ ∈ΓXγ , Πγ ∈Γ τ γ 1 , Πγ ∈Γ τ γ 2 ) ,{πγ}γ ∈Γ ) of these subobjects in L-BiTop; let X ≡ { {xγ}γ ∈Γ : ∀β, δ ∈ Γ, mβ (xβ ) = mδ (xδ) } ⊂×γ ∈ΓXγ ; fix ζ ∈ Γ; and put m ≡ mζ ◦ πζ ◦ →֒ : X → Y . Then equipping X with the L-subspace topologies [Πγ ∈Γ τ γ 1 ] (X) , [Πγ ∈Γ τ γ 2 ] (X) , respectively, it can be shown that ((X, [Πγ ∈Γ τ γ 1 ] (X) , [Πγ ∈Γ τ γ 2 ] (X)) , m) is the required intersection in L-BiTop. We now consider in L2-Top the image {(E× (Xγ , τ γ 1 , τ γ 2 ) , mγ )}γ ∈Γ = {((Xγ , E× (τ γ 1 , τ γ 2 )) , mγ )}γ ∈Γ , under E× of the family {((Xγ , τ γ 1 , τ γ 2 ) , mγ )}γ ∈Γ , which image by the functo- riality of E× is a sink of subobjects for E× (Y, σ1, σ2). Using the X and m of the preceding paragraph, it can be shown that ((X, [Πγ ∈Γ E× (τ γ 1 , τ γ 2 )] (X)) , m) is the required intersection in L2-Top. To show that E× takes the L-BiTop intersection to the L 2-Top intersection, we note E× ([Πγ ∈Γ τ γ 1 ] (X) , [Πγ ∈Γ τ γ 2 ] (X)) = E× (Πγ ∈Γ τ γ 1 , Πγ ∈Γ τ γ 2 ) (X) (by 3.32) = [Πγ ∈Γ E× (τ γ 1 , τ γ 2 )] (X) (by proof of 3.29 (**)), which shows E× (X, [Πγ ∈Γ τ γ 1 ] (X) , [Πγ ∈Γ τ γ 2 ] (X)) = (X, [Πγ ∈Γ E× (τ γ 1 , τ γ 2 )] (X)) . � Theorem 3.35. For each u-quantale L, E× : L-BiTop → L 2-Top preserves all strong limits. Proof. This follows from 3.33, 3.34, and Definition 13.1(3) [1]. � Theorem 3.36. For each u-quantale L, E× : L-BiTop → L 2-Top has a left adjoint. Bitopology as topology 101 Proof. First, L-BiTop has small fibres and is a topological construct (proof of 3.33); hence, L-BiTop is complete and well-powered with coseparators by Corollary 21.17 [1]. Second, Proposition 12.5 [1] now gives L-BiTop is strongly complete. Third, since E× preserves all strong limits (3.35), the Special Adjoint Functor Theorem 18.17 [1] now implies E× is a right-adjoint. Finally, apply Proposition 18.9 [1]. � Proposition 3.37. For each us-quantale L, E× : L-BiTop → L 2-Top reflects and detects all limits and hence lifts all limits and is transportable. Proof. The details are straightfoward using the preservation of limits by Fπ, Fπ ◦ E× = IdL-BiTop, 3.36, and Proposition 13.34 [1]. � 3.4.4. Behavior of E× : L-BiTop → L 2-Top w.r.t. stratification issues. This subsubsection shows E× is essentially neutral w.r.t. stratification issues. Lemma 3.38. Let L be a us-quantale, (X, τ, σ) ∈ |L-BiTop|, and (γ, δ) ∈ L2. Then (γ, δ) ∈ E× (τ, σ) if and only if γ ∈ τ and δ ∈ σ. Proof. It is straightforward to check that (γ, δ) ∈ ϕ→X (τ × σ) ⇔ ∃u ∈ τ, ∃v ∈ σ, ∀x ∈ X, (u (x) , v (x)) = (γ, δ) ⇔ γ ∈ τ, δ ∈ σ. � Theorem 3.39. Let L be a us-quantale,(X, T) ∈ |Top| , (X, τ ) ∈ |L-Top| , and (X, τ, σ) ∈ |L-BiTop|. The following hold: (1) E× (X, τ, σ) always has (⊥,⊥), (⊥, e), (e,⊥), (e, e) as open subsets. (2) E× (X, τ, σ) is anti-stratified if and only if L is inconsistent. (3) For L = 2, E× (X, τ, σ)is weakly stratified. (4) E×Gχ (X, T) is weakly stratified for |L| = 2 and non-stratified for |L| > 2. (5) E× (X, τ, σ) is weakly stratified if and only if (X, τ, σ) is weakly strati- fied. (6) E× (X, τ, σ) is non-stratified if and only if (X, τ, σ) is non-stratified. (7) Statements (1–3, 5–6) with E× (X, τ, σ) replaced with E×Fd (X, τ ) and (X, τ, σ) replaced with (X, τ ). Proof. (1) follows from 3.38 given that {⊥, e}⊂ τ ∩ σ; (2, 3, 4) follow from (1) and the fact that 4 may be taken as precisely {(⊥,⊥) , (⊥, e) , (e,⊥) , (e, e)}; (5) follows from 3.38; (6) contraposes (5); and (7) is immediate from the other statements. � 4. Summary This paper surveys the relationship between (lattice-valued) bitopology and (lattice-valued) topology by examing a variety of functorial relationships —Ed, Fl, Fr, F∧, F∨, FΠ, E×, Fπ —when L is a us-quantale. From this overview 102 S. E. Rodabaugh of these functors and their properties, the following metamathematical conclu- sions emerge: (1) If it were assumed that the underlying lattice L of membership values is not allowed to change, then this survey would support the following viewpoint: (a) (lattice-valued) bitopology is strictly more general than (lattice- valued) topology in an extremely well-behaved way—justified by Ed; and (b) (lattice-valued) topology is not more general than (lattice-valued) bitopology—justified by Fl, Fr, F∧, F∨, FΠ in comparison with Ed, though the variety of ways in which bitopological spaces may be interpreted as topological spaces is rather striking. (2) If it were assumed that the underlying lattice L of membership values is allowed to change (e.g., to the direct s-quantalic product L2), then this survey would support the following viewpoint: (a) (lattice-valued) topology is strictly more general than (lattice- valued) bitopology in an extremely well-behaved way—justified by E×; and (b) (lattice-valued) bitopology is not more general than (lattice-valued) topology—justified by Fπ in comparison with E×, though Fπ is a rather interesting interpretation of topological spaces as bitopo- logical spaces. (3) This paper supports viewpoint (2) against viewpoint (1) for the follow- ing reasons: (a) We are in fact allowed to choose whatever underlying lattice of membership values we wish, so in fact the underlying assumption of (1) is false and the underlying assumption of (2) is true. The class of embeddings E× stands and must be reckoned with. (b) Topology (lattice-valued) is fundamentally simpler than bitopol- ogy (lattice-valued): (i) An L-bitopological space (X, τ, σ) adds to the ground object X three parameters—L, τ, σ; while an M -topological space (X, τ ) adds to the ground object X two parameters—M, τ . (ii) When passing (via E×) from the L-bitopological space (X, τ, σ) to the L2-topological space, the complexity of two topologies is isolated in the underlying lattice of membership values, leaving behind one topology. (c) Topology (lattice-valued) is strictly more general than bitopology (lattice-valued) in each of two ways: (i) For each L ∈ |USQuant| , the direct product L2 ∈ |USQuant| and L-BiTop embeds as a strict subcategory of L2-Top (via E×), which is extremely well-behaved if L ∈ |UQuant| . (ii) The class { L2-Top : L ∈ |USQuant| } Bitopology as topology 103 representing the field of fixed-basis bitopology using us-quantales is a strictly proper subclass of the class {L-Top : L ∈ |USQuant|} representing the field of fixed-basis topology using us-quantales (and not every us-quantale is a direct square of another us- quantale), and this strictness holds if the class is indexed by |UQuant| . (iii) Thus when one proves a theorem in fixed-basis topology, it is strictly more general w.r.t. coverage of categories and coverage of objects in each category in which bitopological spaces are embedded. (d) The upshot of (a, b, c) is that (lattice-valued) bitopology is cate- gorically redundant, particularly for underlying unital quantales: (lattice-valued) topology is fundamentally simpler and strictly more general. Fixed-basis bitopology is a complicated version of re- stricted subcategories of categories from a restricted class of cate- gories of fixed-basis topological spaces. For lattice-theoretic bases larger than 2, workers in lattice-valued bitopology should now be working in lattice-valued topology. (4) The above arguments apply to traditional bitopology in a more sub- tle way. On the one hand, traditional bitopology is isomorphic—in an extremely well-behaved way—to a strictly proper, extremely well- behaved subcategory of the much simpler 4-topology (BiTop embeds into 4-Top: 3.25 above); restated, traditional bitopology is a restricted subcase of a particular kind of fuzzy topology (namely 4-topology) and therefore traditional bitopology is categorically