Microsoft Word - Issue-2_Volume-10_All-Articles.docx 26 Neutrosophic Modal Logic Florentin Smarandache University of New Mexico 705 Gurley Ave., Gallup, New Mexico 87301, USA Phone: +1 505-277-0111 fsmarandache@gmail.com Abstract We introduce now for the first time the neutrosophic modal logic. The Neutrosophic Modal Logic includes the neutrosophic operators that express the modalities. It is an extension of neutrosophic predicate logic and of neutrosophic propositional logic. 1. Introduction The paper extends the fuzzy modal logic (Girle, 2010; HΓ‘jek & HarmancovΓ‘, 1993; & Liau & Pen Lin, 1992), fuzzy environment (Hur et. al., 2006) and neutrosophic sets, numbers and operators (Liu et. al., 2014; Liu & Shi, 2015; Liu & Tang, 2016; Liu & Wang, 2016; Liu & Li, 2017; Liu & Tang, 2016; Liu et. al., 2016; Liu, 2016), together with the last developments of the neutrosophic environment {including (t,i,f)-neutrosophic algeb-raic structures, neutrosophic triplet structures, and neutrosophic overset / underset / offset} (Smarandache, 2016a; Smarandache & Ali, 2016; Smarandache, 2016b) passing through the symbolic neutrosophic logic (Smarandache, 2015), ultimately to neutrosophic modal logic. This paper also answers Rivieccioβs question on neutrosophic modalities. All definitions, sections, and notions in-troduced in this paper were never done before, neither in my previous work nor in other researchersβ. Therefore, we introduce now the Neutrosophic Modal Logic and the Refined Neutrosophic Modal Logic. Then we can extend them to Symbolic Neutrosophic Modal Logic and Refined Symbolic Neutrosophic Modal Logic, using labels instead of numerical values. There is a large variety of neutrosophic modal logics, as actually happens in classical modal logic too. Similarly, the neutrosophic accessibility relation and possible neutrosophic worlds have many interpretations, depending on each par-ticular application. Several neutrosophic modal applications are also listed. Due to numerous applications of neutrosophic modal logic (see the examples throughout the paper), the introduction of the neutrosophic modal logic was needed. Neutrosophic Modal Logic is a logic where some neutrosophic modalities have been included. Let π« be a neutrosophic proposition. We have the following types of neutrosophic modalities: I. Neutrosophic Alethic Modalities (related to truth) has three neutros-ophic operators: Neutrosophic Possibility: It is neutros-ophically possible that π«. Neutrosophic Necessity: It is neutros-ophically necessary that π«. Neutrosophic Impossibility: It is neutros-ophically impossible that π«. II. Neutrosophic Temporal Modalities (related to time) It was the neutrosophic case that π«. It will neutrosophically be that π«. And similarly: It has always neutrosophically been that π«. It will always neutrosophically be that π«. III. Neutrosophic Epistemic Modalities (related to knowledge): It is neutrosophically known that π«. F. Smarandache - Neutrosophic Modal Logic 27 IV. Neutrosophic Doxastic Modalities (related to belief): It is neutrosophically believed that π«. V. Neutrosophic Deontic Modalities: It is neutrosophically obligatory that π«. It is neutrosophically permissible that π«. 2. Neutrosophic Alethic Modal Operators The modalities used in classical (alethic) modal logic can be neutrosophicated by inserting the indeterminacy. We insert the degrees of possibility and degrees of necessity, as refinement of classical modal operators. 