@ Applied General Topology c© Universidad Politécnica de Valencia Volume 4, No. 2, 2003 pp. 289–299 A better framework for first countable spaces Gerhard Preuß Dedicated to Professor S. Naimpally on the occasion of his 70th birthday. Abstract. In the realm of semiuniform convergence spaces first countability is divisible and leads to a well-behaved topological con- struct with natural function spaces and one-point extensions such that countable products of quotients are quotients. Every semiuniform con- vergence space (e.g. symmetric topological space, uniform space, filter space, etc.) has an underlying first countable space. Several applica- tions of first countability in a broader context than the usual one of topological spaces are studied. 2000 AMS Classification: 54A05, 54C35, 54D55, 54E15, 18A40, 18D15. Keywords: first axiom of countability, second axiom of countability, countably compact, sequentially compact, sequentially complete, continuous convergence, sequentially continuous, semiuniform convergence spaces, convergence spaces, filter spaces, topological spaces, uniform spaces, bicoreflective subconstruct, cartesian closedness. 1. Introduction. Recently, the author ([4],[5]) has shown that a topologist’s life is easier in Convenient Topology, where mainly the topological construct SUConv of semiuniform convergence spaces is considered. In SUConv, topological and uniform concepts are available and fundamental constructions can be easily described. In the realm of topological spaces the first axiom of countability plays an essential role whenever sequences are prefered rather than filters (e.g. in Analysis). Unfortunately, quotients of first countable topological spaces need not be first countable. This situation can be improved in the framework of semiuniform convergence spaces: First countability is divisible. Since first countability is also summable, this implies that the construct FC-SUConv of first countable semiuniform convergence spaces is bicoreflective in SUConv, i.e. every semiuniform convergence space has an underlying first countable 290 Gerhard Preuß space. Another consequence is the following: FC-SUConv is a topological universe (= cartesian closed and extensional topological construct) such that countable products of quotients are quotients. Not only first countable (symmetric) topological spaces, but also uniform spaces with a countable base, i.e. pseudometrizable uniform spaces, are first countable (as semiuniform convergence spaces). For uniform spaces, there is no difference between the first and the second axiom of countability, when these axioms are generalized to semiuniform convergence spaces. The applications of first countability, studied here, cover the following themes: 1. The definition of the closure of a subset by means of sequences. 2. The definition of completeness by means of sequences. 3. The equivalence of countable compactness and sequential compactness. 4. The definition of continuous convergence by means of sequences. 5. The definition of continuity by means of sequences. 2. Preliminaries. Definition 2.1. 1) A semiuniform convergence space is a pair (X, JX), where X is a set and JX a set of filters on X×X such that the following are satisfied: UC1) The filter ẋ× ẋ, generated by {(x,x)}, belongs to JX for each x ∈ X, UC2) G ∈ JX, whenever F ∈ JX and F ⊂ G, UC3) F ∈ JX implies F−1 = {F−1 : F ∈ F} ∈ JX, where F−1 = {(y,x) : (x,y) ∈ F}. If (X, JX) is a semiuniform convergence space, then the elements of JX are called uniform filters. 