@ Appl. Gen. Topol. 15, no. 2(2014), 147-154doi:10.4995/agt.2014.3181 c© AGT, UPV, 2014 The classical ring of quotients of Cc(X) Papiya Bhattacharjee a, Michelle L. Knox b and Warren Wm. McGovern c a Penn State Erie, The Behrend College, Erie, PA 16563 (pxb39@psu.edu) b Midwestern State University, Wichita Falls, TX 76308 (michelle.knox@mwsu.edu) c H. L. Wilkes Honors College, Florida Atlantic University, Jupiter, FL 33458 (warren.mcgovern@fau.edu) Abstract We construct the classical ring of quotients of the algebra of continuous real-valued functions with countable range. Our construction is a slight modification of the construction given in [3]. Dowker’s example shows that the two constructions can be different. 2010 MSC: 54C40, 13B30. Keywords: ring of continuous functions; ring of quotients; zero-dimensional space. 1. Introduction Our aim here is two-fold. We aim to add to the growing knowledge regarding the ring of continuous functions of countable range on the space X, denoted by Cc(X), while also supplying a correction to representation of the classical ring of quotients of Cc(X), denoted qc(X). In this section we supply the relevant definitions and concepts. In Section 2, we construct qc(X) in the same vein as the Representation Theorems of Fine, Gillman, and Lambek [2]. The third section is devoted to studying a specific space which shows why the construction in Section 2 is needed. We also include an example of Mysior that is peculiar in its own right. Throughout this paper, X will denote a zero-dimensional Hausdorff space, that is, a Hausdorff space with a base of clopen sets. The ring of all real- valued continuous functions on X is denoted by C(X), and the subring of C(X) consisting of those functions with countable range is denoted by Cc(X). Received 23 May 2013 – Accepted 14 November 2013 http://dx.doi.org/10.4995/agt.2014.3181 P. Bhattacharjee, M. L. Knox and W. Wm. McGovern We may restrict to the class of zero-dimensional spaces because, as it is argued in [3] and [12], for any space Y there is a zero-dimensional Hausdorff space X such that Cc(Y ) and Cc(X) are isomorphic as rings. One of the first results concerning Cc(X) was by W. Rudin [14] who showed that a compact space X satisfies C(X) = Cc(X) precisely when X is scattered. In [9] the authors studied general zero-dimensional spaces for which Cc(X) = C(X), calling such a space functionally countable. Recently, there has been an interest in Cc(X) as a ring in its own right. Recall that for f ∈ C(X), Z(f) denotes its zero-set: Z(f) = {x ∈ X : f(x) = 0}. The set-theoretic complement of a zero-set is known as a cozero-set and we label this set by coz(f). We denote the collection of all cozero-sets by coz(X) and use clop(X) to denote the boolean algebra of clopen subsets of X. When we consider cozero-sets arising from functions in Cc(X), we get what is denoted in [6] by clop(X)σ: the set of all countable unions of clopen subsets, i.e. the set of all σ-clopen sets. One of the main differences between C(X) and Cc(X) is the realization of the maximal ideal spaces. The Gelfand-Kolmogorov Theorem states Max(C(X)) is homeomorphic to the Stone-Čech compactification of X, denoted βX. On the other hand, the maximal ideal space of Cc(X) is homeomorphic to the Banaschewski compactification of X, denoted β0X. (A proof can be modeled after Theorem 5.1 of [6].) The most well-known way of realizing βX is as the collection of all z-ultrafilters of X. A nice way to view β0X is as the Stone dual of clop(X). In general, βX and β0X are not homeomorphic. The next theorem characterizing when they are is well-known (see Chapter 6.2 