Microsoft Word - issue3.docx
17
Questioning, Context-Sensitiveness and Philosophical Inquiry
Paniel Reyes-Cárdenas
Faculty of Philosophy & Humanities UPAEP
Av 9 Pte 1908, Barrio de Santiago, 72410 Puebla, Pue., Mexico
+52 (222) 229 94 00
panielosberto.reyes@upaep.mx
J. Martín Castro-Manzano
Faculty of Philosophy & Humanities UPAEP
Av 9 Pte 1908, Barrio de Santiago, 72410 Puebla, Pue., Mexico
+52 (222) 229 94 00
josemartin.castro@upaep.mx
Abstract:
This paper aims to explain that context-sensitiveness is a very important aspect of
philosophical inquiry, specifically through the activity of questioning. The activity of questioning
fulfills a number of epistemic tasks; these render the inquirer to understand what is relevant about a
context of a determinate inquiry, philosophical or otherwise. In revealing what is relevant for
formulating questions it is also noted that fallibilism enters the picture of the establishing of a
questioning activity: it shows us that the road of inquiry is relentless and we ought to not block it by
context-insensitive questioning.
Keywords: Philosophical questioning, inquiry, contextualist epistemology, fallibilism
1. Introduction
It has been said that the impact of philosophy is dim and hardly relevant for interdisciplinary
approaches: epistemology, in fact, might be considered for some an unhealthy obsession for
achieving a certainty about knowledge that is nowhere to be found, this due to either our fickle
natures or to relativistic opinions. This pessimistic opinion can be proved misguided and wrong,
since it lacks the acknowledgement of the huge informative methodological impact that philosophy
has comported to a number of disciplines ranging from the experimental sciences to the social
sciences and even in technology: philosophical inquiry and epistemology can be hugely beneficial
in organizing ourselves in a self-controlled quest for knowledge. In short, epistemology seems to
entertain doubts and concerns far from our every day worries, to come up with examples that
challenge our common sense, and to establish a very elaborate standard for what we call
knowledge; however, we can benefit from all these activities if we focus on the inquisitive character
they have, and how they push the limits of what we take to know.
It is true, however, that a great deal of the philosophical literature in epistemology seems to
concern about worries that have little or no bearings in actual knowledge acquisition. Much of the
literature on justification seems to stem from an obsession of getting warrants of far-fetched
scenarios such as that we are not deceived brains in sophisticated nerve-stimulating buckets or
deceived by evil dream-leading genies. This, however, does not have to be the case, as
epistemology has the talent to help philosophical and non-philosophical inquiry to carry on further,
even when there are complications to our ways of finding a truth relevant to an aim.
Indeed, we can push forward knowledge if we acquire the skills to make it relevant to a
context and we can discover that through the systematic study of questions, rather than propositions
that represent achieved knowledge. In this paper I reject the claim that epistemology is unimportant
in helping us pursue settling problems by introducing three philosophical topics crucial to Inquiry in
all disciplines of knowledge and methodology in and outside philosophy.
We need to see how common sense beliefs, inquiry, and our more fundamental epistemic
practices, entail considerations of context that raise activities and have practical bearings beyond the
small circle of professionals in epistemology. I will (1) speak about Inquiry as a goal-directed
BRAIN – Broad Research in Artificial Intelligence and Neuroscience, Volume 9, Issue 3 (September, 2018)
ISSN 2067-3957
18
activity that generates beliefs, and then (2) I will characterize inquiry as a process of questioning in
a systematic manner that (3) takes for granted the context-sensitiveness and fallibilism of those
beliefs. I shall conclude that philosophical inquiry expressed in questioning is not only beneficial
but also essential for the systematic progress of human knowledge.
