() @ Appl. Gen. Topol. 19, no. 1 (2018), 129-144doi:10.4995/agt.2018.7849 c© AGT, UPV, 2018 Characterization of quantale-valued metric spaces and quantale-valued partial metric spaces by convergence Gunther Jäger a and T. M. G. Ahsanullah b a School of Mechanical Engineering, University of Applied Sciences Stralsund, 18435 Stralsund, Germany (gunther.jaeger@hochschule-stralsund.de) b Department of Mathematics, College of Science, King Saud University, Riyadh 11451, Saudi Arabia. (tmga1@ksu.edu.sa) Communicated by V. Gregori Abstract We identify two categories of quantale-valued convergence tower spaces that are isomorphic to the categories of quantale-valued metric spaces and quantale-valued partial metric spaces, respectively. As an applica- tion we state a quantale-valued metrization theorem for quantale-valued convergence tower groups. 2010 MSC: 54A20; 54A40; 54E35; 54E70. Keywords: L-metric space; L-partial metric space; L-convergence tower space; L-convergence tower group; metrization. 1. Introduction There are different generalizations of metric spaces. One of them solves the problem of assigning a precise value to the distance between two points by allowing instead the assignment of a probability distribution for each pair of points, the value of which at u ∈ [0,∞] giving the probabilty that the distance between the points is less than u. A thorough treatment of these probabilistic metric spaces can be found in [28]. From a different perspective, metric spaces are viewed as categories in [19] and later, in [9] it has been shown that not only Received 05 July 2017 – Accepted 10 October 2017 http://dx.doi.org/10.4995/agt.2018.7849 G. Jäger and T. M. G. Ahsanullah classical metric spaces but also probabilistic metric spaces are special instances of this approach. The main idea here is to replace the interval [0,∞] as the codomain of a metric by a quantale. For this reason, we speak of quantale- valued metric spaces. Another generalization of metric spaces deals with the problem, that self-distances are not always zero. Relaxing this requirement and at the same time enforcing the transivity axiom leads to the theory of partial metric spaces [17, 21]. This concept was independently, and in much wider generality, introduced under the name M-valued set by Höhle [11], where the relationship with the general view point of [19] becomes obvious, as also M-valued sets take their values in a quantale. All these generalizations allow the introduction of underlying topological spaces and, in consequence, of a concept of convergence. In this paper, we look at convergence for quantale-valued metric spaces from a different perspective. Rather than describing a concept of convergence underlying a quantale-valued metric space, we are looking for a concept of convergence that characterizes such spaces. The key point is here to allow different grades of convergence, where these grades are interpreted as values in the quantale. In this sense, a filter in a quantale-valued (partial) metric space converges to a point with a certain grade. We obtain in this way a family of convergence structures on a set indexed by the quantale. For the unit interval as ”index set” spaces with such towers of convergence structures were first studied by Richardson and Kent under the name probabilistic convergence spaces [26]. In a more general setting, quantale-valued convergence towers are considered in [15]. In this paper, we