2) A map f : (X, JX) → (Y, JY ) between semiuniform convergence spaces is called uniformly continuous provided that (f ×f)(F) ∈ JY for each F ∈ JX. 3) The construct of semiuniform convergence spaces (and uniformly contin- uous maps) is denoted by SUConv. Remark 2.2. SUConv is a topological construct, where initial and final struc- tures have an easy description: If X is a set, ((Xi, JXi))i∈I a family of semiuniform convergence spaces and (fi : X → Xi)i∈I (resp. (fi : Xi → X)i∈I) a family of maps, then JX = {F ∈ F(X × X) : (fi × fi)(F) ∈ JXi for each i ∈ I} (resp. JX = {F ∈ F(X ×X): there is some i ∈ I and some Fi ∈ JXi with (fi ×fi)(Fi) ⊂ F}∪{ẋ× ẋ : x ∈ X}) is the initial (resp. final ) SUConv-structure w.r.t. the given data, where F(X ×X) denotes the set of all filters on X ×X. Example 2.3. 1) Let (X, X) be a (symmetric) topological space. Then its corresponding semiuniform convergence space (X, JγqX ) is defined by F ∈ JγqX iff there is some x ∈ X such that F ⊃ UX(x)×UX(x), where UX(x) denotes the neighborhood filter of x in (X, X). A better framework for first countable spaces 291 2) Let (X, W) be a uniform space. Then its corresponding semiuniform convergence space (X, [W]) is defined by F ∈ [W] iff F ⊃ W. 3) Let X = (X, JX) and Y = (Y, JY ) be semiuniform convergence spaces. Then there is a coarsest SUConv-structure JX,Y on the set [X, Y] of all uniformly continuous maps from X into Y such that the evaluation map eX,Y : X × ([X, Y], JX,Y ) → Y (defined by eX,Y (x,f) = f(x)) is uniformly continuous. It is defined by Φ ∈ JX,Y iff Φ(F) ∈ JY for each F ∈ JX (Φ(F) denotes the filter generated by {A(F) : A ∈ Φ and F ∈ F} with A(F) = {(f(x),g(y)) : (f,g) ∈ A and (x,y) ∈ F}). ([X, Y], JX,Y ) is called a natural function space. 4) Let X = (X, JX) be a semiuniform convergence space. Let X* = X ∪ {∞X} with ∞X /∈ X and JX* = {H ∈ F(X* ×X*): the trace of H on X ×X exists and belongs to JX or the trace on X ×X does not exist}. Then (X*, JX*) is called a one-point extension of (X, JX). Obviously, JX* is the coarsest SUConv-structure on X* such that (X, JX) is a subspace of (X*, JX*). Remark 2.4. 1) The existence of one-point extensions implies that quotients are hereditary, i.e. if f : X → Y is a quotient map in SUConv, then for every Z ⊂ Y , the map f | f−1[Z] : f−1[Z] → Z is again a quotient map. 2) Concerning the definitions of (symmetric) Kent convergence spaces and filter spaces, and their relations to semiuniform convergence spaces, see [4] (or [5]). 3. First countable spaces. Definition 3.1. 1) A semiuniform convergence space (X, JX) is said to fulfill the first axiom of countability or to be first countable iff each uniform filter has a uniform subfilter with a countable base. 2) A filter space (X,γ) is called first countable provided that each F ∈ γ has a subfilter G ∈ γ with a countable base. 3) A Kent convergence space (X,q) is first countable iff for each (F,x) ∈ q, there is some (G,x) ∈ q such that G is a subfilter of F with a countable base. Proposition 3.2. Let (X, JX) be a semiuniform convergence space fulfilling the first axiom of countability. Then the underlying filter space (X,γJX ) is first countable. Proof. Let F ∈ γJX . Then F×F ∈ JX and by assumption there is some G ∈ JX with a countable base B = {B1,B2, . . . ,Bn . . .} such that G ⊂ F × F. Thus, for each n ∈ N = {1, 2, . . .