2.1. Neutrosophic Possibility Operator The classical Possibility Modal Operator Β«β πΒ» meaning Β«It is possible that PΒ» is extended to Neutrosophic Possibility Operator: β π« meaning Β«It is (t, i, f)-possible that π« Β», using Neutrosophic Probability, where Β«(t, i, f)-possibleΒ» means t % possible (chance that π« occurs), i % indeterminate (indeterminate-chance that π« occurs), and f % impossible (chance that π« does not occur). If π« π‘ , π , π is a neutrosophic proposition, with π‘ , π , π subsets of [0, 1], then the neutrosophic truth-value of the neutrosophic possibility operator is: β π« = sup π‘ , inf π , inf π , (1) which means that if a proposition P is π‘ true, π indeterminate, and π false, then the value of the neutrosophic possibility operator β π« is: sup π‘ possibility, inf π indeterminate- possibility, and inf π impossibility. For example. Let P = Β«It will be snowing tomorrowΒ». According to the meteorological center, the neutrosophic truth-value of π« is: π«([0.5, 0.6], (0.2, 0.4), {0.3, 0.5}), i.e. [0.5, 0.6] true, (0.2, 0.4) indeterminate, and {0.3, 0.5} false. Then the neutrosophic possibility operator is: β π« = (sup[0.5, 0.6], inf(0.2, 0.4), inf{0.3, 0.5}) = (0.6, 0.2, 0.3), i.e. 0.6 possible, 0.2 indeterminate-possibility, and 0.3 impossible. 2.2. Neutrosophic Necessity Operator The classical Necessity Modal Operator Β«β‘πΒ» meaning Β«It is necessary that PΒ» is extended to Neutrosophic Necessity Operator: β‘ π« meaning Β«It is (t, i, f)-necessary that π« Β», using again the Neutrosophic Probability, where similarly Β«(t, i, f)-necessityΒ» means t % necessary (surety that π« occurs), i % indeterminate (indeterminate-surety that π« occurs), and f % unnecessary (unsurely that π« occurs). If π« π‘ , π , π is a neutrosophic proposition, with π‘ , π , π subsets of [0, 1], then the neutrosophic truth value of the neutrosophic necessity operator is: β‘ π« = inf π‘ , sup π , sup π , (2) which means that if a proposition π« is π‘ true, π indeterminate, and π false, then the value of the neutrosophic necessity operator β‘ π« is: inf π‘ necessary, sup π indeterminate-necessity, and sup π unnecessary. Taking the previous example: π« = Β«It will be snowing tomorrowΒ», with π«([0.5, 0.6], (0.2, 0.4), {0.3, 0.5}), then the neutrosophic necessity operator is: BRAIN β Broad Research in Artificial Intelligence and Neuroscience Volume 10, Issue 2 (April, 2019), ISSN 2067-3957 28 β‘ π« = (inf[0.5, 0.6], sup(0.2, 0.4), sup{0.3, 0.5}) = (0.5, 0.4, 0.5), i.e. 0.5 necessary, 0.4 indeterminate-necessity, and 0.5 unnecessary. 2.3. Other Possibility and Necessity Operators The previously defined neutrosophic pos-sibility and respectively neutrosophic necessity operators, for π« π‘ , π , π a neutrosophic propos-ition, with π‘ , π , π subset-valued included in [0, 1], βππ« = (sup(π‘π), inf(ππ), inf(ππ)), β‘ππ« = (inf(π‘π), sup(ππ), sup(ππ)), work quite well for subset-valued (including interval-valued) neutrosophic components, but they fail for single-valued neutrosophic components because one gets βππ« = β‘ππ«. Depending on the applications, more possibility and necessity operators may be defined. Their definitions may work, mostly based on max / min / min for possibility operator and min / max / max for