identify a set of axioms, such that the quantale-valued (partial) convergence tower spaces satisfying these axioms can be identified with quantale-valued (partial) metric spaces. The paper is organized as follows. In the second section, we collect the necessary concepts and notions from lattice theory and fix the notation. In the third section, we study quantale-valued metric spaces and quantale-valued convergence tower spaces and their relationship. The fourth section then states an axiom which ensures the isomorphy of quantale-valued metric spaces and a category of quantale-valued convergence tower spaces satisfying this axiom. In a similar fashion, in Section 5, it is shown that quantale-valued partial convergence tower spaces satisfying certain axioms can be used to character- ize quantale-valued partial metric spaces. Finally, in Section 6, we apply our results and state a quantale-valued metrization theorem for quantale-valued convergence tower groups. 2. Preliminaries Let L be a complete lattice. We assume that L is non-trivial in the sense that ⊤ 6= ⊥ for the top element ⊤ and the bottom element ⊥. In any complete lattice L we can define the well-below relation α ✁ β if for all subsets D ⊆ L such that β ≤ ∨ D there is δ ∈ D such that α ≤ δ. Then α ≤ β whenever α✁β and α ✁ ∨ j∈J βj iff α ✁ βi for some i ∈ J. A complete lattice is completely c© AGT, UPV, 2018 Appl. Gen. Topol. 19, no. 1 130 Characterization of L-(partial) metric spaces by convergence distributive (sometimes called constructively completely distributive) if and only if we have α = ∨ {β : β ✁ α} for any α ∈ L, [25]. (For a more accessible proof of the equivalence of this condition with the classical concept of complete distributivity in the presence of the Axiom of Choice see e.g. Theorem 7.2.3 in [1].) In a completely distributive lattice L, from α ✁ β = ∨ {γ ∈ L : γ ✁ β} we infer the existence of γ ∈ L such that α✁γ ✁β, i.e. L satisfies the so-called interpolation property. For more results on lattices we refer to [10]. The triple L = (L,≤,∗), where (L,≤) is a complete lattice, is called a quantale [27] if (L,∗) is a semigroup, and ∗ is distributive over arbitrary joins, i.e. ( ∨ i∈J αi ) ∗ β = ∨ i∈J (αi ∗ β) and β ∗ ( ∨ i∈J αi ) = ∨ i∈J (β ∗ αi). A quantale L = (L,≤,∗) is called commutative if (L,∗) is a commutative semi- group and it is called integral if the top element of L acts as the unit, i.e. if α ∗ ⊤ = ⊤ ∗ α = α for all α ∈ L. A quantale L = (L,≤,∗) is called an MV- algebra [13], if for all α,β ∈ L we have (α → β) → β = α∨β. In a quantale we can define an implication operator by α → β = ∨ {γ ∈ L : α ∗ γ ≤ β}. Then δ ≤ α → β if and only if δ ∗ α ≤ β. We consider in this paper only commutative and integral quantales L = (L,≤,∗) with completely distributive lattices L. Example 2.1. A triangular norm or t-norm is a binary operation ∗ on the unit interval [0,1] which is associative, commutative, non-decreasing in each argu- ment and which has 1 as the unit. The triple L = ([0,1],≤,∗) can be considered as a quantale if the t-norm is left-continuous. The three most commonly used (left-continuous) t-norms are: • the minimum t-norm: α ∗ β = α ∧ β, • the product t-norm: α ∗ β = α · β, • the Lukasiewicz t-norm: α ∗ β = (α + β − 1) ∨ 0. For the minimum t-norm we obtain α → β = { ⊤ if α ≤ β β if α > β . For the product t-norm we have α → β = β α ∧ 1 and for the Lukasiewicz t-norm we have α → β = (1 − α + β) ∧ 