Symbolic Attributed Graphs for Attributed Graph Transformation Electronic Communications of the EASST Volume 30 (2010) International Colloquium on Graph and Model Transformation On the occasion of the 65th birthday of Hartmut Ehrig (GraMoT 2010) Symbolic Attributed Graphs for Attributed Graph Transformation Fernando Orejas and Leen Lambers 25 pages Guest Editors: Claudia Ermel, Hartmut Ehrig, Fernando Orejas, Gabriele Taentzer Managing Editors: Tiziana Margaria, Julia Padberg, Gabriele Taentzer ECEASST Home Page: http://www.easst.org/eceasst/ ISSN 1863-2122 http://www.easst.org/eceasst/ ECEASST Symbolic Attributed Graphs for Attributed Graph Transformation Fernando Orejas1 ∗ and Leen Lambers2 1 orejas@lsi.upc.edu Dpt. de Llenguatges i Sistemes Informátics Universitat Politècnica de Catalunya, Barcelona, Spain. 2 Leen.Lambers@hpi.uni-potsdam.de Hasso Plattner Institut Universität Potsdam, Germany Abstract: In this paper we present a new approach to deal with attributed graphs and attributed graph transformation. This approach is based on working with what we call symbolic graphs, which are graphs labelled with variables together with a formula that constrains the possible values that we may assign to these variables. In particular, in this paper we will compare in detail this new approach with the standard approach to attributed graph transformation. Keywords: Graph Transformation, Attributed Graphs, Symbolic Graphs 1 Introduction The study of graph grammars and graph transformation started 40 years ago. However, the first formal approach to deal with attributed graphs is much more recent [12], even if this kind of graphs are needed in many applications of the field. Actually, the development of the fundamen- tal theory of graph transformation for the case of attributed graphs is quite recent [7]. The reason for this late development is probably that, even if the attributed case may seem to be a straight- forward generalization of the standard case, it presents some difficulties which have hampered the development of this fundamental theory. One of these difficulties lies on the complication of putting together two theoretical frameworks, algebraic specification and graph transformation, even if both are algebraic and categorical frameworks. In fact, to avoid this problem, at least to some extent, in [12] graphs are coded as algebras with the aim of having a uniform setting. The problem is that, in general, algebra transformation does not enjoy the right properties to ensure that the basic theory of graph transformation will hold. The approach studied in [12], based on the approach presented in [10] is, in a sense, the opposite. In this case, the data algebra is embedded in the graph. More, precisely, an attributed graph is seen as a pair formed by an algebra, to define the values of the attributes of the graph, and a graph that includes all the values of the algebra as (a special kind of) nodes. This approach still has some difficulties caused by the fact that, even if the graphs of interest are defined over the same data algebra, we have to consider categories including graphs over different algebras. The reason is that, most often, the algebras in the graphs occurring in the transformation rules are ∗ This work has been partially supported by the CICYT project (ref. TIN2007-66523) and by the AGAUR grant to the research group ALBCOM (ref. 00516). 1 / 25 Volume 30 (2010) mailto:orejas@lsi.upc.edu mailto:Leen.Lambers@hpi.uni-potsdam.de Symbolic Attributed Graphs different from the algebras in the graphs to which we apply these rules. In [7] the algebra used in rules is the freely generated term algebra over a given set of variables, i.e. attributes are terms with variables. However, one could use different algebras for defining transformation rules. In particular, for the formalization of attribute conditions, the term algebra over a set of variables is not sufficient. In this sense, in this paper we introduce a specific way to do this by taking the initial algebra associated to a given specification. In [19], Plump and Steinert present an approach that avoids the complexity of having to deal, in a single concept, with graphs and algebras. This approach is essentially based on two ideas. On the one hand, attributed graphs are seen as labelled graphs, where the labels are defined