}, there exists some Fn ∈ F with Fn × Fn ⊂ Bn . Obviously, the finite intersections of elements of {Fn : n ∈ N} form a countable base of some subfilter H of F. Since G ⊂ H × H , it follows that H × H belongs to JX, i.e. H ∈ γJX . � 292 Gerhard Preuß Proposition 3.3. Let (X,γ) be a filter space and (X, Jγ) its corresponding semiuniform convergence space. Then (X, Jγ) is first countable iff (X,γ) is first countable in the sense of 3.1.2). Proof. “⇒”. This follows immediately from 3.2, since γ = γJγ . “⇐”. Let F ∈ Jγ. Then there is some G ∈ γ with G×G ⊂ F. Furthermore, there is some H ∈ γ with a countable base B such that H ⊂ G. Consequently, H × H ⊂ G × G ⊂ F, where H × H ∈ Jγ has a countable base, namely {B ×B : B ∈ B}. � Proposition 3.4. Let (X,γ) be a first countable filter space. Then the under- lying (symmetric) Kent convergence space (X,qγ) is also first countable. Proposition 3.5. Let (X,q) be a symmetric Kent convergence space and (X, Jγq ) its corresponding semiuniform convergence space. Then (X, Jγq ) is first countable iff (X,q) is first countable in the sense of 3.1 3). Proof. “⇒”. Since γJγq = γq and qγq = q, (X,q) is first countable by means of the above propositions. “⇐”. Let F ∈ Jγq . Then there is some (G,x) ∈ q such that G × G ⊂ F. By assumption, there exists (H,x) ∈ q such that H is a subfilter of G with a countable base B. Hence, H × H ⊂ F, where H × H ∈ Jγq has the countable base {B ×B : B ∈ B}. � Corollary 3.6. The underlying (symmetric) Kent convergence space (X,qγJX ) of a first countable semiuniform convergence space (X, JX) is first countable. Proof. Apply 3.2 and 3.4. � Corollary 3.7. Let (X, X) be a symmetric topological space (=R0-space) and define qX ⊂ F(X) × X by (F,x) ∈ qX iff F ⊃ UX(x). Then the following are equivalent: (1) (X, X) is first countable in the usual sense, i.e. for each x ∈ X, UX(x) has a countable base. (2) (X, X) is first countable as a semiuniform convergence space, i.e. (X, JγqX ) is first countable. (3) (X, X) is first countable as a Kent convergence space, i.e. (X,qX) is first countable in the sense of 3.1.3). Proof. (1) ⇒ (2). Let F ∈ JγqX . Then there is some x ∈ X such that UX(x) × UX(x) ⊂ F. Since, by assumption, UX(x) has a countable base, the subfilter UX(x) × UX(x) of F has also a countable base and belongs to JγqX . (2) ⇒ (3). Apply 3.6. (3) ⇒ (1). Let x ∈ X and consider UX(x). Then (UX(x),x) ∈ qX and, by assumption, there is a subfilter G of UX(x) with a countable base such that (G,x) ∈ qX. Hence, UX(x) ⊂ G ⊂ UX(x), which implies G = UX(x). � Proposition 3.8. Let (X, W) be a uniform space and (X, [W]) its correspond- ing semiuniform convergence space. A better framework for first countable spaces 293 Then the following are equivalent: (1) (X, W) is first countable as a semiuniform convergence space, i.e. (X,[W]) is first countable. (2) The filter W of entourages has a countable base. Proof. Since [W] consists of all filters F on X ×X containing W, the proof is obvious. � Remark 3.9. It is well-known that a uniform space is pseudometrizable, i.e. its uniformity is induced by a pseudometric, iff its filter of entourages has a count- able base. Thus, a semiuniform convergence space (X, JX) is pseudometrizable (i.e. there is a pseudometric d on X such that JX = {F ∈ F(X × X) : F ⊃ {Vε : ε > 0}} with ∨ε = {(x,y) : d(x,y) < ε}) iff it is uniform (i.e. there is a uniformity W on X such that JX = [W]) and first countable. Proposition 3.10. The construct FC-SUConv of first countable semiuni- form convergence spaces (and uniformly continuous maps) is bicoreflective in SUConv, where 1X : (X, (JX)FC) → (X, JX) with (JX)FC = {F ∈ JX: there is some G ∈ JX with G ⊂ F and G has a countable base} is the bicoreflection of (X, JX) ∈| SUConv | w.r.t. FC-SUConv, and (X, (JX)FC) is called the underlying first countable semiuniform convergence space of (X, JX). Proof. Obviously, if f : (Y, JY ) → (X, JX) is a uniformly continuous map from a first countable semiuniform convergence space (Y, JY ) into a semiuniform convergence space (X, JX), then f : (Y, JY ) → (X, (JX)FC) is also uniformly continuous. � Corollary 3.11. In SUConv first countability is summable and divisible. Remark 3.12. 