1. Example 2.2. [19] The interval [0,∞] with the opposite order and addition as the quantale operation α ∗ β = α + β (extended by α + ∞ = ∞ + a = ∞ for all α,β ∈ [0,∞]) is a quantale L = ([0,∞],≥,+), see e.g. [9]. We have here α → β = (β − α) ∨ 0. Example 2.3. A function ϕ : [0,∞] −→ [0,1], which is non-decreasing, left- continuous on (0,∞) – in the sense that for all x ∈ (0,∞) we have ϕ(x) = supz 0 and ϕ ∈ ∆+ the (ϕ,ǫ)-neighbourhood of x ∈ X by Nϕ,ǫx = {y ∈ X : d(x,y)(u + ǫ) + ǫ ≥ ϕ(u) ∀u ∈ [0, 1 ǫ )}. and define the ϕ-neighbourhood filter of x ∈ X, Nϕx as the filter generated by the sets Nϕ,ǫx , ǫ > 0. If we define x ∈ c̃dϕ(F) ⇐⇒ F ≥ N ϕ x then we obtain a left-continuous and pretopological L-convergence tower space (X,c̃d). In order to show that this L-convergence tower space coincides with the L-convergence tower space (X,cd), we need the following results from [29]. For ϕ ∈ ∆+ and 0 ≤ ǫ ≤ 1 we define ϕǫ ∈ ∆+ by ϕǫ(u) =    0 if u = 0 (ϕ(u + ǫ) + ǫ) ∧ 1 if 0 < u ≤ 1 ǫ 1 if u > 1 ǫ . Clearly then ϕ ≤ ϕǫ and Tardiff [29] shows that y ∈ Nϕ,ǫx if and only if d(x,y)ǫ ≥ ϕ and ϕ ≥ ψ if and only if for all ǫ > 0 we have ϕǫ ≥ ψ. The last assertion implies that for ϕ ∈ ∆+ we have ϕ = ∧ ǫ>0 ϕ ǫ. We will need the following results. Lemma A. Let ϕj ∈ ∆ + for all j ∈ J and let 0 ≤ ǫ ≤ 1. Then ( ∨ j∈J ϕj) ǫ = ∨ j∈J(ϕ ǫ j) and ( ∧ j∈J ϕj) ǫ = ∧ j∈J(ϕ ǫ j). c© AGT, UPV, 2018 Appl. Gen. Topol. 19, no. 1 135 G. Jäger and T. M. G. Ahsanullah Proof. We only show the second assertion, the first one being similar. For u = 0 or u > 1 ǫ the assertion is obvious. Let 0 < u ≤ 1 ǫ . Then we have ( ∧ j∈J ϕj) ǫ(u) =  ( ∧ j∈J ϕj)(u + ǫ) + ǫ   ∧ 1 = ( ( sup v 0. So we conclude that for all U ∈ U we have Nψ,ǫx ∩ U 6= ∅, and hence, U being an ultrafilter, N ψ,ǫ x ∈ U for all ǫ > 0, i.e. Nψx ≤ U. Therefore x ∈ c̃ d ψ(U) for all ψ ✁ ϕ and from the left-continuity then also x ∈ c̃dϕ(U). This is true for all ultrafilters U ≥ F and hence, by pretopologicalness, x ∈ c̃dϕ(F). Conversely, let F ≥ Nϕx. Then, for ǫ > 0, we have ∨ F∈F ∧ y∈F d(x,y)ǫ ≥ ∧ y∈N ϕ,ǫ x d(x,y)ǫ ≥ ϕ. c© AGT, UPV, 2018 Appl. Gen. Topol. 19, no. 1 136 Characterization of L-(partial) metric spaces by convergence From Lemma A we conclude ϕ ≤ ∧ ǫ>0 ∨ F∈F ∧ y∈F d(x,y)ǫ = ∧ ǫ>0 ( ∨ F∈F ∧ y∈F d(x,y))ǫ = ∨ F∈F ∧ y∈F d(x,y) and we have x ∈ cdϕ(F). 4. The isomorphy of L-MET and L-MET-CTS We introduce the following axiom for an L-convergence tower space. We say that (X,c) ∈ |L-CTS| satisfies the axiom (LM) if for all U ∈ U(X) and all α ∈ L we have (LM) x ∈ cα(U) ⇐⇒ ∀U ∈ U,β ✁ α∃y ∈ U s.t. x ∈ cβ([y]). This axiom was introduced in [7] for probabilistic convergence spaces in the sense of Richardson and Kent [26]. Theorem 4.1. Let (X,d) ∈ |L-MET|. Then (X,cd) satisfies (LM). Proof. Let U ∈ U(X) and let α ∈ L. Let first x ∈ cdα(U) and let U ∈ U and β ✁ α. Then there is Fβ ∈ U such that for all y ∈ Fβ we have d(x,y) ≥ β. Choose y ∈ U ∩ Fβ. Then ∨ F∈[y] ∧ z∈F d(x,z) ≥ ∧ z∈U∩Fβ d(x,z) ≥ β, i.e. x ∈ cβ([y]). Conversely, let for all U ∈ U, β✁α there is y = yβ ∈ U such that x ∈ c d β([y]), i.e. such that ∨ F∈[y] ∧ z∈F d(x,z) ≥ β. Let further F ∈ U x = ∧ x∈cd β (F) F. Then, for U ∈ U in particular F ∈ [y], i.e. y ∈ F ∩ U. Hence U ∨ Ux exists and because U is an ultrafilter, we get U ≥ ∧ x∈cd β (F) F. As (X,c d) is pretopological, we conclude cdβ(U) ⊇ ⋂ x∈cd β (F) c d β(F) and we have x ∈ c d β(U). This is true for any β ✁ α and by left-continuity we obtain x ∈ cdα(U). � Proposition 4.2. Let (X,c) ∈ |L-PreMET-CTS| satisfy the axiom (LM). Then c (dc) α (F) = cα(F). Proof. Let U ∈ U(X) be an ultrafilter and let x ∈ cα(U). By the axiom (LM) we obtain, for β ✁ α that Nxβ = {y ∈ X : x ∈ cβ([y])} satisfies N x β ∩ U 6= ∅ for all U ∈ U and hence Nxβ ∈ U. Furthermore, for x ∈ cβ([y]) we have dc(x,y) ≥ β. Hence ∨ U∈U ∧ y∈U dc(x,y) ≥ ∧ y∈Nx β dc(x,y) = ∧ x∈cβ([y]) dc(x,y) ≥ β. c© AGT, UPV, 2018 Appl. Gen. Topol. 