of [1]). Theorem 1.1. For a zero-dimensional space X the following statements are equivalent. (1) βX = β0X (2) Every cozero-set is a σ-clopen set. (3) βX is zero-dimensional. Zero-dimensional spaces X for which βX is zero-dimensional are known as strongly zero-dimensional spaces. In this short article we are interested in zero- dimensional spaces which are not strongly zero-dimensional. The third section deals with one of the most well-known of such examples. As for references, the text [4] is still pivotal. We also mention [13] and [1] for topological considerations, definitions, and concepts not explicitly discussed here. We end this section with a remark about σ-clopens. Remark 1.2. It should be apparent that if U ∈ clop(X)σ, then there is some f ∈ Cc(X) such that coz(f) = U. A sketch of this proof is as follows. First write U = ⋃ n Kn as a disjoint union of a countable number of clopen sets. Next, consider the function (call it f) that maps Ki to 1 i and the rest of X to 0. This function is continuous and is an element of Cc(X). Finally, coz(f) = U. c© AGT, UPV, 2014 Appl. Gen. Topol. 15, no. 2 148 The classical ring of quotients of Cc(X) 2. Classical Ring of Quotients In [12] the authors constructed both the classical ring of quotients and the maximum ring of quotients of Cc(X). They modeled their construction after the Representation Theorems of Fine, Gillman, and Lambek [2]. We recall these after we set up some notation. Let G(X) = {U ⊆ X : U is a dense open subset of X} and G0(X) = {O ⊆ X : O is a dense cozero-set of X}. We let q(X) and qc(X) denote the classical rings of quotients of C(X) and Cc(X), respectively. We let Q(X) and Qc(X) denote the maximum rings of quotients of C(X) and Cc(X), respectively. Theorem 2.1 ([2]). Suppose X is a Tychonoff space. Then q(X) = lim O∈G0(X) C(O) and Q(X) = lim U∈G(X) C(U). In the above theorem the use of the limit is to describe that the rings are direct limits of rings of continuous functions. This direct limit can be described as the union of the rings C(U) modulo the equivalence that f1 ∈ C(U1), f2 ∈ C(U2) are equivalent if they agree on U1 ∩ U2. In [12] the authors classified qc(X) and Qc(X) for zero-dimensional X as qc(X) = lim O∈G0(X) Cc(O) and Qc(X) = lim U∈G(X) Cc(U). Unfortunately, we believe that the classification of qc(X) is incorrect. We now construct the classical ring of quotients of Cc(X). Let Gσ(X) = {K ∈ X : K is a dense σ-clopen set of X}. For the purpose of comparison, we will denote q′(X) = lim O∈G0(X) Cc(O). Theorem 2.2. Let X be a zero-dimensional space. Then qc(X) = lim U∈Gσ(X) Cc(U). Proof. Given that X ∈ Gσ(X) we have an embedding Cc(X) ≤ qc(X) ≤ q ′(X). First let f ∈ Cc(X) be a non zero-divisor element of Cc(X). We claim that coz(f) is a dense subset of X. If not, then X r clX coz(f) is a nonempty open subset and hence there is a nonempty clopen set of X which is disjoint from clX coz(f). The characteristic function on said clopen set is a non-zero function belonging to Cc(X) and annihilates f, a contradiction. Thus, coz(f) ∈ Gσ(X). Restricting f to coz(f) produces an element which is invertible in Cc(coz(f)) and hence also in qc(X). So every regular element of Cc(X) is c© AGT, UPV, 2014 Appl. Gen. Topol. 