as elements of an algebra. On the other hand, graph transformations involving computations on the labels are defined by rule schemas, which are similar to graph transformation rules, but defined in terms of graphs labelled by terms with variables. Then, to apply a rule schema to a given graph we must first instantiate the schema assigning data values to the variables in the schema. The result of the instantiation is a rule where the terms labeling the graphs have been replaced by the values of these terms. In our opinion, the approach has two main drawbacks. The first one is the fact that rule schemas are not first class citizens, in the sense that they need to be instantiated to define the rules. This causes that one may need to explicitly reformulate in terms of that framework most constructions and results associated to graph transformation. This would be the case, for instance, if we would want to define in that framework notions like graph constraints, typing or borrowed contexts. On the other hand, in that approach, a limitation is imposed on the number of labels that each node or edge can have. In particular, in that paper, at most one label is allowed, though it would not be difficult to fix a different limitation. The main aim of this paper is to present a new approach to deal with attributed graph transfor- mation, which we believe is conceptually simple but more powerful than previous approaches, as we show. The approach is partially inspired on how the clausal part and the data part are concep- tually separated in Constraint Logic Programming [11, 14]. In particular, attributed graphs are presented as symbolic graphs consisting of a graph that includes as nodes some variables which represent the values of the attributes, together with a set of formulas that constrain the possible values of these variables. This means that the underlying algebra of values remains only implicit to define the satisfaction of these formulas. The idea underlying this approach was first intro- duced in [16, 17] to study graph constraints over attributed graphs and, then, used again with a similar aim to specify model transformations by means of patterns [8]. Symbolic graphs can be seen as specifications of attributed graphs. Actually, to compare the standard approach to attributed graph transformation, we define a semantics of symbolic graphs in terms of classes of attributed graphs and we show how attributed graphs can be identified with some specific kind of symbolic graphs, which we call grounded symbolic graphs. Then, to compare the expressive power of the two approaches with respect to attributed graph trans- formation, we first show that symbolic graphs, as it happens with attributed graphs [10], form an adhesive HLR category [13, 4] to ensure that symbolic graphs inherit the fundamental theory of graph transformation. A variant of this proof is already included in [17]. Finally, we show that attributed graph transformation systems can be coded into symbolic graph transformation systems but that the converse is not true in general. The paper is organized as follows. In Section 2 we provide a reminder of some notions that are used in the rest of the paper. In particular, first, we briefly enumerate some notions from Proc. GraMoT 2010 2 / 25 ECEASST algebraic specification; then, we present E-graphs which are used as the graph part for both attributed graphs and symbolic graphs; finally, we define the category of attributed graphs as presented in [4]. In Section 3 we present the category of symbolic graphs, showing that it is adhesive HLR. Section 4 is dedicated to relate the categories of attributed and symbolic graphs and Section 5 to compare the expressive power of both approaches with respect to attributed graph transformation. In Section 6, we draw some conclusions. Finally, in an appendix some technical details and proofs are provided. 2 Preliminaries We assume that the reader has a basic knowledge on algebraic specification and on graph trans- formation. For instance, we advise to look at [6] for more detail on algebraic specification or at [20, 4] for more detail on graph transformation. 