19, no. 1 137 G. Jäger and T. M. G. Ahsanullah This is true for all β✁α and hence also ∧ y∈Nx β dc(x,y) = ∧ x∈cβ([y]) dc(x,y) ≥ α, which is equivalent to x ∈ c (dc) α (U). Hence we have shown cα(U) ⊆ c (dc) α (U) for all U ∈ U(X) and because both (X,c) and (X,c(d c)) are pretopological, we have for F ∈ F(X) that cα(F) ⊆ c (dc) α (F). The converse implication is always true and so we have equality. � If we denote the subcategory of L-PreMET-CTS with objects the L-metric spaces that satisfy the axiom (LM) by L-MET-CTS, then we obtain the following main result. Theorem 4.3. The categories L-MET-CTS and L-MET are isomorphic. Remark 4.4. For L = (∆+,≤,∗) with a continuous triangle function ∗, we introduced in [14] for (X,d) ∈ |L-CTS| a different axiom (PM): For all U ∈ U(X), all ϕ ∈ ∆+ and all x ∈ X we have x ∈ cϕ(U) ⇐⇒ ∀U ∈ U,ǫ > 0 ∃y ∈ U s.t. ∨ x∈cψ([y]) ψ(u+ǫ)+ǫ ≥ ϕ(u)∀u ∈ [0, 1 ǫ ). With the notation of this paper and of Remark 3.10 then d(c̃ d) = d and if (X,c) is ∗-transitive, left-continuous and pretopological, then c̃ (dc) ϕ (F) = cϕ(F) for all ϕ ∈ ∆+ and all F ∈ F(X). It follows from this, that for an L-convergence tower space (X,c) that is ∗-transitive, left-continuous and pretopological, the axioms (PM) and (LM) are equivalent. In fact, if (PM) is true, then c̃ (dc) ϕ = cϕ and hence, using Remark 3.10, then also c (dc) ϕ = cϕ and as d c is an L-metric on X we know that (X,c) = (X,c(d c)) satisfies (LM). A similar argument shows that (LM) implies (PM). 5. L-partial metric spaces as L-convergence tower spaces An L-partial metric space [17, 22] is a pair (X,p) of a set X and a mapping p : X × X −→ L with (LPM1) p(x,y) ≤ p(x,x) for all x,y ∈ X; (LPM2) p(x,y) = p(y,x) for all x,y ∈ X; (LPM3) p(x,y) ∗ (p(y,y) → p(y,z)) ≤ p(x,z). Morphisms are defined as in L-MET and the category of L-partial metric spaces is denoted by L-PMET. For L = ([0,∞],≥,+), an L-partial metric space is a partial metric space [22]. These spaces were introduced motivated by problems in computer science, where the self-distances d(x,x) are not always zero, [21]. Independently and in much wider generality, L-partial metric spaces were introduced and studied under the name M-valued sets in [11, 12]. For L = (∆+,≤,∗), L-partial metric spaces are called probabilistic partial metric spaces in [31] and fuzzy partial metric spaces in [30]. We note that p(y,z) ≤ p(y,y) → p(y,z) and hence (LPM3) implies the transitivity axiom (LM2). c© AGT, UPV, 2018 Appl. Gen. Topol. 19, no. 1 138 Characterization of L-(partial) metric spaces by convergence In the sequel, we need to adapt the definition of L-convergence tower spaces. We relax the axiom (LC1) and replace it by (wLC1) x ∈ cα([x]) whenever cα([x]) 6= ∅. An L-partial convergence tower space is a pair (X,c) which satisfies the axioms (wLC1), (LC2), (LC3) and (LC4). With morphisms as defined before, we denote the category of L-partial convergence tower spaces by L-PCTS. We will use the same functors as defined above to embed the category of L-partial metric