2. The aims of inquiry
As mentioned above, Inquiry can be defined as a goal-directed activity, and what we reach as
an aim of inquiry is a belief that we want to hold as true. We can focus in two aims in this goal-
directed process: we can either concentrate in finding a proposition p that fits the purpose of being
the response to a relevant and pungent question or we can try to find ways of settling the kind of
propositions that would make the question to settle upon, in both cases we are in the search for a
belief that needs to be fixed, but the emphasis can be on the proposition to achieve or in the context
that will make that proposition become salient. In a series of famous papers in which pragmatism
was for the first time popularized, Charles Peirce (1878) observed, against the traditional inflated
doubt of the Cartesian inquirer, that doubts are prompted by forces external to us, i.e., a genuine
doubt represents an “irritation” that is to be settled by a belief:
Nor must we overlook a third point of difference. Doubt is an uneasy and dissatisfied state
from which we struggle to free ourselves and pass into the state of belief; while the latter is a calm
and satisfactory state which we do not wish to avoid, or to change to a belief in anything else. On
the contrary, we cling tenaciously, not merely to believing, but to believing just what we do believe
(Peirce, 1877, 3; EP 1: 110).
Now, in order to perform inquiries that will allow us to settle genuine doubts by a belief, we
need to have impinging doubts that prompt us to carry on in the way of inquiry, such are the cases
of the so-called big questions, but it also applies for concrete inquiries. Unless we take the logic of
questions seriously, we shall have a flawed understanding of central issues in the philosophies of
language and mind: assertions and beliefs are elicited or activated by questions and questioning.
(see Hookway 1990, 10) Some aspects of this questioning activity are the following, and they are
first and foremost characteristics of questions in epistemology:
- Through questions we can formulate cognitive goals, i.e., we can establish what kind of
responses to those questions actually will work as answers, and whether more questions
have to be asked in this process.
- By the use of contextual aspects of a question we can elicit information: we surely will
come across propositional information, but the emphasis of this paper wants to underlie that
propositional information is secondary to the aim of generating questions that permit us to
say that we are carrying a self-controlled activity.
- Questions are used to have indirect complements in reflection, to exercise regulative
control over inquires (see Hintikka, 2007).
- Questions are formulated in a pragmatic or contextual consideration: we cannot answer our
questions if the beliefs or propositions we have come across do not make a difference in the
ways we should act or respond, should we be presented with a similar situation.
The above considerations are aimed to express some of the roles that are played by
questions in order to achieve the aims of our inquiry. Stressing the value of questions over
propositions is not a matter of preference in the epistemic domain, what we want to say is that
focusing in the kind of questions we can articulate will render us more propositional information
than focusing on the justification of a particular proposition. The belief that the question aims to
settle is expressed in propositional form, but arriving at it requires the process of inquiry. Presuming
that things can be the other way round equates to claim that we know the answers before asking the
questions, but in that case we do not really need the inquiring activity.
Thus, for example, if I ask questions as to how far a galaxy is from us I might also be
interested in questioning for the methods to find out that distance and other scientifically interesting
P. Reyes-Cárdenas, J. M. Castro-Manzano - Questioning, Context-Sensitiveness and Philosophical Inquiry
19
questions: I could use that information in a creative way perhaps by questioning if that distance is
actually stable or changing due the alleged expansion of the universe, or whether the distances
represent some stage of the universe’s development and the like. But common-day inquiries also are
favoured: suppose I am interested in getting a flight from Helsinki to London: I can ask how to do
the online booking and the like, but knowing that I can also ask about times when the price is low
can actually help me save resources or optimise the flight, asking whether there are particular
restrictions (even though my initial answers are settled), can make me change my mind about
buying a deceivingly cheap flight and rather get another route, etc.
3. Questioning as inquiring
Our best way to understand concepts such as the concept of knowledge is by examining
their role in regulating our inquiries. A dynamic conception of knowledge is suited to favour inquiry
rather than the static picture: suppose I know that p, how can I take a dynamic stance in my
propositional state of knowing it? I can maybe ask: what is the belief that p good for? And if I can
have salient considerations that can impact other related concepts then I am in a good place to see if
the consequences of knowing that p are promising to push knowledge forward, rather than
contemplating a system of beliefs. Questions establish our cognitive goals, so therefore our
progress in inquiry can be monitored and traced if we can discover to what extend we have
answered a relevant question. Doing questions elicits salient considerations if an inquiry is to
prosper. The way we know that these considerations keep being relevant is if we can keep asking
surrogate questions that push the road of inquiry forward. The way of inquiry is effectively push if
it has the following order: a question prompts a problem to solve, this generates more questions and
subordinate inquiries and so on… this process, if it is properly bound by a continuous aim of
solving a problem in the road of inquiry, represents a dynamic (as well as unified) view of our
inferential activities.