15, no. 2 149 P. Bhattacharjee, M. L. Knox and W. Wm. McGovern invertible in qc(X). It follows (by a straightforward ring theoretic argument) that the classical ring of quotients of Cc(X) is embedded inside of qc(X). As for the reverse inclusion, the proof follows mutatis mutandi from the proof of the Representation Theorem of [2] (Theorem 2.6). This was attempted in Theorem 2.12 of [12]. The only error made there was that when taking a dense cozeroset U of X there might not be a d ∈ Cc(X) such that coz(d) = U. In fact, the only change needed from their proof is the modification we have suggested in using Gσ(X) instead of G0(X). � Remark 2.3. Observe that qc(X) ≤ q ′(X) since Gσ(X) ⊆ G0(X). One might question whether both direct limits produce the same rings. In the next section we will exhibit an example of a zero-dimensional space for which qc(X) < q ′(X). Of course, if X is strongly zero-dimensional, then G0(X) = Gσ(X) and hence qc(X) = q ′(X). Remark 3.10 discusses the equality and the question of whether such a space need be strongly zero-dimensional. We end this section with some remarks and results whose proofs are in the same vein as above. Corollary 2.4. Let F be a proper subfield of R. For a zero-dimensional space X, the classical ring of quotients of C(X, F) is lim U∈Gσ(X) C(U, F). In particular, the classical ring of quotients of C(X, Q) is q(X, Q) = lim U∈Gσ(X) C(U, Q). 3. A Counterexample We let X be the space defined in 4V of [13]. We give a brief sketch of the construction. Let W denote the space of countable ordinals equipped with the interval topology. For an ordinal σ, we use W(σ) to denote the set of ordinals smaller than σ. Notice that W(ω1) = W. Let J = R r Q. For x ∈ J, let Jx = {x + r : r ∈ Q} and J = {Jx : x ∈ J}. Re-index J by J = {Jα : α ∈ W} so that Jα ∩ Jβ = ∅ whenever α 6= β. For α < ω1, let Uα = Rr ⋃ {Jβ : α < β < ω1}, and let X = ⋃ {{α}×Uα : α < ω1}. Equip X with the subspace topology from W×R; X is a Tychonoff space. The space X is similar to Dowker’s Example from [1]. X is a classical example of a zero-dimensional space that is not strongly zero-dimensional. Another reference for this space is Exercise 16M of [4]. For notational purposes, let Xσ = {(τ, r) ∈ X : τ < σ}. In other words Xσ = X ∩ (W(σ) × R). We denote the X-complement of Xσ by X ′ σ and call such a set a cofinal band of X since X′σ = {(τ, r) ∈ X : σ ≤ τ}. Since X is not strongly zero-dimensional, we know that not every cozeroset of X is a σ-clopen. We aim to convince the reader of three things. First, that if C is a σ-clopen of X, then either C or X r C is a subset of Xσ for some σ ∈ W. Second, if C is a σ-clopen, then X r clXC is also a σ-clopen. Third, qc(X) < q ′(X). We let π : X → W be the continuous projection map. We recall some subsets of X defined in Section 3 of [8]. c© AGT, UPV, 2014 Appl. Gen. Topol. 15, no. 2 150 The classical ring of quotients of Cc(X) Definition 3.1. Let K be a clopen subset of X such that π(K) is cofinal in W. Define the following sets for r ∈ R and ǫ > 0: Sǫr = {σ ∈ W : ({σ} × (r − ǫ, r + ǫ)) ∩ X ⊆ K} and TK = {r ∈ R : S ǫ r is cofinal in W for some ǫ > 0}. Proposition 3.18 of [8] states TK is an unbounded subset of R. Here we show more: that TK is an open subset of R. Proposition 3.2. Suppose K is a clopen subset of X such that π(K) is cofinal in W. Then TK = {r ∈ R : there is a σr ∈ W such that {(τ, r) ∈ X : σr ≤ τ} ⊆ K}. Proof. For r ∈ R notice that by the construction of X, if (σ, r) ∈ X, then for all σ ≤ τ ∈ W, (τ, r) ∈ X. If r ∈ TK, then choose σ ∈ W such that (σ, r) ∈ X. Set Y = {(τ, r) ∈ X : σ ≤ τ} and observe that Y is homeomorphic to W. Let g = χK ∈ C(X) be the characteristic function on K; K = coz(g). The restriction of g to Y is constant on a tail (see Chapter 5 [4]), and r ∈ TK, so there is some σr ∈ W such that for all σr ≤ τ ∈ W, (τ, r) ∈ coz(g) = K. Next, let r ∈ R have the property that there is σr ∈ W such that {(τ, r) ∈ X : σr ≤ τ} ⊆ K. Assume, by way of contradiction, that r /∈ TK, so for each n ∈ N we have that S 1 n r is not