spaces into the category of L-partial convergence tower spaces. Only few adaptations are necessary, so that we simply repeat the results and only prove the modifications. Proposition 5.1. Let (X,p) ∈ |L-PMET|. Define x ∈ cpα(F) ⇐⇒ ∨ F∈F ∧ y∈F p(x,y) ≥ α. Then (X,cp) ∈ |L-PCTS|. Proof. We only need to prove (wLC1). As before, we can show that y ∈ cpα([x]) if and only if p(x,y) ≥ α. If y ∈ cpα([x]), then p(x,y) ≥ α and then by (LPM1) we have p(x,x) ≥ α, i.e. x ∈ cpα([x]). � We call an L-(partial) convergence tower space (X,c) strongly ∗-transitive if (LST) x ∈ cα∗(E(y)→β)([z]) whenever x ∈ cα([y]) and y ∈ cβ([z]), where E(y) = ∨ y∈cγ([y]) γ. It is called symmetric if (LS) x ∈ cα([y]) whenever y ∈ cα([x]). Lemma 5.2. If the L-(partial) convergence tower space (X,c) is strongly ∗- transitive, then it is transitive. Proof. This follows from α ∗ β ≤ α ∗ (E(y) → β) and the axiom (LC3). � Proposition 5.3. Let (X,p) ∈ |L-PMET|. Then (X,cp) is strongly ∗-transitive, left-continuous, symmetric and pretopological. Proof. We need to check the strong ∗-transitivity (LST) and the symmetry (LS). For (LST) we first note that E(y) = ∨ y∈c p β ([y]) β = ∨ β≤p(y,y) β = p(y,y). Let x ∈ cpα([y]) and y ∈ c p β ([z]). Then α ≤ p(x,y) and β ≤ p(y,z) and hence α ∗ (E(y) → β) ≤ p(x,y) ∗ (p(y,y) → p(y,z)) ≤ p(x,z) and hence x ∈ pα∗(E(y)→β)([z]). For (LS), let x ∈ c p α([y]). Then p(x,y) = p(y,x) ≥ α and hence y ∈ cpα([x]). � Proposition 5.4. Let f : (X,d) −→ (X′,d′) be an L-PMET-morphism. Then f : (X,cd) −→ (X′,cd ′ ) is continuous. Hence we have a functor from L-PMET into the category of strongly ∗- transitive, left-continuous, symmetric and pretopological L-partial convergence tower spaces, L-PrePMET-PCTS. Again, this functor is injective on objects. c© AGT, UPV, 2018 Appl. Gen. Topol. 19, no. 1 139 G. Jäger and T. M. G. Ahsanullah In the sequel, we have to restrict the lattice context quite strongly. We say that the quantale L = (L,≤,∗) satisfies the axiom (DM2) if for all non-empty index sets J we have (DM2) α → ∨ j∈J βj = ∨ j∈J(α → βj) for all α,βj ∈ L(j ∈ J). Examples for quantales that satisfy (DM2) are complete MV-algebras and also L = ([0,∞],≥,+). In general, L = (∆+,≤,∗) does not satisfy (DM2). We show this with the following example. Example 5.5. We consider the triangle function induced by the product t- norm defined by ϕ ∗ ψ(u) = ϕ(u) · ψ(u) for all u ∈ [0,∞]. We define for each natural number n ∈ IN the distance distribution function ϕn ∈ ∆ + by ϕn(u) = n(u−1) for 1 ≤ u ≤ 1+ 1 n . Then ∨ n∈IN ϕn = ε1 and hence ε1 → ∨ n∈IN ϕn = ε0. On the other hand it is not difficult to show that ε1 → ϕn = ϕn and hence ∨ n∈IN (ε1 → ϕn) = ε1. Proposition 5.6. Let the quantale L = (L,≤,∗) satisfy the axiom (DM2). Let (X,c) ∈ |L-PrePMET-PCTS| and define pc(x,y) = ∨ x∈cα([y]) α. Then (X,pc) ∈ |L-PMET|. Proof. (LPM1) We have, using (wLC1), pc(x,y) = ∨ y∈cα([x]) α = { ⊥ if cα([x]) = ∅ ≤ ∨ x∈cα([x]) α if cα([x]) 6= ∅ } ≤ pc(x,x). (LPM2) follows from the symmetry (LS). We show (LPM3). First we note that E(y) = ∨ y∈cβ([y]) β = pc(y,y). Let now x ∈ cα([y]) and y ∈ cβ([z]). With the axiom (LST) then x ∈ cα∗(E(y)→β)([z]) and hence α ∗ (E(y) → β) ≤ p c(x,z). We conclude with (DM2) and by the distributivity of the quantale operation over joins ∨ x∈cα([y]) ∨ y∈cβ([z]) (α∗(E(y) → β)) = ( ∨ x∈cα([y]) α)∗  E(y) → ∨ y∈cβ([z]) β   ≤ pc(x,z), which is nothing else than pc(x,y) ∗ (pc(y,y) → pc(y,z)) ≤ pc(x,z). � Proposition 5.7. Let the