1) In classical General Topology first countability is not di- visible, e.g. the usual topological space Rt of real numbers is first countable, whereas the topological quotient space Rt/N, obtained by identifying the set N of positive integers to a point is not first countable. If Rt is regarded as a semiuniform convergence space and the quotient Rt/N is formed in SUConv, then Rt/N is first countable, but no longer topological. Indeed, Rt/N is a convergence space (=symmetric Kent convergence space), since Rt is a convergence space and convergence spaces are closed under for- mation of quotients in SUConv. 2) The convergence spaces are exactly the quotients (in SUConv) of the topological semiuniform convergence spaces (= symmetric topological spaces). This has been proved in the language of nearness by W. A. Robertson [6] (cf. also [1]). Proposition 3.13. 1) FC-SUConv is closed under formation of subspaces in SUConv. 2) FC-SUConv is closed under formation of countable products in SU- Conv. 294 Gerhard Preuß Proof. 1) Let (X, JX) ∈|FC-SUConv|,A ⊂ X and let i : A → X be the inclusion map. If the initial SUConv-structure on A w.r.t. i : A → X is denoted by JA, then let F ∈ JA. By definition, (i × i)(F) ∈ JX, and by assumption, there is some G ∈ JX with a countable base B such that G ⊂ (i × i)(F). Hence, the subfilter (i × i)−1(G) of F belongs to JA and has the countable base {B ∩ (A×A) : B ∈ B}. 2) Let ((Xi, JXi))i∈I be a countable family of first countable semiuniform convergence spaces and let (Πi∈IXi, JX) be their product. Further, let F ∈ JX. Then (pi × pi)(F) ∈ JXi for each i ∈ I, where pi : Πi∈IXi → Xi denotes the i − th projection. By assumption, there is some subfilter Gi ∈ JXi of (pi ×pi)(F) with a countable base Bi. Hence, Πi∈IGi ⊂ Πi∈I(pi ×pi)(F) ⊂ F where Πi∈I(Xi ×Xi) and (ΠXi) × (Πi∈IXi) are not distinguished. Obviously, Πi∈IGi ∈ JX. The set B consisting of all finite intersections of elements of the countable set B′ = {(pi × pi)−1[Bi] : i ∈ I,Bi ∈ Bi} is a countable base of Πi∈IGi. � Remark 3.14. Since the construct TopS of symmetric topological spaces (and continuous maps) is closed under formation of products in SUConv, arbitrary products of first countable semiuniform convergence spaces need not be first countable, e.g. it is well-known that the topological product space RRt is not first countable. Theorem 3.15. 1) FC-SUConv is a topological universe, where the natural function spaces (resp. one-point extensions) arise from the natural function spaces (resp. one-point extensions) SUConv by forming the underlying first countable spaces. 2) In FC-SUConv countable products of quotients are quotients. Proof. 1) Since FC-SUConv is bicoreflective in the topological universe SU- Conv and closed under formation of finite products and subspaces, it is the desired topological universe (cf. [5; 3.1.7 and 3.2.5]). 2) Since countable products and quotients are formed in FC-SUConv as in SUConv, where products of quotients are quotients, in FC-SUConv count- able products of quotients are quotients. � A much stronger condition than the first axiom of countability is the sec- ond axiom of countability which can be defined in the realm of semiuniform convergence spaces as follows: Definition 3.16. A semiuniform convergence space (X, JX) is said to fulfill the second axiom of countability or to be second countable if there is a countable set A ⊂ P(X ×X) such that each F ∈ JX has a subfilter G ∈ JX with a base of elements of A. Proposition 