redundant vis-a-vis fixed-basis lattice-valued topology. On the other hand, the crisp lattice 2 underlying BiTop is so extremely simple that it is really a question of two topologies in BiTop vis-a-vis the lattice 4 and one topology in 4-Top; restated, moving from (X, T, S) to (X, E× (T, S)) means mov- ing from the parameters (2, T, S) to the parameters (4, E× (T, S)) , with the increased complexity in going from 2 to 4 offset by going from the two topologies T, S to the one 4-topology E× (T, S) , noting that each of T, S is more complex than 4. At the very least, workers in traditional bitopology should consider working in 4-topology. (5) The above arguments for redundancy in some sense are even stronger than those used in [16] to show that various versions of “intuitionistic” topologies or topologies comprising double subsets are redundant and a categorically special case of fixed-basis topology since the E×’s of this paper are strict embeddings and not functorial isomorphisms (when L is consistent) as in [16]. (6) The rich history and literature of traditional bitopology, including in- teresting separation and compactness axioms which “mix” together the two topologies, are now immediately part of the literature of 4-Top 104 S. E. Rodabaugh since the functorial embedding E×◦Gχ is an embedding at the power- set and fibre levels in which these axioms are formulated. The precise shape of these axioms as packaged by E×◦Gχ in 4-Top is, however, an open question. Answering this question may teach us how to use suc- cessful axioms of traditional bitopology to formulate successful axioms for fixed-basis topology. We illustrate (6) by showing that from traditional bicompactness E× in- duces the compactness of [5] for lattice-valued topology and by discussing the relationship between the respective Tihonov Theorems for the two categories BiTop and 4-Top. As repeatedly shown in [36, 37, 38, 42, 34], Chang’s original axiom of compactness [5] for lattice-valued topology, dubbed localic compact- ness in [38] and simply compactness in [19, 42], has been extraordinarily successful and justified with regard to classes of representations of L-spatial locales, L-coherent locales, distributive lattices, Boolean algebras, traditional compact Hausdorff spaces, classes of Stone-Čech compactifications, classes of Stone-Weierstraß theorems [42], etc; indeed, for L a frame, only this compact- ness axiom (and the very closely related axiom of [20]) has an unrestricted compactification reflector for all of L-Top. Further, its Tihonov Theorem, namely the Goguen-Tihonov Theorem [12], is one of the few Tihonov Theo- rems in the fuzzy literature which does not need the classical theorem in its proof; and hence it generalizes and explains both the statement and the proof of the classical theorem. We need the statement of this theorem. Let L be any complete lattice and let κ be a cardinal. We say ⊤ is κ-isolated [12] in L if for each A ⊂ L −{⊤} with |A| ≤ κ, ∨ A < ⊤. Theorem 4.1 (Goguen-Tihonov [12]). Let L be a complete lattice and Γ be an indexing set. Then ⊤ is |Γ|-isolated in L if and only if each collection {(Xγ , τγ ) : γ ∈ Γ} ⊂ L-Top of compact spaces (in the sense of [5]) yields a compact product ∏ γ ∈Γ (Xγ , τγ ). Corollary 4.2. The traditional Tihonov Theorem holds: for any indexing set Γ, ∏ γ ∈Γ (Xγ ,Tγ ) is compact if and only if each (Xγ ,Tγ ) is compact. Proof. The forward direction—the easier direction—can be given the usual proof. As for the backward direction—the harder direction, we proceed as fol- lows. First, the backward direction transfers directly, via the functorial isomor- phism Gχ : Top → 2-Top, to the claim that each collection {(Xγ , τγ ) : γ ∈ Γ}⊂ 2-Top of compact spaces (in the sense of [5]) yields a compact product ∏ γ ∈Γ (Xγ , τγ ); and this