quantale L satisfy the axiom (DM2). Let f : (X,c) −→ (X′,c′) be continuous. Then f : (X,pc) −→ (X′,pc ′ ) is an L-PMET-morphism. Proposition 5.8. Let the quantale L satisfy the axiom (DM2). Let (X,p) ∈ |L-PMET|. Then p(c p) = p. Proposition 5.9. Let the quantale L satisfy the axiom (DM2). Let (X,c) ∈ |L-PMET-PCTS|. Then c (pc) α (F) ⊆ cα(F). Theorem 5.10. Let the quantale L satisfy the axiom (DM2). Then the category L-PMET can be coreflectively embedded into the category L-PrePMET-PCTS. c© AGT, UPV, 2018 Appl. Gen. Topol. 19, no. 1 140 Characterization of L-(partial) metric spaces by convergence We extend the axiom (LM) to L-partial convergence tower spaces. (LM) ∀U ∈ U(X),α ∈ L we have x ∈ cα(U) ⇐⇒ ∀U ∈ U,β ✁ α∃y ∈ U s.t. x ∈ cβ([y]). The proofs of the following results do not make use of the axiom (LC1) and hence they carry over to L-partial metric spaces without any alterations. Theorem 5.11. Let (X,p) ∈ |L-PMET|. Then (X,cp) satisfies (LM). Proposition 5.12. Let the quantale L satisfy the axiom (DM2) and let (X,c) ∈ |L-PrePMET-PCTS| satisfy the axiom (LM). Then c (pc) α (F) = cα(F). If we denote the subcategory of L-PrePMET-PCTS with objects the L-partial metric spaces that satisfy the axiom (LM) by L-PMET-PCTS, then we obtain the following main result. Theorem 5.13. Let the quantale L satisfy the axiom (DM2). Then the cate- gories L-PMET-PCTS and L-PMET are isomorphic. 6. L-metrization of L-convergence tower groups Let (X, ·) be a group with neutral element e. For filters F,G ∈ F(X), the filter F ⊙ G is generated by the sets F ⊙ G = {xy : x ∈ F,y ∈ G} for F ∈ F and G ∈ G and the filter F−1 is generated by the sets F−1 = {x−1 : x ∈ F} for F ∈ F. Definition 6.1 (see [4]). A triple (X, ·,c), where (X, ·) is a group and (X,c) is an L-convergence tower space, is called an L-convergence tower group if for all x,y ∈ X and all F,G ∈ F(X) (LCTGM) xy ∈ cα∗β(F ⊙ G) whenever x ∈ cα(F) and y ∈ cβ(G); (LCTGI) x−1 ∈ cα(F −1) whenever x ∈ cα(F). A mapping f : X −→ X′, where (X, ·,c) and (X′, ·′,c′) are L-convergence tower groups, is called an L-CTG-morphism, if f is a homomorphism between the groups (X, ·),(X′, ·′) and a morphism in L-CTS. The category of L-convergence tower groups and L-CTG-morphisms is denoted by L-CTG. For L = {0,1}, we obtain classical convergence groups [18, 6], for L = ([0,1],≤,∗) we obtain the probabilistic convergence groups in the sense of [16] and for L = (∆+,≤,∗) we obtain the probabilistic convergence groups of [4]. For L = ([0,∞],≥,+) we obtain limit tower groups [3]. An L-convergence tower group is a stratified {0,1}{0,1}L-convergence tower group in the definition of [5]. Lemma 6.2. Let (X, ·,c) ∈ |L-CTG| and let α ∈ L, x ∈ X and F ∈ F(X). Then x ∈ cα(F) if and only if e ∈ cα([x −1] ⊙ F). Proof. If x ∈ cα(F) then by (LC1) and (LCTGM) we conclude e = x −1x ∈ c⊤∗α([x −1] ⊙ F) = cα([x −1] ⊙ F). Conversely, if e ∈ cα([x −1] ⊙ F), then x = xe ∈ c⊤∗α([x] ⊙ [x −1] ⊙ F) = cα(F). � Lemma 6.3. Let (X, ·,c) ∈ |L-CTG|. Then (X,c) is ∗-transitive. c© AGT, UPV, 2018 Appl. Gen. Topol. 