Consider the case of a murder, if I am a detective it won’t be any wise to ask: “who killed
x?” I rather ask: who had any relevant relationship R that was relevant as a cause for the murder of
x? A detective will have to know if she can keep asking questions that elicit explanations, but the
most interesting thing is that the responses can be formulated in the interrogative mode and still be
relevant.
4. Epistemic contextualism
Contextualism is a strand of epistemology that focuses knowledge-attribution not only in the
proposition itself, but also in the situation in which the attributor of the proposition is. There are
many versions of contextualism; many of them are aimed to defuse sceptical challenges, so as to
permit to consider if a sceptic challenge is actually salient. I will avoid spending too much of this
space explaining what the nuances of different versions of contextualism (for detailed accounts see
Rysiew 2016). My aim is to show the reader that taking seriously our context can help us to be more
sensitive to what a real doubt prompts. Contextualism, so understood, is the proposition that
“knowing” is an activity that ought to be relevant to a context, the context is the situation that will
require higher or lesser standards for some belief to count as knowledge. As I see it, contextualism
does not strip away the importance of either truth or justification, but articulates these around the
process of a living problem or a body of problems: truth is something we want to count as settled
belief for a problem, and justification is the explanation of how this is so.
Consider cases in which two groups of people can have questions about a matter that
depends highly in fallible hypotheses: imagine one group of people is a group that survived a
shipwreck in the middle of the Pacific Ocean and happened to find themselves in a desert island.
Now imagine that the other group of people is a team of relatives and rescue squads that have
searched for them for months. After an extended period of time they start to entertain that there
were no survivors: they fallibly, but steadily start to entertain that probably that will be the kind of
proposition that will settle the matter. However, for the group of survivors the entertainment of that
hypothesis is completely implausible, as they have survived! So in a way the context seems to give
BRAIN – Broad Research in Artificial Intelligence and Neuroscience, Volume 9, Issue 3 (September, 2018)
ISSN 2067-3957
20
reasons to the other group to entertain the no-survivors hypothesis, while the group of survivors
needs to hold on to questioning how they might solve their conundrum of made themselves found.
In the example presented, we can appreciate that the context of both groups (attributors of
propositions) has entirely different epistemic scenarios about one question. The two groups do not
claim to have contradictory knowledge about one situation, but differing contexts that render each
of them different accesses to knowledge.
5. How questions can connect to contexts?
We can consider the value of questions in two ways: one of them is to look at the semantic
content of the question itself; in which case we need to see whether is a “who-question”, “why-
question” etc. Questions also offer an explanatory contrast among competing explanations, so they
seem as important as propositions to render inquiry going (Cross, Charles, & Roelofsen, 2016: 1).
The semantic content of questions is a fundamental ability to use them properly, but it is not all
there is to questions. Indeed, the other kind of considerations about questions is how they relate to
contexts: if a question is relevant that will not be revealed by its semantic content, but the pragmatic
considerations that the question releases. Suppose that I am interested in finding out whether a
personality disorder, in the context of psychological inquiry, is an indicator of a mental illness: the
semantic content will take me as far as identifying if there is a meaningful correlation between the
two concepts. But if I want to discover whether this is the case for a particular person I also need to
ask questions that have pragmatic considerations sensitive to the context of a patient such as
questions of her personal history, family relations, and the like. The more a question produces a
subordinate inquiry the more promising is, pragmatically speaking. But how to know if a question is
sensitive to the context in pragmatic grounds. Keith DeRose, a prominent contextualist
epistemologist, proposes the “rule of sensitivity” in these words:
When it is asserted that some subject S knows (or does not know) some proposition P, the
standards for knowledge (the standards of how good an epistemic position one must be in to
count as knowing) tend to be raised, if need be, to such a level as to require S’s belief in that
particular P to be sensitive for it to count as knowledge. (DeRose, 1995, 36)
The activity of questioning, in my opinion, is the best way to find out what is relevant for a
context, and how the knowledge-attribution gets its main property: salience. Salience is the fact that
there is a relevant relation between a proposition and how an inquiry can be pushed forward. The
value of the salience of a particular proposition can be put to a test if it renders responses that, as a
subordinate inquiry, can be put in the interrogative mode.