necessity operator ( when dealing with single-valued neutrosophic components in [0, 1] ), or based on sup / inf / inf for possibility operator and inf / sup / sup for necessity operator (when dealing with interval-valued or more general with subset-valued of neutrosophic components included in [0, 1] ): For examples. Let π« π‘ , π , π be a neutrosophic proposition, with π‘ , π , π single-valued of [0, 1], then the neutrosophic truth-value of the neutrosophic possibility operator is: β π« = ( max{π‘ , 1-π }, min{π , 1-π }, min{π , 1- π‘ } ) or β π« = ( max{π‘ , 1-π‘ }, min{π , 1-π }, min{π , 1- π } ) or β π« = (1- π , π , π ) {defined by Anas Al-Masarwah}. Let π« π‘ , π , π be a neutrosophic proposition, with π‘ , π , π single-valued of [0, 1], then the neutrosophic truth-value of the neutrosophic necessity operator is: β‘ π« = ( min{π‘ , 1-π }, max{π , 1-π }, max{π , 1- π‘ } ) or β‘ π« = ( min{π‘ , 1-π‘ }, max{π , 1-π }, max{π , 1- π } ) or β‘ π« = (π‘ , π , 1 β π‘ ) {defined by Anas Al-Masarwah}. The above six defined operators may be extended from single-valued numbers of [0, 1] to interval and subsets of [0, 1], by simply replacing the subtractions of numbers by subtractions of intervals or subsets, and βminβ by βinfβ, while βmaxβ by βsupβ. 3. Connection between Neutrosophic Possibility Operator and Neutrosophic Necessity Operator In classical modal logic, a modal operator is equivalent to the negation of the other: β π β Β¬β‘Β¬π, (3) β‘π β Β¬ β Β¬π. (4) In neutrosophic logic one has a class of neutrosophic negation operators. The most used one is: Β¬ π π(π‘, π, π) = π(π, 1 β π, π‘), (5) where t, i, f are real subsets of the interval [0, 1]. Letβs check whatβs happening in the neutros-ophic modal logic, using the previous example. One had: F. Smarandache - Neutrosophic Modal Logic 29 π«([0.5, 0.6], (0.2, 0.4), {0.3, 0.5}), then Β¬ π π« = π«({0.3, 0.5}, 1 β (0.2, 0.4), [0.5, 0.6]) = π«({0.3, 0.5}, 1 β (0.2, 0.4), [0.5, 0.6]) = π«({0.3, 0.5}, (0.6, 0.8), [0.5, 0.6]). Therefore, denoting by β π the neutrosophic equivalence, one has: Β¬ π β‘ π Β¬ π π«([0.5, 0.6], (0.2, 0.4), {0.3, 0.5}) β π β π It is not neutrosophically necessary that Β«It will not be snowing tomorrowΒ» β π It is not neutrosophically necessary that π«({0.3, 0.5}, (0.6, 0.8), [0.5, 0.6]) β π It is neutrosophically possible that Β¬ π π«({0.3, 0.5}, (0.6, 0.8), [0.5, 0.6]) β π It is neutrosophically possible that π«([0.5, 0.6], 1 β (0.6, 0.8), {0.3, 0.5}) β π It is neutrosophically possible that π«([0.5, 0.6], (0.2, 0.4), {0.3, 0.5}) β π β π π«([0.5, 0.6], (0.2, 0.4), {0.3, 0.5}) = (0.6, 0.2, 0.3). Letβs check the second neutrosophic equivalence. Β¬ π β π Β¬ π π«([0.5, 0.6], (0.2, 0.4), {0.3, 0.5}) β π β π It is not neutrosophically possible that Β«It will not be snowing tomorrowΒ» β π It is not neutrosophically possible that π«({0.3, 0.5}, (0.6, 0.8), [0.5, 0.6]) β π It is neutrosophically necessary that Β¬ π π«({0.3, 0.5}, (0.6, 0.8), [0.5, 0.6]) β π It is neutrosophically necessary that π«([0.5, 0.6], 1 β (0.6, 0.8), {0.3, 0.5}) β π It is neutrosophically necessary that π«([0.5, 0.6], (0.2, 0.4), {0.3, 0.5}) β π β‘ π π«([0.5, 0.6], (0.2, 0.4), {0.3, 0.5}) = (0.6, 0.2, 0.3). 