2.1 Basic algebraic concepts and notation As usual, a signature Σ = (S, Ω) consists of a set of sorts S, and a family of operation symbols of the form op : s1 ×···×sn → s, denoted by Ω, where n ≥ 0 and s1, . . . , sn, s ∈ S. However, in this paper, signatures include also predicates. We can deal with this extended case in two ways. The first one is to consider that Σ consists, in addition, of a family of predicate symbols. The second one, which we will use, because it is simpler, is based in considering that there is a special sort in S, which we could call logical, and that predicate symbols are just operation symbols with profile s1×···×sn → logical. In this case, logical connectives can be treated as operation symbols over the logical sort. In addition, the truth values t and f may be seen as constants in the signature of sort logical. A Σ-algebra A consists of an S-indexed family of sets {As}s∈S and a function opA : As1 ×···× Asn →As for each operation op : s1×···×sn →s in the signature. A Σ-homomorphism h : A→A ′ consists of an S-indexed family of functions {hs : As → A ′ s}s∈S commuting with the operations. Σ-algebras and Σ-homomorphisms form the category AlgΣ. A congruence ≡ on an algebra A is an S-indexed family of equivalence relations {≡s}s∈S which are compatible with the operations. In this case, A/ ≡ denotes the quotient algebra whose elements are equivalence classes of values in A. Between A and A/ ≡ there is a canonical homo- morphism mapping every element in A into its equivalent class. Given signatures Σ, Σ′, with Σ′ ⊆ Σ, every Σ-algebra can be seen as a Σ′-algebra, by forgetting all the sorts and operations which are not in Σ′. In particular this is called the Σ′-reduct of a Σ-algebra A and is denoted by A|Σ′. Given a signature Σ, we denote by TΣ the term algebra, consisting of all the possible Σ-(ground) terms. TΣ is initial in AlgΣ, and the unique homomorphism hA : TΣ → A yields the value of each term in A. Similarly, TΣ(X ) denotes the algebra of all Σ-terms with variables in X , and given a variable assignment σ : X → A, this assignment extends to a unique homomorphism σ # : TΣ(X ) → A yielding the value of each term after the replacement of each variable x by its value σ (x). In particular, when an assignment is defined over the term algebra, i.e. σ : X → TΣ, then σ #(t) denotes the term obtained by substituting each variable x in t by the term σ (x). 3 / 25 Volume 30 (2010) Symbolic Attributed Graphs A Σ-algebra A is finitely generated if every element in A is the value of some ground term. It is not difficult to see that if A is finitely generated there is at most one homomorphism between A and any other Σ-algebra A′. A specification SP = (Σ, Ax) consists of a signature Σ and a set of axioms Ax, which may be seen as terms of logical sort. Equational specifications are a special case, where the only predicate symbol is the equality. Similarly, conditional equations may be considered as a special kind of terms. Given SP, AlgSP denotes the full subcategory of AlgΣ, consisting of all Σ-algebras A satisfying the axioms in the specification, i.e. A |= Ax. In the case where SP consists of equations or conditional equations there is an initial algebra in AlgSP, denoted by TSP. 2.2 E-graphs E-graphs are introduced in [4] as a first step to define attributed graphs. Intuitively, an E-graph is a kind of labelled graph, where both nodes and edges may be decorated with labels from a given set E . The difference with labelled graphs, as commonly understood, is that in labelled graphs it is usually assumed that each node or edge is labelled with a given number of labels, which is fixed a priori. In the case of E-graphs, each node or edge may have any arbitrary (finite) number of labels, which is not fixed a priori. Actually, in the context of graph transformation, the application of a rule may change the number of labels of a node or of an edge. Formally, in E-graphs labels are considered as a special class of nodes and the labeling relation between a node or an edge and a given label is represented by a special kind of edge. Notice that, for instance, this means that the labeling of an edge is represented by an edge whose source is an edge and whose target is a node (a label). Definition 1 (E-Graphs and morphisms) An E-graph over the set of labels L is a tuple G = (VG, L, EG, ENL, EE L,{s j,t j} j∈{G,NL,E L}) consisting of: • VG and L, which are the sets of graph nodes and of label nodes, respectively. • EG, ENL, and EE L, which are the sets of graph