cofinal in W. That is, for each n ∈ N there exists σn ∈ W where ({α} × (r − 1 n , r + 1 n )) ∩ X is not a subset of K for all α > σn. Let σ = sup{σn : n ∈ N}, then for all α > σ, ({α} × (r − 1 n , r + 1 n )) ∩ X is not a subset of K. However, choosing a β ∈ W for which σ, σr ≤ β,then since K is open there must exist n ∈ N such that ({β} × (r − 1 n , r + 1 n )) ∩ X ⊆ K, a contradiction. Therefore r ∈ TK. � Proposition 3.3. Let K be a clopen subset of X such that π(K) is cofinal in W. The set TK is a nonempty open subset of R. Proof. As we did previously, let g = χK ∈ C(X) with coz(g) = K. Let t ∈ TK, and suppose, by means of contradiction, that there is no open neighborhood of t contained in TK. Then there is (without loss of generality) an increasing sequence of rationals, say {qn}, not belonging to TK which converges to t. Note that g is eventually zero on a tail of [W × {qn}] ∩ X for each n ∈ N. Thus for each n ∈ N there is a σn ∈ W such that for all σ > σn we have g((σ, qn)) = 0, i.e. (σ, qn) /∈ K for every σ > σn. Let ζ = sup{σn : n ∈ N}. Then consider an appropriate α > ζ such that for all α ≤ β (β, t) ∈ K. (Such an α exists because t ∈ TK.) But then since K is open there is a rational qn < t such that (α, qn) ∈ K, a contradiction. � c© AGT, UPV, 2014 Appl. Gen. Topol. 15, no. 2 151 P. Bhattacharjee, M. L. Knox and W. Wm. McGovern Remark 3.4. We observe that the proof of Proposition 3.2 actually shows that if K is clopen subset of X such that π(K) is cofinal in W, then for any r ∈ R the set {σ ∈ W : (σ, r) ∈ K} is either bounded by a countable ordinal or contains a tail of W. In other words, TK ={r ∈ R : there is a cofinal subset of W, say W, such that (τ, r) ∈ K for all τ ∈ W}. This is pivotal in proving our next result. Proposition 3.5. Let K be a clopen subset of X such that π(K) is cofinal in W. Then π(X r K) is not cofinal in W. Thus K contains a cofinal band of X. Proof. We suppose that both π(K) and π(X r K) are cofinal in W. By the previous remark it follows that TK ∩ TXrK = ∅ and TK ∪ TXrK = R. By Proposition 3.3 both TK and TXrK are nonempty open sets. This produces a disconnection of R, the desired contradiction. � Proposition 3.6. Let K be a σ-clopen subset of X. Then X r clXK is also a σ-clopen subset. Proof. Suppose K is a σ-clopen subset of X. First consider the case where π(K) is not cofinal in W. Then K ⊆ Xτ for some τ ∈ W. Xτ is a separable zero-dimensional metrizable space and hence strongly zero-dimensional. Hence Xτ r clXK is a σ-clopen subset of Xτ. Since Xτ is a clopen subset of X, it follows that Xτ r clXK is a σ-clopen subset of X, thus X r clXK = X ′ τ ∪ (Xτ r clXK) is σ-clopen subset of X. Next consider the case where π(K) is cofinal in W. Then for some τ ∈ W K contains the cofinal band X′τ . Since X r clXK is an open subset of Xτ . We mentioned in the previous paragraph that Xτ is a separable zero-dimensional metrizable space and hence strongly zero-dimensional. It follows that XrclXK is a σ-clopen subset of Xτ and thus a σ-clopen subset of X. � Corollary 3.7. Suppose K is a dense σ-clopen subset of X. Then π(K) is cofinal, and thus K contains a cofinal band of X. Theorem 3.8. For the space X, qc(X) < q ′(X). Proof. Let T1 = [W × (−∞, 0)] ∩ X and T2 = [W × (0, ∞)] ∩ X. Both T1 and T2 are cozero-sets of X and hence so is T = T1 ∪ T2. Moreover, T is a dense subset of X. We note that π(T ) is cofinal in X, but T does not contain a cofinal band. Therefore, T is not a σ-clopen subset of X. It follows that T ∈ G0(X) r Gσ(X). Let f : T → R be defined by f(x) = { 1, if x ∈ T1 0, if x ∈ T2. Then f ∈ Cc(T ) and so f ∈ q ′(X). We claim that f /∈ qc(X). If it were, then there would exist a dense σ-clopen of X, say V ∈ Gσ(X), and g ∈ Cc(V ) such c© AGT, UPV, 2014 Appl. Gen. Topol. 