4. Neutrosophic Modal Equivalences Neutrosophic Modal Equivalences hold within a certain accuracy, depending on the definitions of neutrosophic possibility operator and neutros-ophic necessity operator, as well as on the definition of the neutrosophic negation β employed by the experts depending on each application. Under these conditions, one may have the following neutrosophic modal equivalences: β π« π‘ , π , π β π Β¬ π β‘ π Β¬ π π« π‘ , π , π (6) β‘ π« π‘ , π , π β π Β¬ π β π Β¬ π π« π‘ , π , π (7) For example, other definitions for the neutros-ophic modal operators may be: β π« π‘ , π , π = sup π‘ , sup π , inf π , (8) or β π« π‘ , π , π = sup π‘ , , inf π etc., (9) while β‘ π« π‘ , π , π = inf π‘ , inf π , sup π , (10) or BRAIN β Broad Research in Artificial Intelligence and Neuroscience Volume 10, Issue 2 (April, 2019), ISSN 2067-3957 30 β‘ π« π‘ , π , π = inf π‘ , 2π β© [0,1], sup π (11) etc. 5. Neutrosophic Truth Threshold In neutrosophic logic, first we have to introduce a neutrosophic truth threshold, ππ» = β©π , πΌ , πΉ βͺ, where π , πΌ , πΉ are subsets of [0, 1]. We use uppercase letters (T, I, F) in order to distinguish the neutrosophic components of the threshold from those of a proposition in general. We can say that the proposition π« π‘ , π , π is neutrosophically true if: inf π‘ β₯ inf(π ) and sup π‘ β₯ sup(π ); (12) inf π β€ inf(πΌ ) and sup π‘ β€ sup(πΌ ); (13) inf π β€ inf(πΉ ) and sup π β€ sup(πΉ ). (14) For the particular case when all π , πΌ , πΉ and π‘ , π , π are single-valued numbers from the interval [0, 1], then one has: The proposition π« π‘ , π , π is neutrosophically true if: π‘ β₯ π ; π β€ πΌ ; π β€ πΉ . The neutrosophic truth threshold is established by experts in accordance to each application. 6. Neutrosophic Semantics Neutrosophic Semantics of the Neutrosophic Modal Logic is formed by a neutrosophic frame πΊ , which is a non-empty neutrosophic set, whose elements are called possible neutrosophic worlds, and a neutrosophic binary relation β , called neutrosophic accesibility relation, between the possible neutrosophic worlds. By notation, one has: β©πΊ , β βͺ. A neutrosophic world π€β² that is neutrosophically accessible from the neutrosophic world π€ is symbolized as: π€ β π€β² . In a neutrosophic model each neutrosophic proposition π« has a neutrosophic truth-value π‘ , π , π respectively to each neutrosophic world π€ β πΊ , where π‘ , π , π are subsets of [0, 1]. A neutrosophic actual world can be similarly noted as in classical modal logic as π€ β . Formalization Let π be a set of neutrosophic propositional variables. 7. Neutrosophic Formulas 1. Every neutrosophic propositional variable π« β π is a neutrosophic formula. 2. If A, B are neutrosophic formulas, then Β¬ π π΄, π΄ β§ π π΅, π΄ β¨ π π΅, π΄ β π π΅, π΄ β π π΅, and β π π΄, β‘ π π΄, are also neutrosophic formulas, where Β¬ π , β§ π , β¨ π , β π , β π , and β π , β‘ π represent the neutrosophic negation, neutrosophic intersection, neutrosophic union, neutros-ophic implication, neutrosophic equivalence, and neutrosophic possibility operator, neutrosophic necessity operator respectively. F. Smarandache - Neutrosophic Modal Logic 31 8. Accesibility Relation in a Neutrosophic Theory Let πΊ be a set of neutrosophic worlds π€ such that each π€ chracterizes the propositions (formulas) of a given neutrosophic theory π. We say that the neutrosophic world π€β² is accesible from the neutrosophic world π€ , and we write: π€ β π€β² or β (π€ , π€β² ), if for any proposition (formula) π« β π€ , meaning the