claim holds immediately from 4.1 since in the lat- tice 2, ⊤ is κ-isolated in 2 for each cardinal κ, and so the claim holds for each indexing set Γ. � A traditional bicompact bitopological space (X, T, S) is defined by saying that X is compact w.r.t. each of the topologies T, S. Given the construction of products in BiTop (Subsection 1.5), we immediately have the usual Tihonov Theorem for traditional bitopology. Bitopology as topology 105 Corollary 4.3. For any indexing set Γ, ∏ γ ∈Γ (Xγ , Tγ , Sγ ) is bicompact if and only if each (Xγ , Tγ , Sγ ) is bicompact. Corollary 4.4. Let Γ be an indexing set. Then each collection {(Xγ , τγ ) : γ ∈ Γ} ⊂ 4-Top of compact spaces (in the sense of [5]) yields a compact product ∏ γ ∈Γ (Xγ , τγ ) if and only if |Γ| = 0 or 1. Proof. Letting 4 be written as {⊥, a, b,⊤} with a, b unrelated, this is immediate from 4.1 since ⊤ is κ-isolated in 4 if and only if κ ≤ 1. � The plot thickens with the next definition, theorem, and corollary. Definition 4.5. Let L ∈ |USQuant| . An L-bitopological space (X, τ1, τ2) is (L-)bicompact if X is compact (in the sense of [5]) w.r.t. each of τ1 and τ2. Theorem 4.6. For each L ∈ |USQuant|, E× : L-BiTop → L 2-Top preserves bicompactness to compactness in the sense of [5]. Proof. Let a bicompact L-topological space (X, τ1, τ2) be given and let {uγ × vγ : γ ∈ Γ} be a cover of X from the L2-topology E× (τ1, τ2). If Γ is finite, then this cover is its own finite subcover; so we assume Γ is not finite. Now (⊤,⊤) = (⊤,⊤) = ∨ γ∈Γ (uγ × vγ ) = ∨ γ∈Γ uγ × ∨ γ∈Γ vγ , forcing each of {uγ : γ ∈ Γ} and {vγ : γ ∈ Γ} to be covers of X from τ1 and τ2, respectively. The bicompactness yields two finite subcovers which we may respectively write as follows: {ui : i = 1, ..., m} , {vi : i = m + 1, ..., m + n} . Then |Γ| ≥ m + n and m+n ∨ i=1 (ui × vi) = m+n ∨ i=1 ui × m+n ∨ i=1 vi ≥ m ∨ i=1 ui × m+n ∨ i=m+1 vi = ⊤×⊤ = (⊤,⊤), showing that {ui × vi : i = 1, ..., m + n} is the needed subcover of X. � Corollary 4.7. The functorial embedding E×◦Gχ : BiTop → 4-Top preserves bicompactness to compactness in the sense of [5]. Proof. Since Gχ : BiTop → 4-BiTop preserves traditional bicompactness to the bicompactness of 4.5, the corollary follows from 4.6. � We close this discussion of (6) above with a few comments. First, tradi- tional bicompactness mandates the compactness of [5] for lattice-valued topol- ogy (4.7). Second, we note (E×Gχ) → (BiTop) is isomorphic to BiTop and closed under all products (in 4-Top) (3.23, 3.29): this means that the cardi- nality unrestricted Tihonov Theorem for BiTop (4.3) transfers to a cardinal- ity unrestricted Tihonov Theorem for the subcategory (E×Gχ) → (BiTop) of 4-Top w.r.t. the compactness of [5]. Third, it now follows (4.4, 4.7) that E× 106 S. E. Rodabaugh is not object-onto (already known) and that the special cardinality restriction of the Goguen-Tihonov Theorem for 4-Top resides outside the subcategory (E×Gχ) → (BiTop). Acknowledgements. The referees are thanked for their thorough reading and helpful criticisms which significantly improved this paper. The author is especially grateful to the referee who found an important error in the original submission following Corollary 4.4, the correction of which sheds light on the topological properties of the E× functor. References [1] J. Adámek, H. Herrlich, G. E. Strecker, Abstract And Concrete Categories: The Joy Of Cats, Wiley Interscience Pure and Applied Mathematics (John Wiley & Sons, Bris- bane/Chicester/New York/Singapore/Toronto, 1990). [2] B. Banaschewski, G. C. L. Brümmer, K. A. Hardie, Biframes and bispaces, Proc. Symp. Categorical Algebra and Topology (Cape Town, 1981), Quaestiones Mathematicae 6 (1983), 13–25. [3] J. Cerf, Groupes d’homotopie locaux et groupes d’homotopie mixtes des espaces bitopologiques: Définitions