DERMATOLOGY PRACTICAL & CONCEPTUAL www.derm101.com Essay | Dermatol Pract Concept 2012;2(2):14 71 Essay Definitions Diagnosis: a judgment about what a particular illness or problem is, made after making an examination. [Cam- bridge Dictionaries Online. Diagnosis. Cambridge Uni- versity Press 2011. Accessed February 17, 2012. http:// dictionary.cambridge.org.] Diagnose (to): to recognize and name the exact character of a disease or a problem, by making an examination. [Cambridge Dictionaries Online. Diagnose. Cambridge University Press 2011. Accessed February 17, 2012. http://dictionary.cambridge.org.] Prognosis: (1) a doctor’s judgment of the likely or expected development of a disease or of the chances of getting bet- ter; (2) a statement of what is judged likely to happen in the future, especially in connection with a particular situation. Prognose (to): to make a prognosis. [Cambridge Dictionar- ies Online. Prognosis. Cambridge University Press 2011. Accessed February 17, 2012. http://dictionary.cambridge. org.] According to the definitions above, a diagnosis is an affirmation based on an examination, recognition and nam- ing of the exact character of a present disease. For example the identification of Mycobacterium tuberculosis in sputum implies a certainty: the patient has tuberculosis. All to the contrary, prognosis is a statistical computation of what might occur in the future. By its very nature, statisti- cal evaluation is uncertain. Statistics is nothing but a precise quantification of uncertainty. Diagnosis is certain; prognosis is uncertain. A patient with tuberculosis may die from his disease or he may not. Nobody will try to “adjust therapy to prognosis” for a tuberculous patient; antituberculous drugs will be prescribed. During the last few decades, and for reasons not entirely clear (some even suspect such as the redefinition of diseases according to the medications available in the market), in cases of cancer pathologists have been asked more frequently to evaluate the prognosis of (to “grade”) neoplasms on the basis of the histological characteristics of tumors. The “grad- ing systems” are more and more elaborate, proliferate every- where, occupying an ever-growing part of textbooks. This even goes to the point where diseases tend to be defined by their prognosis. It is not rare to find in the literature state- ments such as: “The evolution of dermatopathology, along with the development and introduction of new molecular biology techniques with the identification of new bio- markers, has opened a new field that may [emphasis ours] allow the classification of lesions in function of their prognoses in a completely objective and repro- ducible manner, putting an end to the eternal debates regarding the subjectivity of the currently utilized grading criteria.” [Arumi-Uria M. Dysplastic nevus: the eye of the hurricane. J Cutan Pathol. 2008;35 Suppl 2:16-9.] and even: “A diagnosis is a clinical tool that assists in the pro- cess of codifying patients into disease groups that share a common outcome and a common set of Predicting outcome: a fourfold delusion! François Milette, MD1 1 Centre Hospitalier Pierre-Boucher, Longueuil, Canada Citation: Milette F. Predicting outcome: a fourfold delusion! Dermatol Pract Conc. 2012;2(2):14. http://dx.doi.org/10.5826/dpc.0202a14. Copyright: ©2012 Milette. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License, which permits unrestricted use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original author and source are credited. Corresponding author: François Milette, M.D., Centre Hospitalier Pierre-Boucher, Longueuil, Canada. Email: francois.milette@rrsss16. gouv.qc.ca. http://dictionary.cambridge.org http://dictionary.cambridge.org http://dictionary.cambridge.org http://dictionary.cambridge.org http://dictionary.cambridge.org 72 Essay | Dermatol Pract Concept 2012;2(2):14 prognosis. For instance, it is worse to suffer from small-cell carcinoma of the lung than from basal-cell carcinoma of the skin. One is therefore justified in communicating to a patient the prognosis associated with his disease. It is even correct to specify the prognosis by specifying the diagnosis in terms cogent, for instance, by typing and sub-typing tumors according to solid morphological basis, but prognosis nev- ertheless remains a (more or less) likely statement concern- ing the future of a population of patients, whereas diagnosis must remain a sure fact concerning the present of an indi- vidual patient. The patient dying from metastatic basal-cell carcinoma does not care for a minute that he had a 99.99% chance of survival when the rare patient surviving 10 years with small-cell carcinoma of the lung has had these years spoiled by the constant threat implied that he had a 90% chance of dying as a result of his disease. And to all other patients, that information is useless. The only conceivable usefulness of prognosis is to calibre the aggressiveness of therapy: “bad” cancers are worth being treated more aggressively than “good” cancers. To this end the prognosis implied by a precise diagnosis should suffice. Other aspects of the misunderstanding of prognosis by clinicians are illustrated well by the two following examples: (1) We have seen a patient surviving 30 years with metastatic melanoma or small-cell carcinoma of the lung, who refuses to believe the diagnosis even after the slides had been reviewed and the diagnosis con- firmed. Outcome was inconsistent with the diagnosis according to them and therefore the diagnosis must have been wrong. This is nonsense. Delusion. No indi- vidual outcome is inconsistent. The chance of winning a lottery may be very low, but can you imagine a win- ner being told that the fact that he won meant that it was not a lottery to which he participated? (2) We have seen patients who thought they were cured and told by their doctor that “one never is cured from cancer” with devastating consequences. Delusion once again! Some patients are cured from even the worst cancers. In every case, moreover, the fundamental diktat of medicine, primum non nocere, must be respected; “information” such as “one never is cured from cancer” simply violates it. The third delusion afflicts the pathologist, and it is enough to make one paranoid. It is not sufficient anymore for him to make a correct diagnosis. He must now also report thickness in hundredths of millimetre, grades histological and/or cyto- logical on scales of 3, 5 and even 10, distances of margins in fractions of a