neutrosophic truth-value of π« with respect to π€ is π« π‘ , π , π , one has the neutrophic truth-value of π« with respect to π€β² π« π‘ , π , π , where inf π‘ β₯ inf π‘ and sup π‘ β₯ sup π‘ ; (15) inf π β€ inf π and sup π β€ sup π ; (16) inf π β€ inf π and sup π β€ sup π (17) (in the general case when π‘ , π , π and π‘ , π , π are subsets of the interval [0, 1]). But in the instant of π‘ , π , π and π‘ , π , π as single-values in [0, 1], the above inequalities become: π‘ β₯ π‘ , (18) π β€ π , (19) π β€ π . (20) 9. Applications If the neutrosophic theory π is the Neutros-ophic Mereology, or Neutrosophic Gnosisology, or Neutrosophic Epistemology etc., the neutrosophic accesibility relation is defined as above. 9.1. Neutrosophic n-ary Accesibility Relation We can also extend the classical binary accesibility relation β to a neutrosophic n-ary accesibility relation β ( ) , for n integer β₯ 2. Instead of the classical π (π€, π€β²), which means that the world π€β² is accesible from the world π€, we generalize it to: β ( ) π€ , π€ , β¦ , π€ ; π€ , which means that the neutrosophic world π€ is accesible from the neutrosophic worlds π€ , π€ , β¦ , π€ all together. 9.2. Neutrosophic Kripke Frame π = β©πΊ , π βͺ is a neutrosophic Kripke frame, since: π. πΊ is an arbitrary non-empty neutrosophic set of neutrosophic worlds, or neutrosophic states, or neutrosophic situations. ππ. π β πΊ Γ πΊ is a neutrosophic accesibility relation of the neutrosophic Kripke frame. Actually, one has a degree of accessibility, degree of indeterminacy, and a degree of non-acces- sibility. 9.3. Neutrosophic (t, i, f)-Assignement The Neutrosophic (t, i, f)-Assignement is a neutrosophic mapping π£ : π Γ πΊ β [0,1] β¨― [0,1] β¨― [0,1] (21) where, for any neutrosophic proposition π« β π and for any neutrosophic world π€ , one defines: π£ π, π€ = π‘ , π , π β [0,1] β¨― [0,1] β¨― [0,1] (22) BRAIN β Broad Research in Artificial Intelligence and Neuroscience Volume 10, Issue 2 (April, 2019), ISSN 2067-3957 32 which is the neutrosophical logical truth value of the neutrosophic proposition π« in the neutros-ophic world π€ . 9.4. Neutrosophic Deducibility We say that the neutrosophic formula π« is neutrosophically deducible from the neutrosophic Kripke frame π , the neutrosophic (t, i, f) β assignment π£ , and the neutrosophic world π€ , and we write as: π , π£ , π€ β¨ π π«. (23) Letβs make the notation: πΌ (π«; π , π£ , π€ ) that denotes the neutrosophic logical value that the formula π« takes with respect to the neutrosophic Kripke frame π , the neutrosophic (t, i, f)-assignment π£ , and the neutrosphic world π€ . We define πΌ by neutrosophic induction: 1. πΌ (π«; π , π£ , π€ ) πππ = π£ (π«, π€ ) if π« β π and π€ β πΊ . 2. πΌ Β¬ π π«; π , π£ , π€ πππ = Β¬ π [πΌ (π«; π , π£ , π€ )]. 3. πΌ π« β§ π π; π , π£ , π€ πππ = [πΌ (π«; π , π£ , π€ )] β§ π [πΌ (π; π , π£ , π€ )] 4. πΌ π« β¨ π π; π , π£ , π€ πππ = [πΌ (π«; π , π£ , π€ )] β¨ π [πΌ (π; π , π£ , π€ )] 5. πΌ π« β π π; π , π£ , π€ πππ = [πΌ (π«; π , π£ , π€ )] β π [πΌ (π; π , π£ , π€ )] 6. πΌ β π π«; π , π£ , π€ πππ = β©sup, inf, infβͺ{πΌ (π«; π , π£ , π€ ), π€ β πΊ and π€ π π€β² }. 7. πΌ β‘ π π«; π , π£ , π€ πππ = β©inf, sup, supβͺ{πΌ (π«; π , π£ , π€ ), π€ β πΊ and π€ π π€β² }. 