19, no. 1 141 G. Jäger and T. M. G. Ahsanullah Proof. Let x ∈ cα([y]) and y ∈ cβ([z]). Then e ∈ cα([x −1] ⊙ [y]) and e ∈ cβ([y −1] ⊙ [z]). By (LCTGM) then e = ee ∈ cα∗β([x −1] ⊙ [y] ⊙ [y−1] ⊙ [z]) = cα∗β([x −1] ⊙ [z]) and hence x ∈ cα∗β([z]). � Definition 6.4. A triple (X, ·,d) is called an L-metric group if d is invariant, i.e. if d(x,y) = d(xz,yz) = d(zx,zy) for all x,y,z ∈ X. A group homomor- phism f : (X, ·) −→ (X′, ·′) between the L-metric groups (X, ·,d),(X′, ·′,d′) is called an L-METG-morphism if it is an L-metric morphism between (X,d) and (X′,d′). The category of L-metric groups is denoted by L-METG. This definition is motivated by the following result, where we use, for an L-metric d : X × X −→ L on X, the product L-metric on X × X defined by d ⊛ d : (X × X) × (X × X) −→ L, d ⊛ d((x,y),(x′,y′)) = d(x,x′) ∗ d(y,y′). Lemma 6.5. Let (X, ·) be a group and let d : X × X −→ L be an L-metric which is symmetric, i.e. for which d(x,y) = d(y,x) for all x,y ∈ X holds. Then the L-metric d is invariant if and only if the mappings m : X ×X −→ X, m(x,y) = xy and i : X −→ X, i(x) = x−1 are L-metric morphisms. Proof. Let first d be an invariant metric on X. Then using the transitivity, we obtain d ⊛ d((x,y),(x′,y′)) = d(x,x′) ∗ d(y,y′) = d(xy,x′y) ∗ d(x′y,x′y′) ≤ d(xy,x′y′) = d(m(x,y),m(x′,y′)), i.e. multiplication is an L-metric morphism. Furthermore, using the symmetry of d, we obtain d(x,y) = d(y−1xx−1,y−1yx−1) = d(y−1,x−1) = d(x−1,y−1), i.e. inversion is an L-metric morphism. For the converse, we note that, multiplication being an L-metric morphism, we have for all x,x′,y,y′ ∈ X, d(x,y) ∗ d(x′,y′) = d ⊛ d((x,x′),(y,y′)) ≤ d(xy,x′y′). In particular, we have d(x,y) = d(x,y) ∗ d(z,z) ≤ d(xz,yz) and similarly d(xz,yz) = d(xz,yz) ∗ d(z−1,z−1) ≤ d(xzz−1,yzz−1) = d(x,y). Sim- ilarly we can show that d(x,y) = d(zx,zy) and hence d is invariant. � We call an L-convergence tower group (X,c) L-metrizable if there is a sym- metric and invariant L-metric d on X such that c = cd. Theorem 6.6. An L-convergence tower group (X, ·,c) is L-metrizable if and only if it is left-continuous, pretopological, symmetric and satisfies the axiom (LM). Proof. We have seen above that if there is an L-metric d such that c = cd, then (X,c) is left-continuous, pretopological and satisfies the axiom (LM). Symmetry of (X,cd) follows easily from the symmetry of d. Conversely, let (X,c) be left-continuous, pretopological, symmetric and satisfy the axiom (LM). Then dc(x,y) = ∨ x∈cα([y]) α is a symmetric L-metric on X that satisfies cd c = c. We only need to show that dc is invariant. To this end, we note that by (LCTGM) and (LC1) we have for x,y,z ∈ X that x ∈ cα([y]) if and only if xz ∈ cα([yz]). Hence dc(xz,yz) = ∨ xz∈cα([yz]) α = ∨ x∈cα([y]) α = dc(x,y). Similarly, we see that dc(zx,zy) = dc(x,y) and hence dc is invariant. � c© AGT, UPV, 2018 Appl. Gen. Topol. 19, no. 1 142 Characterization of L-(partial) metric spaces by convergence References [1] S. Abramsky and A. Jung, Domain Theory, in: S. Abramsky, D.M. Gabby, T. S. E. Maibaum (Eds.), Handbook of Logic and Computer Science, Vol. 3, Claredon Press, Oxford 1994. [2] J. Adámek, H. Herrlich and G. E. Strecker, Abstract and Concrete Categories, Wiley, New York, 1989. [3] T. M. G. Ahsanullah and G. Jäger, On approach limit groups and their uniformization, Int. J. Contemp. Math. Sciences 9 (2014), 195–213. [4] T. M. G. Ahsanullah and G. Jäger, Probabilistic uniformization and probabilistic metrization of probabilistic convergence groups, Math. Slovaca 67 (2017), 985–1000. [5] T. M. G. Ahsanullah and G. Jäger, Stratified LMN-convergence tower groups and their stratified LMN-uniform convergence tower structures, Fuzzy Sets and Systems 330 (2018), 105–123. [6] R. Beattie and H.