millimetre, mitotic activity, percentages of tissue affected by cancer in a biopsy, presence of ulceration, necrosis, apoptotic rates, etc. And with all these “prognostic factors” added to it, his “diagnosis” soon fills two pages! Afraid of missing some “important prognostic factor” he response to therapy.” [Elder D, Elenitsas R, Johnson Jr BL, Murphy GF, Xu X (eds.) Lever’s Histopathol- ogy of the Skin. 10th ed. Philadelphia, PA: Lippincott Williams & Wilkins, 2009.] How far we are with this definition from the classic defi- nition quoted earlier that has been the cornerstone of the practice of medicine for centuries! At least such a redefinition should be the subject of a debate among pathologists but no objection, no reaction is raised in the community of patholo- gists against those assertions and against new entities defined on the basis of them. They are even received with enthusi- asm! Such profession of faith meets consensus if not unanim- ity. According to this textbook definition, penicillin sensitive pneumonia, pyelonephritis and meningitis would be one single diagnosis: each entity being able to cause death if untreated (“common outcome”) and all of them responding favourably to penicillin (“common set of response to therapy”)! In fact even if the promise of “objective” classification of lesions according to their prognoses were met (and this is far from certain even in the mind of the author of the article quoted, as implied by his use of the word “may”), prognosis would still remain what it is: an approximation of the likely outcome; never a certainty. With time this leads to a devalu- ation of diagnosis and to confusion in the understanding of diseases, to a degradation of pathology itself. Examples are numerous of the noxious consequences that result from confounding diagnosis and prognosis: It is the favorable prognosis of melanoma in situ that for years has impaired the recognition of its being melanoma; it is the “indolent clinical behavior” of small plaque parapsoriasis that continues to impair the recognition of its being mycosis fungoides; it is “outcome” of spitzoid melanoma metastatic to lymph node that purportedly justifies the flawed concept of “metastatic Spitz nevus”; it is purported indolent biologic behavior that constitutes the raison d’être of “small and medium cell cutaneous T-cell lymphoma” as an entity differ- ent from mycosis fungoides, etc. In short, defining disease according to prognosis is a delusion. No clinician is satisfied by a “likely diagnosis” and no pathologist should accept entities defined by prognosis, a “judgment of the likely or expected development of a dis- ease.” This is the first of four delusions hidden behind “pre- diction of outcome.” It concerns the very understanding of diseases and affects the students of them. The second delusion concerns the clinician and can be stated thus: informing a patient of his “individual prognosis” reveals a total misunderstanding of the nature of a progno- sis—it being a statistical value and therefore applicable only to a population of patients. It is perfectly true that various tumors have various prognoses and that any diagnosis comes with its associated Essay | Dermatol Pract Concept 2012;2(2):14 73 After all, if it is legitimate for a suffering person to ask “what will happen to me?” it is just as legitimate for a healthy person to ask, “What are my chances of getting sick?” And when experts pretend to have answered the first question, it is only a matter of time before they become tempted to answer the second, acquiring the power to cure diseases even before they occur! Ultimately this transforms risks into diseases and makes everybody sick! After all, isn’t life the ultimate risk in itself, the ultimate “disease” from which everybody shall die? Without entirely discrediting “evaluation and treatment of risks,” we wish to stress here the dark sides of it that can take delusional proportions. First, the apparent benefits of such an approach may appear as positive as to hinder any critic of it. Second, these same benefits apparently may induce, in a very delusional manner, denial of the side effects of “treating risks.” Third, economical interests generated by treating a huge number of healthy persons may create mas- sive incentive in favour of possibly useless or even harmful “risk therapy.” Fourth, patients refusing to have their risks evaluated may be refused insurability or, worse, be brought to feel guilty for their insouciance [1]. In short, a diagnosis certain must remain the cornerstone of therapy; prognosis in individual case is of little, if any, utility to a clinician and may, in many ways, be harmful to patients. Pathologists therefore should concentrate exclu- sively on the diagnosis and forget about the prognosis if they want to avoid, as modern haruspices, being the laughing stock of future generations. Reference 1. Marcotte J, Milette F. Cancer screening: I go . . . Yes . . . No . . . Perhaps later . . . Dermatopathology: Practical and Conceptual. 2008;15(1):20. http://www.derm101.com/indexDPC?issueID=57. forgets to concentrate on diagnosis. After a while it becomes necessary for him to take refuge in the no man’s land of “dys- plasia” and other “entities of unknown or indeterminate sig- nificance” and, compiling data for “predicting outcome,” he becomes something like a haruspex, this diviner of antiquity whose function was to predict, for the benefit of the Emperor (the clinician), the issue of a battle by reading in the viscerae of a sacrificed animal (the patient) (Figure 1). Poor pathologist caught in such a cruel trap of being mocked! The fourth delusion is induced in patients when, as a result of the first three delusions already described, they are informed of “their” prognosis. It may take various forms. For instance, a “good” prognosis may induce reassurance, per- haps even euphoria, only to be deceived later by facts whereas a “bad” prognosis if not inducing depression or despair, may spoil the duration of survival. More importantly perhaps, a subtle form of delusion is created in the mind of patients through a drift from “prediction of outcome” for diseased individuals to “evaluation of risks” for healthy persons. Figure 1. The bronze sheep’s liver of Piacenza, with Etruscan inscrip- tions, intended as a guide to the haruspex of Roman antiquity for “predicting outcome” of battles. [Wikipedia. Haruspex. 18 Febru- ary 2012. Accessed February 18, 2012. http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/ Haruspex.]