et propriétés, C. R. Acad. Sci. Paris 252 (1961) 4093–4095. [4] J. Cerf, Groupes d’homotopie locaux et groupes d’homotopie mixtes des espaces bitopologiques: Presque n-locale connexion: Applications, C. R. Acad. Sci. Paris 253 (1961) 363–365. [5] C. L. Chang, Fuzzy topological spaces, J. Math. Anal. Appl. 24 (1968), 182–190. [6] C. De Mitri, C. Guido, G-fuzzy topological spaces and subspaces, Suppl. Rend. Circolo Matem. Palermo 29 (1992), 363–383. [7] C. De Mitri, C. Guido, Some remarks on fuzzy powerset operators, Fuzzy Sets and Systems 126 (2002), 241–251. [8] C. De Mitri, C. Guido, R. E. Toma, Fuzzy topological properties and hereditariness, Fuzzy Sets and Systems 138 (2003), 127–147. [9] J. T. Denniston, S. E. Rodabaugh, Functorial relationships between lattice-valued topol- ogy and topological systems, in submission. [10] A. Frascella, C. Guido, Structural lattices and ground categories of L-sets, in [24], 53–54. [11] A. Frascella, C. Guido, Topological categories of L-sets and (L, M)-topological spaces on structured lattices; in [13], 50. [12] J. A. Goguen, The fuzzy Tychonoff theorem, J. Math. Anal. Appl. 43 (1973), 734–742. [13] S. Gottwald, P. Hájek, U. Höhle, E. P. Klement, eds, Fuzzy Logics And Related Struc- tures: Abstracts, 26th Linz Seminar On Fuzzy Set Theory, February 2005, Bildungszen- trum St. Magdalena, Linz, Austria, (Universitätsdirektion Johannes Kepler Universtät, A-4040, Linz, 2005). [14] C. Guido, The subspace problem in the traditional point set context of fuzzy topology, in [26], 351–372. [15] C. Guido, Powerset operators based approach to fuzzy topologies on fuzzy sets, Chapter 15 in [47], 401–413. [16] J. Gutiérrez Garćıa, S. E. Rodabaugh, Order-theoretic, topological, categorical redun- dancies of interval-valued sets, grey sets, vague sets, interval-valued “intuitionistic” sets, “intuitionistic” fuzzy sets and topologies, Fuzzy Sets and Systems 156 (2005), 445–484. Bitopology as topology 107 [17] U. Höhle, Many Valued Topology And Its Applications to Fuzzy Subsets, (Kluwer Aca- demic Publishers, Boston/Dordrecht/London, 2001). [18] U. Höhle, E. P. Klement, eds, Nonclassical Logics And Their Applications, Theory and Decision Library—Series B: Mathematical and Statistical Methods, Volume 32 (Kluwer Academic Publishers, Boston/Dordrecht/London, 1995). [19] U. Höhle, S. E. Rodabaugh, eds, Mathematics Of Fuzzy Sets: Logic, Topology, And Measure Theory, The Handbooks of Fuzzy Sets Series, Volume 3 (Kluwer Academic Publishers, Boston/Dordrecht/London, 1999). [20] U. Höhle, A. Šostak, Axiomatic foundations of fixed-basis fuzzy topology, Chapter 3 in [19], 123–272. [21] P. T. Johnstone, Stone Spaces, (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1982). [22] J. C. Kelly, Bitopological spaces, Proc. London Math. Soc. 13:3 (1963), 71–89. [23] E. P. Klement, R. Mesiar, E. Pap, Triangular Norms, Trends in Logic, Studia Logica Library, Volume 8 (Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrecht/Boston/London, 2000). [24] E. P. Klement, E. Pap, eds, Mathematics of Fuzzy Systems: Abstracts, 25th Linz Seminar On Fuzzy Set Theory, February 2004, Bildungszentrum St. Magdalena, Linz, Austria (Universitätsdirektion of Johannes Kepler Universität, A-4040, Linz, 2004). [25] R. Kopperman, J. D. Lawson, Bitopological and topological ordered k-spaces, Topology and its Applications 146–147 (2005), 385–396. [26] W. Kotzé, ed, Special Issue, Quaestiones Mathematicae 20(3) (1997). [27] S. S. Kumar, Weakly continuous mappings in fuzzy bitopological spaces, Proc. First Tamilnadu Science Congress Tiruchirappalli (1992), 1–7. [28] S. Mac Lane, Categories for the Working Mathematician (Springer-Verlag, Berlin), 1971. [29] MathSciNet: Mathematical Reviews On The Web, database under “Anywhere = bitopolog***”, 2006. [30] M. E. Abd