-P. Butzmann, Convergence Structures and Applications to Functional Analysis, Springer Science & Business Media, 2002. [7] P. Brock, Probabilistic convergence spaces and generalized metric spaces, Int. J. Math. and Math. Sci. 21 (1998), 439–452. [8] P. Brock and D. C. Kent, Approach spaces, limit tower spaces, and probabilistic con- vergence spaces, Appl. Cat. Structures 5 (1997), 99–110. [9] R. C. Flagg, Quantales and continuity spaces, Algebra Univers. 37 (1997), 257–276. [10] G. Gierz, K. H. Hofmann, K. Keimel, J. D. Lawson, M. W. Mislove and D. S. Scott, Continuous lattices and domains, Cambridge University Press 2003. [11] U. Höhle, M-valued sets and sheaves over integral cl-monoids, in: S.E. Rodabaugh, E.P. Klement and U. Höhle (eds.), Applications of category theory to fuzzy subsets, Kluwer, Boston 1992, 33–72. [12] U. Höhle, Presheaves over GL-monoids, in: U. Höhle and E.P. Klement (eds.), Non- classical logics and their applications to fuzzy subsets, Kluwer, Boston 1995, 127–157. [13] U. Höhle, Commutative, residuated l-monoids, in: Non-classical logics and their ap- plications to fuzzy subsets (U. Höhle, E.P. Klement, eds.), Kluwer, Dordrecht 1995, 53–106. [14] G. Jäger, A convergence theory for probabilistic metric spaces, Quaestiones Math. 38 (2015), 587–599. [15] G. Jäger, Stratified LMN-convergence tower spaces, Fuzzy Sets and Systems 282 (2016), 62–73. [16] G. Jäger and T. M. G. Ahsanullah, Probabilistic limit groups under a t-norm, Topology Proc. 44 (2014), 59–74. [17] R. Kopperman, S. Matthews and H. Pajoohesh, Partial metrizability in value quantales, Applied General Topology 5 (2004), 115–127. [18] H.-J. Kowalsky, Limesraume und Komplettierung, Math. Nachrichten 12 (1954), 301– 340. [19] F. W. Lawvere, Metric spaces, generalized logic, and closed categories, Rendiconti del Seminario Matematico e Fisico di Milano 43 (1973), 135–166. Reprinted in: Reprints in Theory and Applications of Categories 1 (2002), 1–37. [20] R. Lowen, Approach spaces. The missing link in the topology-uniformity-metric triad, Claredon Press, Oxford 1997. [21] S. G. Matthews, Metric domains for completeness, PhD thesis, University of Warwick, 1985. [22] S. G. Matthews, Partial metric topology, Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences 728 (1994), 183–197. [23] G. Preuss, Theory of topological structures, D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dor- drecht/Boston/Lancaster/Tokyo 1988. [24] G. Preuss, Foundations of topology. An approach to convenient topology, Kluwer Aca- demic Publishers, Dordrecht 2002. c© AGT, UPV, 2018 Appl. Gen. Topol. 19, no. 1 143 G. Jäger and T. M. G. Ahsanullah [25] G. N. Raney, A subdirect-union representation for completely distributive complete lattices, Proc. Amer. Math. Soc. 4 (1953), 518–512. [26] G. D. Richardson and D. C. Kent, Probabilistic convergence spaces, J. Austral. Math. Soc. (Series A) 61 (1996), 400–420. [27] K. I. Rosenthal, Quantales and Their Applications, Pitman Research Notes in Mathe- matics 234, Longman, Burnt Mill, Harlow 1990. [28] B. Schweizer and A. Sklar, Probabilistic metric spaces, North Holland, New York, 1983. [29] R. M. Tardiff, Topologies for probabilistic metric spaces, Pacific J. Math. 65 (1976), 233–251. [30] J. Wu and Y. Yue, Formal balls in fuzzy partial metric spaces, Iranian J. Fuzzy Systems 14 (2017), 155–164. [31] Y. Yue, Separated ∆+-valued equivalences as probabilistic partial metric spaces, Journal of Intelligent & Fuzzy Systems 28 (2015), 2715–2724. c© AGT, UPV, 2018 Appl. Gen. Topol. 19, no. 1 144