8. β¨ π π« if and only if π€ ββ¨ π« (a formula π« is neutrosophically deducible if and only if π« is neutrosophically deducible in the actual neutrosophic world). We should remark that πΌ has a degree of truth π‘ , a degree of indeterminacy π , and a degree of falsehood π , which are in the general case subsets of the interval [0, 1]. Applying β©sup, inf, infβͺ to πΌ is equivalent to calculating: β©sup π‘ , inf π , inf π βͺ, and similarly β©inf, sup, supβͺπΌ = β©inf π‘ , sup π , sup π βͺ. 10. Refined Neutrosophic Modal Single-Valued Logic Using neutrosophic (t, i, f) - thresholds, we refine for the first time the neutrosophic modal logic as: F. Smarandache - Neutrosophic Modal Logic 33 10.1. Refined Neutrosophic Possibility Operator β π π«( , , ) = Β«It is very little possible (degree of possibility π‘ ) that π«Β», corresponding to the threshold (π‘ , π , π ), i.e. 0 β€ π‘ β€ π‘ , π β₯ π , π β₯ π , for π‘ a very little number in [0, 1]; β π π«( , , ) = Β«It is little possible (degree of pos-sibility π‘ ) that π«Β», corresponding to the threshold (π‘ , π , π ), i.e. π‘ < π‘ β€ π‘ , π β₯ π > π , π β₯ π > π ; β¦ β¦ β¦ and so on; β π π«( , , ) = Β«It is possible (with a degree of possibility π‘ ) that π«Β», corresponding to the threshold (π‘ , π , π ), i.e. π‘ < π‘ β€ π‘ , π β₯ π > π , π β₯ π > π . 10.2. Refined Neutrosophic Necessity Operator β‘ π π«( , , ) = Β«It is a small necessity (degree of necessity π‘ ) that π«Β», i.e. π‘ < π‘ β€ π‘ , π β₯ π β₯ π , π β₯ π > π ; β‘ π π«( , , ) = Β«It is a little bigger necessity (degree of necessity π‘ ) that π«Β», i.e. π‘ < π‘ β€ π‘ , π β₯ π > π , π β₯ π > π ; β¦ β¦ β¦ and so on; β‘ π π«( , , ) = Β«It is a very high necessity (degree of necessity π‘ ) that π«Β», i.e. π‘ < π‘ β€ π‘ = 1, π β₯ π > π , π β₯ π > π . 11. Application of the Neutrosophic Threshold We have introduced the term of (t, i, f)-physical law, meaning that a physical law has a degree of truth (t), a degree of indeterminacy (i), and a degree of falsehood (f). A physical law is 100% true, 0% indeterminate, and 0% false in perfect (ideal) conditions only, maybe in laboratory. But our actual world (π€ β) is not perfect and not steady, but continously changing, varying, fluctuating. For example, there are physicists that have proved a universal constant (c) is not quite universal (i.e. there are special conditions where it does not apply, or its value varies between (π β π, π + π), for π > 0 that can be a tiny or even a bigger number). Thus, we can say that a proposition π« is neutrosophically nomological necessary, if π« is neutrosophically true at all possible neutrosophic worlds that obey the (t, i, f)-physical laws of the actual neutrosophic world π€ β. In other words, at each possible neutrosophic world π€ , neutrosophically accesible from π€ β, one has: π« π‘ , π , π β₯ ππ»(π , πΌ , πΉ ), (24) i.e. π‘ β₯ π , π β€ πΌ , and π β₯ πΉ . (25) 12. Neutrosophic Mereology Neutrosophic Mereology means the theory of the neutrosophic relations among the parts of a whole, and the neutrosophic relations between the parts and the whole. BRAIN β Broad Research in Artificial Intelligence and Neuroscience Volume 10, Issue 2 (April, 2019), ISSN 2067-3957 34 A neutrosophic relation between two parts, and similarly a neutrosophic relation between a part and the whole, has a degree of connectibility (t), a degree of indeterminacy (i), and a degree of disconnectibility (f). 