Thus, for example, consider the case of a solicitor trying to find a way to excuse her client
from the enforcement of a particular law due to an exceptional circumstances: she will need to ask
different questions; possibly how the law can be interpreted, will have to find another cases that
render flexibility to that interpretation in which she can ask why the law was interpreted otherwise.
She will carry on finding evidence of different situations and in each case ask whether there are
similarities to the context of her client. Only if there are enough subordinate inquiries the solicitor
will be able to make her case for her client, and hence try to push for an exception to the usual
interpretation of a law.
6. Fallibilism and Context-sensitiveness
Fallibilism and Context-sensitiveness Fallibilism, as the doctrine that our beliefs must be
sensitive to error and our theories prone to correction entails a concrete philosophical character to
any kind of inquiry. However, only philosophical inquiry is wide enough to encompass the
consequences to adopt fallibilism. Fallibilism helps us to distinguish when a question is logically
real and relevant as a real doubt prompting inquiry.
P. Reyes-Cárdenas, J. M. Castro-Manzano - Questioning, Context-Sensitiveness and Philosophical Inquiry
21
So a question is locally real (for a community) when that community recognizes some things
as straight answers to it, and recognizes that some evidence would favour one of those answers over
the rest (Hookway, 2008, 17), that it is its cognitive frame, but we must recognise that we do not
hold absolute certainty for any of our beliefs. Even in well-settled beliefs as those coming from
mathematics or logic, there is always room for improvement or revision (see Priest, Tanaka, and
Weber, 2015).
Fallibilism is the negation that knowledge works as a fixed body of beliefs that remains
unaltered and can be contemplated back without change. A fallibilist will rather consider that
beliefs are, in Peirce’s happy expression: strands of a cable rather than links on a chain: i.e., their
effectiveness comes from the joint way they overlap with other relevant beliefs, but these are
always developing.
This conclusive aspect of fallibilism is good news, though: it means that our cognitive
interest meets a balance with our pragmatic interest, and makes our beliefs sensitive to context and,
even more importantly, sensitive to error. In this paper this relationships between inquiry, the
context-sensitiveness of beliefs and the importance of questioning will become apparent. Examples
on how to apply these epistemic virtues beyond epistemology and philosophy will be shown.
Acknowledgments
We would like to express gratitude to Sally Haslanger, who gave great insights as to extend
applications of what is expressed here in an early version of this paper presented in Rotterdam.
Thanks also to Chris Hookway, source of many interesting conversations in which we can
reconsider the importance of questions.
References
Belnap, N., & Steel, T. (1976) The Logic of Questions and Answers, New Haven: Yale University
Press.
Cross, C., & Roelofsen, F. (2016). "Questions", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring
2016 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL:
.
De Rose, K. (1995). “Solving the Skeptical Problem”, The Philosophical Review, 104(1), pp. 1–52.
Hintikka, J. H. (1974). “Questions about Questions”, in Semantics and Philosophy, M. Munitz (ed.),
New York: NYU Press.
–––. (1976). The Semantics of Questions and the Questions of Semantics: Case Studies in the
Interrelations of Logic, Semantics, and Syntax (Acta Philosophica Fennica, 28 (4)),
Amsterdam: North-Holland Publishing Company.
–––. (1983). “New Foundations for a Theory of Questions and Answers”, in Questions and
Answers, Ferenc Kiefer (ed.), Dordrecht: Reidel, pp. 159–190.
Hookway, C. (1996). “Questions of Context”, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 96 (Part 1):
pp. 1–16.
–––. (2008) “Questions, Epistemology, and Inquiries”, Grazer Philosophische Studien, 77, pp. 1-21
Misak, C. (1987). “Peirce, Levi and the Aims of Inquiry”, Philosophy of Science, 54, 2.
–––. (2004). Truth and the End of Inquiry, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Peirce, C. S. (1877/1878). “The Fixation of Belief” and “How to Make our Ideas Clear”, in The
Essential Peirce, Vol. I. ed. Nathan Houser and Christian Kloesel. Bloomington: Indiana
University Press.
Priest, G., Tanaka, K., & Weber, Z. (2015). "Paraconsistent Logic", The Stanford Encyclopedia of
Philosophy (Spring 2015 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL:
.
Rysiew, P. (2016). "Epistemic Contextualism", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer
2016 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL:
.