@ Applied General Topology c© Universidad Politécnica de Valencia Volume 4, No. 2, 2003 pp. 217–221 Transitivity of hereditarily metacompact spaces Hans-Peter A. Künzi ∗ Dedicated to Professor S. Naimpally on the occasion of his 70th birthday. Abstract. We prove that each regular hereditarily metacompact (monotonic) β-space has the property that the third power of any neigh- bornet belongs to its point-finite quasi-uniformity. 2000 AMS Classification: 54E15, 54D20, 54E18, 54E25. Keywords: point-finite quasi-uniformity, transitive quasi-uniformity, transi- tive topological space, β-space, monotonic β-space, hereditarily metacompact, Choquet game. 1. Introduction. Junnila [6, Corollary 4.13] showed (see also [4, Theorem 6.21]) that in a semistratifiable metacompact space the third power of each neighbornet belongs to the point-finite quasi-uniformity. Similarly, in [7] it was proved that each regular hereditarily metacompact compact space possesses the latter property. Junnila’s result and the techniques used in [7] suggested that it should be possible to generalize the latter result beyond (local) compactness using meth- ods known from the theory of monotonic properties (compare [2]). In this note we verify this conjecture by presenting a proof which shows that each regular hereditarily metacompact (monotonic) β-space satisfies the condition that the third power of any neighbornet belongs to its point-finite quasi-uniformity. Recall that a topological space is called transitive (see e.g. [4]) provided that its finest compatible quasi-uniformity has a base consisting of transitive entourages. Hence in particular our result implies that each regular hereditarily metacompact (monotonic) β-space is transitive. For basic facts about quasi-uniformities we refer the reader to [4]. ∗The author acknowledges support by the Swiss National Science Foundation (under grant 20-63402.00) during stays at theUniversity of Berne, Switzerland. 218 H.-P.A. Künzi 2. Main result. Let us first mention some pertinent definitions and recall a few well-known facts. A regular topological space X is said to be a monotonic β-space [1] if, for each point x ∈ X, there exists a decreasing sequence 〈Bn(x)〉n∈ω of open neighborhood bases of X at the point x such that if Bn ∈ Bn(xn) and Bn+1 ⊆ Bn whenever n ∈ ω and if ⋂ n∈ω Bn is nonempty, then the sequence 〈xn〉n∈ω has a cluster point. The family {〈Bn(x)〉n∈ω : x ∈ X} is called a monotonic β-system of X. The following results are known to hold (in the class of regular (T1-)spaces): Each β-space is a monotonic β-space. Every monotonic p-space is a monotonic β-space [1, Proposition 1.7]. Furthermore, every submetacompact monotonic p-space is a p-space [2, Theorem 2.8(b)]. Recall also that each submetacompact space is a p-space if and only if it is a w∆-space [5, Theorem 3.19]. We shall find it convenient to work with the following class of (regular) topological spaces X that is defined in terms of a game G(X) in X, which is a modification of certain games introduced in [3] and was suggested to us by Prof. J. Chaber. The game G(X) is similar to the strong game of Choquet. Player I starts the game by choosing a nonempty open set V0 and a point x0 ∈ V0. After player I has chosen his nonempty open set Vn and xn ∈ Vn in his nth move where n ∈ ω, player II replies with an open set Wn ⊆ Vn containing xn and player I, in the next move, has to pick Vn+1 inside Wn. Player II wins if either ∩n∈ωWn = ∅ or the sequence 〈xn〉n∈ω has a cluster point in X. A winning strategy for player II is a function s into the topology of X defined on all finite sequences of moves of player I so that player II always wins when using the function s to determine his next move. It is readily seen that for each (regular) monotonic β-space X, player II has a winning strategy for the game G(X). Indeed in his nth move he will choose as Wn some (fixed) member of Bn(xn) contained in Vn. A scattered partition (see e.g. [8, Definition 2.4]) of a topological space X is a cover {Lα : α < γ} of X by pairwise disjoint sets such that the set Sβ = ⋃ {Lα : α < β} is open for each β ≤ γ. A binary relation N on a topological space X is called a neighbornet of X if N(x) = {y ∈ X : (x,y) ∈ N} is a neighborhood at x whenever x ∈ X. For any interior-preserving open cover C of a topological space X, we define the neighbornet DC of X by setting DC(x) = ⋂ {C ∈ C : x ∈ C} whenever x ∈ X. We recall that the filter on X ×X generated by the subbase {DC : C is a point-finite open cover of X} is called the point-finite quasi-uniformity of X (see e.g. [4]). Lemma 2.1. Suppose that X is a hereditarily metacompact space and let O be a neighbornet of X such that O(x) is open whenever x ∈ X. Then there is a point-finite open cover G(X) of X such that for each member H ∈G(X) there is xH ∈ X such that xH ∈ H ⊆ O(xH). Proof. Choose inductively a possibly transfinite sequence 〈xα〉α of points in X such that xα ∈ X\ ⋃ β<α O(xβ) as long as possible, say whenever α < γ. Then Transitivity 219 {O(xα) \ ⋃ β<α O(xβ) : α < γ} is a scattered partition of X. According to [8, Theorem 6.3] a topological space X is hereditarily metacompact if and only if every scattered partition of X has a point-finite open expansion. Hence there is a point-finite open collection {Pα : α < γ} of X such that [O(xα) \ ⋃ β<α O(xβ)] ⊆ Pα whenever α < γ. It follows that ⋃ {Pα ∩ O(xα) : α < γ} = X and xα ∈ Pα∩O(xα) ⊆ O(xα) whenever α < γ. Therefore we can set G(X) = {Pα ∩O(xα) : α < γ}. � Theorem 2.2. Let O be a neighbornet of a regular hereditarily metacompact space X. If player II has a winning strategy in the game G(X) described above, then there exists a point-finite open family U of X such that DU ⊆ O3. Proof. Without loss of generality we suppose that O(x) is open whenever x ∈ X. Inductively for each n ∈ ω we shall define a point-finite open family Un of X. By Lemma 2.1 there is a point-finite open cover U0 of X which has the property that for each U0 ∈ U0 there is some point pU0 ∈ X such that pU0 ∈ U0 ⊆ O(pU0 ). Let n ∈ ω. Suppose that we have defined the point-finite open family Uk+1 as the union of families Gk+1(U) where U runs through a subfamily of Uk whenever k < n. (In the following we distinguish between members in different families Gk+1(U) or in U0 that denote the same set; in this way each member arises on a well-defined level of the construction and each member V belonging to the level Uk+1 has a unique element U in the level Uk preceding it in the sense that V ∈Gk+1(U).) Furthermore suppose that each Un where Uk+1 ∈Gk+1(Uk) whenever k < n determines the sequence (U0 \ O−1(pU0 ),pU1,W0,U1 \ O−1(pU1 ),pU2,W1, . . . , Un−1 \ O−1(pUn−1 ),pUn,Wn−1) which describes the moves k < n of a well- defined instance of the game G(X) in the sense that (1) player I has used Uk \ O−1(pUk) and some well-defined point pUk+1 of Uk \O−1(pUk) in his k th-move whenever k < n, and (2) player II has chosen the set Wk according to his winning strategy in his kth move whenever k < n. In particular note that each Wk is determined by the preceding moves of player I and that each Uk \O−1(pUk) 6= ∅ whenever k < n. Call a member Un of Un suitable (in Un) if Un 6⊆ O−1(pUn). Assume now that Un is a suitable member of Un. Suppose that player I continues the beginning of the game G(X) associated with Un by choosing Un\O−1(pUn) and any x ∈ Un\O−1(pUn) in his nth move. Then player II finds Wn(. . . ,Un,x) according to his winning strategy such that x ∈ Wn(. . . ,Un,x) ⊆ Un \O−1(pUn). By hereditary metacompactness and regularity of X there exists a point- finite open cover Vn+1(Un) of Un\O−1(pUn) such that the closures of its mem- bers are all contained in Un \O−1(pUn). Consider the neighbornet of the sub- space Un \O−1(pUn) of X determined by the neighborhoods Wn(. . . ,Un,x) ∩ 220 H.