12.1. Neutrosophic Mereological Threshold Neutrosophic Mereological Threshold is def-ined as: (min( ),max( ),max( ))M M M MTH t i fο½ (26) where π‘ is the set of all degrees of con-nectibility between the parts, and between the parts and the whole; π is the set of all degrees of indeterminacy between the parts, and between the parts and the whole; π is the set of all degrees of disconnectibility between the parts, and between the parts and the whole. We have considered all degrees as single-valued numbers. 13. Neutrosophic Gnosisology Neutrosophic Gnosisology is the theory of (t, i, f)-knowledge, because in many cases we are not able to completely (100%) find whole knowledge, but only a part of it (t %), another part remaining unknown (f %), and a third part indeterminate (unclear, vague, contradictory) (i %), where t, i, f are subsets of the interval [0, 1]. 13.1. Neutrosophic Gnosisological Threshold Neutrosophic Gnosisological Threshold is defined, similarly, as: (min( ), max( ), max( ))G G G GTH t i fο½ (27) where π‘ is the set of all degrees of knowledge of all theories, ideas, propositions etc., π is the set of all degrees of indeterminate-knowledge of all theories, ideas, propositions etc., π is the set of all degrees of non-knowledge of all theories, ideas, propositions etc. We have considered all degrees as single-valued numbers. 14. Neutrosophic Epistemology And Neutrosophic Epistemology, as part of the Neutrosophic Gnosisology, is the theory of (t, i, f)-scientific knowledge. Science is infinite. We know only a small part of it (t%), another big part is yet to be discovered (f%), and a third part indeterminate (unclear, vague, contradictory) (i%). Of course, t, i, f are subsets of [0, 1]. 14.1. Neutrosophic Epistemological Threshold Neutrosophic Epistemological Threshold is defined as: (min( ), max( ), max( ))E E E ETH t i fο½ (28) where π‘ is the set of all degrees of scientific knowledge of all scientific theories, ideas, propositions etc., π is the set of all degrees of indeterminate scientific knowledge of all scientific theories, ideas, propositions etc., π is the set of all degrees of non-scientific knowledge of all scientific theories, ideas, propositions etc. We have considered all degrees as single-valued numbers. F. Smarandache - Neutrosophic Modal Logic 35 15. Conclusions We have introduced for the first time the Neutrosophic Modal Logic and the Refined Neutrosophic Modal Logic. Symbolic Neutrosophic Logic can be connected to the neutrosophic modal logic too, where instead of numbers we may use labels, or instead of quantitative neutrosophic logic we may have a quantitative neutrosophic logic. As an extension, we may introduce Symbolic Neutrosophic Modal Logic and Refined Symbolic Neutrosophic Modal Logic, where the symbolic neutrosophic modal operators (and the symbolic neutrosophic accessibility relation) have qualitative values (labels) instead on numerical values (subsets of the interval [0, 1]). Applications of neutrosophic modal logic are to neutrosophic modal metaphysics. Similarly to classical modal logic, there is a plethora of neutrosophic modal logics. Neutrosophic modal logics is governed by a set of neutrosophic axioms and neutrosophic rules. The neutrosophic accessibility relation has various interpretations, depending on the applications. Similarly, the notion of possible neutrosophic worlds has many interpretations, as part of possible neutrosophic