edges, node label edges, and edge label edges, respectively. and the source and target functions: • sG : EG →VG and tG : EG →VG • sNL : ENL →VG and tNL : ENL → L • sE L : EE L → EG and tE L : EE L → L Given the E-graphs G and G′, an E-graph morphism f : G → G ′ is a tuple, 〈 fVG : VG →V ′ G, fL : L → L′, fEG : EG → E ′ G, fENL : ENL → E ′ NL, fEEL : EE L → E ′ E L〉 such that f commutes with all the source and target functions. E-graphs and E-graph morphisms form the category E−Graphs. The following construction, which tells us how we can replace the labels of an E-graph, is used in the sections below. Proc. GraMoT 2010 4 / 25 ECEASST Definition 2 (Label substitution) Given an E-graph G = (VG, L, EG, ENL, EE L,{s j ,t j} j∈{G,NL,E L}), a set of labels L′, and a function h : L → L′ we define the E-graph h(G) resulting from the substi- tution of L along h as h(G) = (V ′G, L ′, E′G, E ′ NL, E ′ E L,{s ′ j,t ′ j} j∈{G,NL,E L}) with: • V ′G = VG, E ′ G = EG, E ′ NL = ENL, E ′ E L = EE L,{s ′ j = s j} j∈{G,NL,E L}, and t ′ G = tG • For every e ∈ E′NL : t ′ NL(e) = h(tNL(e)) • For every e ∈ E′E L : t ′ E L(e) = h(tE L(e)) Moreover, h induces the definition of the E-graph morphism h∗ : G → h(G), with h∗ = 〈idV , h, idEG , idENL , idEEL〉. It is routine to see that h(G) is indeed an E-graph and h∗ is an E-graph morphism. In addition, it should be obvious that if h is a bijection then h∗ is an isomorphism. 2.3 Attributed Graphs Following [4], an attributed graph is an E-graph whose labels are the values of a given data algebra that is assumed to be included in the graph. Definition 3 (Attributed graphs and morphisms) Given a signature Σ an attributed graph over Σ is a pair 〈G, D〉, where D is a given Σ-algebra, called the data algebra of the graph, and G is an E-graph such that the set LG of labels of G consists of all the values in D, i.e. LG = ⊎ s∈S Ds, where s is the set of sorts of the data algebra and ⊎ denotes disjoint union. Given the attributed graphs over Σ AG = 〈G, D〉 and AG′ = 〈G′, D′〉, an attributed graph mor- phism h : AG → AG′ is a pair 〈hgraph, halg〉, where hgraph is an E-graph morphism, hgraph : G → G ′ and halg is a Σ-homomorphism, halg : D → D′ such that the values in D are mapped consistently by hgraph and halg, i.e. for each sort s ∈ S the diagram below commutes: Ds halg // � _ �� D′s� _ �� LG hgra ph // L′G Attributed graphs and attributed graph morphisms form the category AttGraphs. Moreover, given a data algebra D we will denote by AttGraphsD the full subcategory of AttGraphs con- sisting of attributed graphs over D. When defining transformation rules over graphs in AttGraphsD, usually the algebra under- lying the graphs in the rules is not D but a term algebra over the signature of D. That is, the attributes in the rules are not values but terms, typically with variables. We call these graphs term-attributed graphs. Definition 4 (Term-attributed graphs) Given a signature Σ = (S, Ω), a term-attributed graph over Σ is an attributed graph over the algebra TΣ(X ), for some S-sorted set of variables X . 5 / 25 Volume 30 (2010) Symbolic Attributed Graphs Moreover, as we will see in Section 5, it is also useful to define transformation rules where the underlying algebra has been defined using a specification. In particular this is useful when we want that the match morphism used to apply the given rule satisfies some specific condition. For instance, suppose that the graph below is the left-hand side of a rule. x1 x2 and suppose that, whenever we apply this rule, we would like that the corresponding match m satisfies that m(x1) ≤ m(x2). We can do this as follows. First we define a specification SP extending Σ with the variables x1 and x2 as constants, and the desired condition as an axiom, i.e.: SP = Sorts nat, bool Opns 0 : nat x1, x2 : nat suc : nat → nat true, f alse : bool + : nat ×nat → nat ≤: nat ×nat → bool Axms (x1 ≤ x2) = true Now, let TSP be the initial algebra associated to SP, and TSP|Σ its Σ-reduct. In TSP the term x1 ≤ x2 and the term true belong to the same congruence class, which means that they denote the same element in TSP|Σ. Therefore, any homomorphism m from TSP|Σ into a Σ-algebra D must satisfy that, in this algebra, m(x1) ≤ m(x2) yields the true value. Hence, we should define the transformation rule over the algebra TSP|Σ. Definition 5 (Term-Attributed graphs over a specification) Given a signature Σ and a specifi- cation SP = (Σ′, Ax), with Σ ⊆ Σ′, a term-attributed graph over the specification SP extending Σ is an attributed graph over the algebra TSP|Σ. In [4] it has been proven that AttGraphs is an adhesive HLR category for a given class of M-morphisms. Let us first recall this notion [4, 13]: Definition 6 (Adhesive HLR category) A category C is adhesive HLR with respect to a class M of morphisms if: 1. M is a class of monomorphisms closed under isomorphism, composition (i.e. if f : A → B ∈ M and g : B → A ∈ M then g◦ f ∈ M), and decomposition (i.e. if g◦ f ∈ M and g ∈ M then f ∈ M). 