3.17. Every second countable semiuniform convergence space is first countable. Proposition 3.18. Let (X, W) be a uniform space and (X, [W]) its corre- sponding semiuniform convergence space. Then the following are equivalent: A better framework for first countable spaces 295 (1) (X, [W]) is first countable, (2) (X, [W]) is second countable, (3) W has a countable base. Proof. The equivalence of (1) and (3) has been proved under 3.8. Since 3.17 is valid, it suffices to prove: (1) ⇒ (2). Let F ∈ JX. Then F ⊃ W and by (3), W has a countable base A. � Proposition 3.19. Let (X, X) be a symmetric topological space and (X,JγqX) its corresponding semiuniform convergence space. Then (X, JγqX ) is second countable iff (X, X) is second countable in the usual sense. Proof. “⇒”. Let A ⊂ P(X × X) be countable and let each F ∈ JγqX have a subfilter G ∈ JγqX with a base of elements of A. For each x ∈ X, UX(x) × UX(x) ∈ JγqX , and by assumption there is some filter G ∈ JγqX , i.e. G ⊃ UX(y) × UX(y) for some y ∈ X, such that (∗) UX(y) × UX(y) ⊂ G ⊂ UX(x) × UX(x) where G has a base of elements of A. If p1 : X × X → X denotes the first projection, it follows from (∗) UX(y) ⊂ p1(G) ⊂ UX(x) and, since (X, X) is symmetric, p1(G) = UX(x) = UX(y). Thus, UX(x) has a base of elements of the countable set A′ = {p1[A] : A ∈ A}. Let A′′ = {(p1[A])0 : A ∈ A}. Then A′′ is countable and UX(x) has also a base of elements of A′′. Each O ∈ X is a union of elements of A′′, i.e. (X, X) is second countable. “⇐”. Let X have a countable base B and let F ∈ JγqX , i.e. there is some x ∈ X such that F ⊃ UX(x) × UX(x). Obviously, UX(x) has a base of elements of B, and UX(x) × UX(x) has a base of elements of the countable set A = {B × B : B ∈ B}. Consequently, (X, JγqX ) is second countable. � Remark 3.20. The second axiom of countability does not have the nice struc- tural behaviour as the first axiom of countability. It is easily checked that second countable semiuniform convergence spaces are hereditary, countably productive, countably summable and divisible, but they do not form a bi- coreflective subconstruct of SUConv, since arbitrary sums of second count- able spaces are not second countable, which is known from second countable topological spaces (note: coproducts [=sums] of topological semiuniform con- vergence spaces are topological). Nevertheless, in the realm of semiuniform convergence spaces, second countability is divisible, a result which is not true in the framework of topological spaces. 296 Gerhard Preuß 4. Applications of first countability. Remark 4.1. If (X, JX) is a semiuniform convergence space, then a filter F on X is called a Cauchy filter iff F × F ∈ JX (i.e. F ∈ γJX ), and it is said to converge to x (i.e. (F,x) ∈ qγJX ) iff F ∩ ẋ is a Cauchy filter. A sequence (xn) in X is a Cauchy sequence iff the elementary filter Fe of (xn) is a Cauchy filter, and it converges to x iff the elementary filter of (xn) converges to x. Definition 4.2. For each subset A in a semiuniform convergence space (X, JX), the closure A is defined as follows: A = {x ∈ X : there is some filter F on X converging to x such that A ∈ F}. Proposition 4.3. Let (X, JX) be a first countable semiuniform convergence space and A a subset in (X, JX). Then A = {x ∈ X : there is a sequence in A converging to x in (X, JX)}. Proof. Let x ∈ A. Then there is some filter F on X such that A ∈ F and (F,x) ∈ qγJX , i.e. F converges to x in (X, JX). By 3.6, there is some (G,x) ∈ qγJX such that G ⊂ F has a countable base B = {B1,B2, . . .