-P.A. Künzi⋂ {E ∈ Vn+1(Un) : x ∈ E}∩ O(x) whenever x ∈ Un \ O−1(pUn). By Lemma 2.1 there exists a point-finite open cover Gn+1(Un) of Un \O−1(pUn) such that for each Un+1 ∈ Gn+1(Un) there is some point pUn+1 ∈ Un \ O−1(pUn) sat- isfying pUn+1 ∈ Un+1 ⊆ Wn(. . . ,Un,pUn+1 ) ∩ ⋂ {E ∈ Vn+1(Un) : pUn+1 ∈ E}∩O(pUn+1 ). Set Un+1 = ⋃ {Gn+1(Un) : Un is a suitable member of Un}. Note that Un+1 is a point-finite open family of X. Observe also that for each suitable Un of Un the closures of all members of Gn+1(Un) are contained in Un \ O−1(pUn) because Vn+1(Un) had the latter property. Furthermore by the construction above it is readily checked that for each member Un+1 ∈ Gn+1(Un) we have constructed the moves k < n + 1 of the instance of the game G(X) associated with Un+1 by adding to the (unique) sequence of moves associated with Un the nth moves (Un\O−1(pUn),pUn+1,Wn) of player I and player II, respectively, where Wn = Wn(. . . ,Un,pUn+1 ). Claim 2.3. There exists a point-finite family U of open sets of X such that the family H = {U ∩O−1(pU ) : U ∈U} covers X. We shall show that our claim holds for the family U = ⋃ n∈ω Un: Suppose that for some x ∈ X there are infinitely many sets in U containing x. Consider the family S of all sets in U containing x. Since each family Un is point-finite, we conclude by König’s Lemma [9] and the definition of the families Un+1 that in S there exists a sequence 〈Un〉n∈ω such that for each n ∈ ω, Un+1 ∈ Gn+1(Un). We shall show next that such a sequence does not exist. Note first that the sequence 〈Un \O−1(pUn),pUn+1〉n∈ω yields the moves of player I in an instance of the game G(X) where player II uses his winning strategy to find the sets Wn = Wn(. . . ,Un,pUn+1 ) whenever n ∈ ω. By the construction of the family Gn+1(Un), Un+1 ⊆ Un+1 ⊆ Un\O−1(pUn) and pUn+1 ∈ Un+1 ⊆ Wn(. . . ,Un,pUn+1 ) ⊆ Un \O−1(pUn) whenever n ∈ ω. Since x ∈ ∩n∈ωUn and thus x ∈ ∩n∈ωWn(. . . ,Un,pUn+1 ), we conclude that 〈pUn〉n∈ω has a cluster point z in X. Thus pUn ∈ O(z) for infinitely many n ∈ ω. But also z ∈ Un+1 whenever n ∈ ω, because for each n ∈ ω a tail of the sequence 〈pUn〉n∈ω is contained in Un+1. Since Un+1 ∩ O−1(pUn) = ∅ whenever n ∈ ω, we see that z 6∈ O−1(pUn) whenever n ∈ ω —a contradiction. We conclude that the family U is point-finite. Suppose that some point x ∈ X is not contained in any set U ∩ O−1(pU ) where U ∈ U. Since U0 is a cover of X, there exists U0 ∈ U0 such that x ∈ U0. Suppose that n ∈ ω and sets Uk (k ≤ n) have inductively been defined such that x ∈ Uk+1 ∈ Gk+1(Uk) (k < n). By our assumption, we have that x ∈ Un \ O−1(pUn). In particular, Un is suitable in Un. Since Gn+1(Un) covers Un\O−1(pUn), there exists Un+1 ∈Gn+1(Un) such that x ∈ Un+1. This concludes the induction. Of course, x ∈ ∩n∈ωUn. But as we just noted above such a sequence 〈Un〉n∈ω cannot exist. Hence H is a cover of X. Transitivity 221 Finally we show that DU ⊆ O3. Let x ∈ X. By the claim verified above there exists U ∈ U such that x ∈ U ∩ O−1(pU ). Furthermore, we see that DU(x) = ⋂ {V ∈ U : x ∈ V} ⊆ U ⊆ O(pU ) by the selection of the sets U belonging to U. Since we have that x ∈ O−1(pU ), there exists a point y ∈ O(x) ∩ O−1(pU ). We now conclude that y ∈ O(x) and pU ∈ O(y). It follows that pU ∈ O2(x) and, furthermore, that O(pU ) ⊆ O3(x). As a consequence, we see that DU(x) ⊆ O(pU ) ⊆ O3(x), which confirms the assertion. � Acknowledgements. We would like to thank Prof. J. Chaber for sugges- tions that led to several improvements of this note. References [1] J. Chaber, On point-countable collections and monotonic properties, Fund. Math. 94 (1977), 209–219. [2] J. Chaber, M.M. Čoban and K. Nagami, On monotonic generalizations of Moore spaces, Čech complete spaces and p-spaces, Fund. Math. 84 (1974), 107–119. [3] J. Chaber and R. Pol, On hereditarily Baire spaces and σ-fragmentability of mappings and Namioka property, preprint. [4] P. Fletcher and W.F. Lindgren, Quasi-uniform Spaces, Lecture Notes Pure Appl. Math. 77, Dekker, New York, 1982. [5] G. Gruenhage, Generalized metric spaces, in: Handbook of Set-theoretic Topology, K. Kunen and J.E. Vaughan, eds., North-Holland Amsterdam, 1984, pp. 423–501. [6] H.J.K. Junnila, Neighbornets, Pacific J. Math. 76 (1978), 83–108. [7] H.J.K. Junnila, H.P.A. Künzi and S. Watson, On a class of hereditarily paracompact spaces, Topology Proc. 25 Summer (2000), 271–289; Russian translation in: Fundam. Prikl. Mat. 4 (1998), 141–154. [8] H.J.K. Junnila, J.C. Smith and R. Telgársky, Closure-preserving covers by small sets, Topology Appl. 23 (1986), 237–262. [9] D. König, Sur les correspondances multivoques des ensembles, Fund. Math. 8 (1926), 114–134. Received September 2001 Revised July 2002 Hans-Peter A. Künzi Dept. Math. and Appl. Math., University of Cape Town, Rondebosch 7701, South Africa E-mail address : kunzi@maths.uct.ac.za