El-Monsef, A. E. Ramadan, α-Compactness in bifuzzy topological spaces, Fuzzy Sets and Systems 30 (1989), 165–173. [31] L. Motchane, Sur la notion d’espace bitopologique et sur les espaces de Baire, C. R. Acad. Sci. Paris 244(1957), 3121–3124. [32] L. Motchane, Sur la caractérisation des espaces de Baire, C. R. Acad. Sci. Paris 246 (1958), 215–218. [33] C. J. Mulvey, M. Nawaz, Quantales: quantal sets, Chapter VII in [18], 159–217. [34] A. Pultr, S. E. Rodabaugh, Lattice-valued frames, functor categories, and classes of sober spaces, Chapter 6 in [47], pp. 153–187. [35] A. Pultr, S. E. Rodabaugh, Category theoretic properties of chain-valued frames: Part I: categorical and presheaf theoretic foundations, Fuzzy Sets and Systems, to appear; Category theoretic properties of chain-valued frames: Part II: applications to lattice- valued topology, Fuzzy Sets and Systems, to appear. [36] S. E. Rodabaugh, Point-set lattice-theoretic topology, Fuzzy Sets and Systems 40 (1991), 297–345. [37] S. E. Rodabaugh, Categorical frameworks for Stone representation theorems, Chapter 7 in [48], 178-231. [38] S. E. Rodabaugh, Applications of localic separation axioms, compactness axioms, rep- resentations, and compactifications to poslat topological spaces, Fuzzy Sets and Systems 73 (1995), 55–87. [39] S. E. Rodabaugh, Powerset operator based foundation for point-set lattice-theoretic (poslat) fuzzy set theories and topologies, in [26], 463–530. [40] S. E. Rodabaugh, Powerset operator foundations for poslat fuzzy set theories and topolo- gies, Chapter 2 in [19], 91–116. [41] S. E. Rodabaugh, Categorical foundations of variable-basis fuzzy topology, Chapter 4 in [19], 273–388. [42] S. E. Rodabaugh, Separation axioms: representation theorems, compactness, and com- pactifications, Chapter 7 in [19], 481–552. 108 S. E. Rodabaugh [43] S. E. Rodabaugh, Fuzzy real lines and dual real lines as poslat topological, uniform, and metric ordered semirings with unity, Chapter 10 in [19], 607–631. [44] S. E. Rodabaugh, Axiomatic foundations for uniform operator quasi-uniformities, Chapter 7 in [47], 199–233. [45] S. E. Rodabaugh, Relationship of algebraic theories to powersets over objects in Set and Set × C, to appear. [46] S. E. Rodabaugh, Relationship of algebraic theories to powerset theories and fuzzy topological theories for lattice-valued mathematics, International Journal of Mathe- matics and the Mathematical Sciences, 2007 (3) (2007), Article ID 43645, 71 pages. doi:10.1155/2007/43645. http://www.hindawi.com/getarticle.aspx?doi=10.1155/2007/43645. [47] S. E. Rodabaugh, E. P. Klement, eds, Topological And Algebraic Structures In Fuzzy Sets: A Handbook of Recent Developments in the Mathematics of Fuzzy Sets, Trends in Logic 20 (Kluwer Academic Publishers, Boston/Dordrecht/London, 2003). [48] S. E. Rodabaugh, E. P. Klement, U. Höhle, eds, Application Of Category Theory To Fuzzy Sets, Theory and Decision Library—Series B: Mathematical and Statistical Meth- ods 14 (Kluwer Academic Publishers (Boston/Dordrecht/London, 1992). [49] K. I. Rosenthal, Quantales And Their Applications, Pitman Research Notes In Mathe- matics 234 (Longman, Burnt Mill, Harlow, 1990). [50] A. S. M. Abu Safiya, A. A. Fora, M. W. Warner, Compactness and weakly induced fuzzy bitopological spaces, Fuzzy Sets and Systems 62( 1994), 89–96. [51] R. Srivastava, M. Srivastava, On compactness in bifuzzy topological spaces, Fuzzy Sets and Systems 121 (2001), 285–292. [52] C. K. Wong, Fuzzy topology: product and quotient theorems, J. Math. Anal. Appl. 45 (1974), 512–521. [53] L. A. Zadeh, Fuzzy sets, Information and Control 8 (1965), 338–353. Received October 2006 Accepted April 2007 S. E. Rodabaugh (rodabaug@math.ysu.edu) Department of Mathematics and Statistics, Youngstown State University, Youngstown, Ohio 44555-3609, USA