}, where we may assume without loss of generality that B1 ⊃ B2 ⊃ . . . . For each n ∈ N, choose some xn ∈ Bn ∩A. Then the elementary filter Fe of (xn) contains G , which implies that (xn) converges to x in (X, JX). The inverse implication is evident. � Remark 4.4. Uniform spaces have been generalized to uniform limit spaces, which are semiuniform convergence spaces fulfilling the following two additional axioms: UC4) If F and G are uniform filters, then F ∩ G is also a uniform filter; UC5) If the composition F ◦ G of two uniform filters F and G exists, it is a uniform filter, which has {F ◦G : F ∈ F,G ∈ G} as a base, where ◦ stands for the composition of relations. The underlying filter spaces of uniform limit spaces are called Cauchy spaces. Proposition 4.5. A first countable Cauchy space (X,γ) is complete iff it is sequentially complete (i.e. each Cauchy sequence in (X,γ) converges). Proof. “⇒”. Obvious. “⇐”. Let F ∈ γ. By assumption, there is some G ∈ γ with a countable base B = {B1,B2, . . .} such that G ⊂ F. Without loss of generality, let B1 ⊃ B2 ⊃ . . . . For each n ∈ N, choose some xn ∈ Bn. Since the elementary filter Fe of (xn) is finer than G, it is a Cauchy filter. Furthermore, γ = γJ*γ , where Jγ* = {G ∈ F(X × X) : there are K1, . . . Kn ∈ γ with G ⊃ ∩ni=1Ki × Ki} is a uniform limit space structure for X. It follows from G × Fe ⊃ (G ∩ Fe) × (G ∩ Fe) ∈ Jγ*, G×Fe ∈ Jγ*, and since by assumption Fe converges to some x ∈ X, Fe×ẋ ∈ J*γ. Thus, G × ẋ = (Fe × ẋ) ◦ (G ◦ Fe) ∈ J*γ, i.e. G converges to x, which implies that F converges to x. � A better framework for first countable spaces 297 Corollary 4.6. A first countable uniform limit space (X, JX) is complete iff each Cauchy sequence in (X, JX) converges. Proof. By 3.2, the underlying filter space (=Cauchy space) of the first countable uniform limit space (X, JX) is first countable. Applying 4.5, 4.6 is proved. � Definition 4.7. A semiuniform convergence space (X, JX) is called 1) countably compact provided that each filter F on X with a countable base has an adherence point x ∈ X, i.e. there is some filter G on X converging to x such that G ⊃ F, 2) sequentially compact iff each sequence in X has a subsequence converging in (X, JX). Proposition 4.8. A semiuniform convergence space (X, JX) is countably com- pact iff each sequence in X has an accumulation point (in (X,qγJX )). Proof. “⇒”. Let (xn) be a sequence in X and Fe its elementary filter. Then Fe has a countable base and by assumption there is an adherence point x ∈ X of Fe, i.e. x is an accumulation point of (xn). “⇐”. Let F be a filter on X with a countable base B = {B1,B2, . . .} such that, without loss of generality, B1 ⊃ B2 ⊃ . . . . For each n ∈ N, choose some xn ∈ Bn. The elementary filter Fe of (xn) is finer that F and has an adherence point by assumption. Hence, F has an adherence point. � Proposition 4.9. 1) Every sequentially compact semiuniform convergence space is countably compact. 2) Every countably compact semiuniform convergence space, which is first countable, is sequentially compact. Proof. 1) is obvious. 2) Let (xn) be a sequence in X and Fe its elementary filter. Since (X, JX) is countably compact, Fe has an adherence point x ∈ X, i.e. there is some filter F ⊃ Fe such that (F,x) ∈ qγJX . By 3.6, there is a subfilter G of F with a countable base B = {B1,B2, . . .