15, no. 2 152 The classical ring of quotients of Cc(X) that f and g agree on T ∩ V . But since V is a dense σ-clopen set, V contains a cofinal band of X. Therefore, V ∩ T equals T on this band and so g sends T1 to 1 and T2 to 0. But g is defined on the whole band, contradicting continuity at points of the form (τ, 0) for large enough τ. � Remark 3.9. Proposition 3.6 is interesting on its own. The proposition yields for a zero-dimensional space Y , both rings qc(Y ) and limU∈Gσ(Y ) C(U) are von Neumann regular rings. The proof would be modeled after the proofs of Proposition 1.2 [10] and Theorem 1.3 of [7]. Simply, you would need that X is σ-clopen complemented. The ring limU∈Gσ(X) C(U) has not been studied except in the case that X is strongly zero-dimensional. We conjecture that the ring can be realized as the classical ring of quotients of the Alexandroff Algebra A(X) (see [6] or [5] for more information). Remark 3.10. Let X∗ denote the finer topology on R2 defined by Mysior [11] using D = Q × Q. X∗ is another example of a zero-dimensional space that is not strongly zero-dimensional. The countable set D is precisely the set of all isolated points of X∗. Thus, D is the smallest dense σ-clopen subset of X∗. It follows that qc(X ∗) = q′(X∗) = C(N) = q(X∗) = Q(X∗). Therefore, in general it is not the case that the equality qc(X) = q ′(X) forces X to be strongly zero-dimensional. We are unable to characterize in any nice way when qc(X) = q ′(X). Acknowledgements. We would like to express our gratitude to the referee for his/her helpful comments. References [1] R. Engelking, General Topology, Sigma Ser. Pure Math. 6 (Heldermann Verlag, Berlin, 1989). [2] N. J. Fine, L. Gillman and J. Lambek, Rings of Quotients of Rings of Functions, Lecture Note Series ( McGill University Press, Montreal, 1966). [3] M. Ghadermazi, O. A. S. Karamzadeh and M. Namdari, On the functionally countable subalgebra of C(X), Rend. Sem. Mat. Univ. Padova, to appear. [4] L. Gillman and M. Jerison, Rings of Continuous Functions, Graduate Texts in Mathe- matics, 43, (Springer Verlag, Berlin-Heidelberg-New York, 1976). [5] A. Hager, Cozero fields, Confer. Sem. Mat. Univ. Bari. 175 (1980), 1–23. [6] A. Hager, C. Kimber and W. Wm. McGovern, Unique a-closure for some ℓ-groups of rational valued functions, Czech. Math. J. 55 (2005), 409–421. [7] M. Henriksen and R. G. Woods, Cozero complemented spaces; when the space of minimal prime ideals of a C(X) is compact, Topology Appl. 141, no. 1-3 (2004), 147–170. [8] M. L. Knox and W. Wm. McGovern, Rigid extensions of ℓ-groups of continuous func- tions, Czech. Math. Journal 58(133) (2008), 993–1014. [9] R. Levy and M. D. Rice, Normal P -spaces and the Gδ-topology, Colloq. Math. 44, no. 2 (1981), 227–240. c© AGT, UPV, 2014 Appl. Gen. Topol. 15, no. 2 153 P. Bhattacharjee, M. L. Knox and W. Wm. McGovern [10] R. Levy and J. Shapiro, Rings of quotients of rings of functions, Topology Appl. 146/147 (2005), 253–265. [11] A. Mysior, Two easy examples of zero-dimensional spaces, Proc. Amer. Math. Soc. 92, no. 4 (1984), 615–617. [12] M. Namdari and A. Veisi, Rings of quotients of the subalgebra of C(X) consisting of functions with countable image, Inter. Math. Forum 7 (2012), 561–571. [13] J. Porter and R. G. Woods, Extensions and Absolutes of Hausdorff Spaces, (Springer- Verlag, New York, 1988). [14] W. Rudin, Continuous functions on compact spaces without perfect subsets, Proc. Amer. Math. Soc. 8 (1957), 39–42. c© AGT, UPV, 2014 Appl. Gen. Topol. 15, no. 2 154