semantics. References Girle, R. (2010). Modal Logics and Philosophy, 2nd ed., McGill-Queen's University Press. HΓ‘jek, P., & HarmancovΓ‘, D. (1993). A comparative fuzzy modal logic, in Fuzzy Logic in Artificial Intelligence, Lecture Notes in AI 695: 27-34. http://meetings.aps.org/Meeting/GEC16/Session/HT6.111 Hur, K., Kang, H. W., & Lee, K. C. (2006). Fuzzy equivalence relations and fuzzy partitions, Honam Math. J. 28: 291-315. Liau, C. J., & Lin, B. I-Pen (1992). Quantitative Modal Logic and Possibilistic Reasoning, 10th European Conference on Artificial Intelligence, 43-47. Liu, P. (2016). The aggregation operators based on Archimedean t-conorm and t-norm for the single valued neutrosophic numbers and their application to Decision Making, Int. J. Fuzzy Syst., 18(5): 849β863. Liu, P. D., & Li, H. G. (2017). Multiple attribute decision making method based on some normal neutrosophic Bonferroni mean operators, Neural Computing and Applications, 28(1), 179- 194. Liu, P. D., & Shi, L. L. (2015). The Generalized Hybrid Weighted Average Operator Based on Interval Neutrosophic Hesitant Set and Its Application to Multiple Attribute Decision Making, Neural Computing and Applications, 26(2): 457-471. Liu, P. D., & Tang, G. L. (2016). Some power generalized aggregation operators based on the interval neutrosophic numbers and their application to decision making, Journal of Intelligent & Fuzzy Systems 30: 2517β2528. Liu, P. D., & Wang, Y. M. (2016). Interval neutrosophic prioritized OWA operator and its application to multiple attribute decision making, Journal of Systems Science & Complexity, 29(3): 681-697. Liu, P. D., Chu, Y. C., Li, Y. W., & Chen, Y.B. (2014). Some generalized neutrosophic number Hamacher aggregation operators and their application to Group Decision Making, Int. J. Fuzzy Syst.,16(2): 242-255. Liu, P., & Tang, G. (2016). Multi-criteria group decision-making based on interval neutrosophic uncertain linguistic variables and Choquet integral, Cognitive Computation, 8(6), 1036- 1056. Liu, P., Zhang, L., Liu, X., & Wang, P. (2016). Multi-valued Neutrosophic Number Bonferroni mean Operators and Their Application in Multiple Attribute Group Decision Making, International Journal of Information Technology & Decision Making 15(5), 1181β1210. Smarandache, F. (2015). Symbolic Neutrosophic Theory, EuropaNova, Brussels, 2015. BRAIN β Broad Research in Artificial Intelligence and Neuroscience Volume 10, Issue 2 (April, 2019), ISSN 2067-3957 36 Smarandache, F. (2016a). Neutrosophic Overset, Neutrosophic Underset, and Neutrosophic Offset. Pons Editions, Brussels, https://arxiv.org/ftp/arxiv/papers/1607/1607.00234.pdf Smarandache, F. (2016b). Neutrosophic Overset, Neutrosophic Underset, and Neutrosophic Offset. Similarly for Neutrosophic Over-/Under-/Off- Logic, Probability, and Statistics, 168 p., Pons Editions, Brussels. Smarandache, F. (2016, May 23-27). (t, i, f)-Physical Laws and (t, i, f)-Physical Constants, 47th Annual Meeting of the APS Division of Atomic, Molecular and Optical Physics, Providence, Rhode Island, Volume 61, Number 8, Monday-Friday. Smarandache, F., & Ali, M. (2016). Neutrosophic Triplet as extension of Matter Plasma, Unmatter Plasma, and Antimatter Plasma, 69th Annual Gaseous Electronics Conference, Bochum, Germany, Volume 61, Number 9, Monday-Friday, https://arxiv.org/ftp/arxiv/papers/1512/1512.00047.pdf.