} converging to x. Without loss of generality, let B1 ⊃ B2 ⊃ . . . . For each m ∈ N, Em∩Bm 6= Ø, where Em = {xn : n ≥ m}. Choose ym ∈ Bm ∩Em for each m ∈ N. Then (ym)m∈N converges to x, since the elementary filter F′e of (ym) is finer than G. Furthermore, there exists a subsequence (xjn) of (xn) such that the elementary filter of (xjn) coincides with the elementary filter of (ym), i.e. (xjn) converges to x. � Remark 4.10. Continuous convergence, introduced by H. Hahn [3] in Analy- sis, is nowadays mainly considered in the realm of limit spaces, where a Kent convergence space (X,q) is called a limit space provided that for any x ∈ X and any two filters F and G on X converging to x, the intersection F ∩ G con- verges to x. Let X = (X,q) and Y = (Y,r) be limit spaces and let [X, Y] be the set of all continuous maps between X and Y, where a map f : X → Y is continuous iff (f(F),f(x)) ∈ r for each (F,x) ∈ q. A filter F on [X, Y] converges continuously to f ∈ [X, Y] provided that for each x ∈ X and each 298 Gerhard Preuß filter G on X converging to x in X, the filter eX,Y (G × F) converges to f(x) in Y, where G × F denotes the product filter and eX,Y (x,g) = g(x) for each (x,g) ∈ X×[X, Y]). A sequence (fn) in [X, Y] is said to converge continuously to f ∈ [X, Y] iff the elementary filter of (fn) converges continuously to f. If a Kent convergence space X = (X,q) has the property that for each x ∈ X, the neighborhood filter U(x) = ⋂ {F ∈ F(X) : (F,x) ∈ q} converges to x, then it is called a pretopological space. Proposition 4.11. Let X = (X,q) be a first countable limit space and Y = (Y,r) a pretopological space. Then a sequence (fn) in [X, Y] converges contin- uously to f ∈ [X, Y] iff for each x ∈ X and each sequence (xn) in X converging to x, the sequence (fn(xn)) converges to f(x) in Y. Proof. “⇐” (indirectly). If the elementary filter Fe of (fn) does not converge continuously to f ∈ [X, Y], there is some (G,x) ∈ q such that eX,Y (G × Fe) does not converge to f(x), i.e. there is some U ∈ U(f(x)) in Y such that for each G ∈ G and each F ∈ Fe, there are y ∈ G and g ∈ F with g(y) /∈ U. By assumption, there exists some (H,x) ∈ q such that H has a countable base B = {B1,B2, . . .} and H ⊂ G. Without loss of generality, let B1 ⊃ B2 ⊃ . . . . Since for each n ∈ N,Bn ∈ G and {fm : m ≥ n} ∈ F, one can construct sequences (xn) and m0 < m1 < ... such that xn ∈ Bn and fmn(xn) /∈ U. Define a sequence (yn) in X by y0 = . . . = ym0 = x0,ym0+1 = . . . = ym1 = x1, . . . and so on. Obviously, (yn) converges to x in X, but (fn(yn)) does not converge to f(x), since fmn(ymn) = fmn(xn) /∈ U. “⇒”. This implication is straightforward. � Proposition 4.12. Let X = (X,q) be a first countable Kent convergence space and Y = (Y,r) a pretopological space. A map f : X → Y is continuous, where continuity is defined as under 3.10., iff for each x ∈ X and each sequence (xn) in X converging to x in X, the sequence (f(xn)) converges to f(x) in Y Proof. “⇒”. This implication is evident. “⇐”. Since each filter F on X with a countable base is the intersection of all elementary filters on X containing F (cf. [2; 2.8.6.]) and each map f : X → Y preserves intersection of filters, the proof is obvious. � References [1] H.L. Bentley, H. Herrlich and W.A. Robertson, Convenient categories for topologists, Comm. Math. Univ. Carolinae 17 (1976), 207–227. [2] W. Gähler, Grundstrukturen der Analysis I/II (Birkhäuser, Basel, 1977/78). [3] H. Hahn, Theorie der reellen Funktionen (Berlin, 1921). [4] G. Preuß, Semiuniform convergence spaces, Math. Japonica 41 (1995), 465–491. [5] G. Preuß, Foundations of Topology – An Approach to Convenient Topology (Kluwer, Dor- drecht, 2002). [6] W.A. Robertson, Convergence as a nearness concept, PhD thesis (Carlton University, Ot- tawa, 1975). A better framework for first countable spaces 299 Received November 2001 Revised October 2002 Gerhard Preuß Department of Mathematics and Computer Science, Free University Berlin, Arnimallee 3, 14195 Berlin, Germany E-mail address : preuss@math.fu-berlin.de