2. C has pushouts and pullbacks along M-morphisms. Moreover, M-morphisms are closed under pushouts and pullbacks. 3. Pushouts in C along M-morphisms are van Kampen squares, i.e. for any commutative di- agram as the one below, assuming that h1 and g2 are M-morphisms, if the bottom diagram Proc. GraMoT 2010 6 / 25 ECEASST is a pushout and the back faces are pullbacks then the top diagram is a pushout if and only if the front diagrams are pullbacks. A′0 h′1 wwoo oo oo oo oo oo oo o h′2 ��? ? ? ? ? ? ? f0 �� A′1 g′1 ��? ? ? ? ? ? ? f1 �� A′2 f2 �� g′2 wwoo oo o oo oo oo o oo o A′3 f3 �� A0 h1 wwoo oo oo oo oo oo oo o h2 ��@ @ @ @ @ @ @ @ A1 g1 A A A A A A A A2 g2 wwnn nn nn nn nn nn nn n A3 The key idea to show that AttGraphs is adhesive HLR is the choice of the right kind of M- morphisms. Actually, AttGraphs is not adhesive1 because it fails to satisfy the van Kampen property for arbitrary monomorphisms. Theorem 1 AttGraphs is adhesive HLR, with respect to the class of M-morphisms consisting of all monomorphisms 〈hgraph, halg〉 such that halg is an isomorphism. 3 The category of symbolic graphs A symbolic graph can be seen as the specification of an attributed graph (or of a class of attributed graphs). In particular, a symbolic graph consists of an E-graph G whose labels are variables, together with a set of formulas Φ that constrain the possible values of these variables. In this sense, we consider that a symbolic graph denotes the class of all attributed graphs where the variables in the E-graph have been replaced for values that make Φ true in the given data domain. For instance, below on the right, we can see an example of a very simple symbolic graph and, on the left, the (unique) attributed graph denoted by that symbolic graph. 27 45 3712 15 18 x y zd1 d2 d3 with (x = 27)∧(y = 45)∧z = 37 ∧ (d1 = 12)∧(d2 = 15)∧(d3 = 18) However, as said above, a symbolic graph, in general denotes a class of graphs. For instance, the graph below specifies a class of attributed graphs that includes the graph depicted above on the left, but it also specifies many other graphs. 1 Roughly speaking, an adhesive category [13] is like an adhesive HLR category, where M is the class of all monomor- phisms 7 / 25 Volume 30 (2010) Symbolic Attributed Graphs x y zd1 d2 d3 with d3 ≤ d1 + d2 It may be noted that the class of attributed graphs denoted by a symbolic graph may be empty if the associated condition is unsatisfiable. Therefore, let us define what is a symbolic graph over a given data algebra. Definition 7 (Symbolic graphs and morphisms) A symbolic graph over the data Σ-algebra D, with Σ = (S, Ω), is a pair 〈G, Φ〉, where G is an E-graph over an S-sorted set of variables X = {Xs}s∈S, i.e. LG = ∪s∈SXs, and Φ is a set of first-order Σ-formulas built over the free variables in X and including the elements in D as constants. Given symbolic graphs 〈G1, Φ1〉 and 〈G2, Φ2〉 over the same data algebra D, a symbolic graph morphism h : 〈G1, Φ1〉→〈G2, Φ2〉 is an E-graph morphism h : G1 → G2 such that D |= Φ2 ⇒ h#(Φ1), where h#(Φ1) is the set of formulas obtained when replacing in Φ1 every variable x1 in the set of labels of G1 by hL(x1). Symbolic graphs over D together with their morphisms form the category SymbGraphsD. In what follows, to simplify notation, even if it may be considered an abuse of notation, we will write h(Φ) instead of h#(Φ). Moreover, also for simplicity, we may identify the set of formulas Φ with the formula consisting of the conjunction of all the formulas in Φ, even if that formula may be infinitary in the case where Φ is an infinite set. Notice that, according to the above definition, given any E-graph G, if D |= Φ ⇔ Φ′ then 〈G, Φ〉 and 〈G, Φ′〉 are isomorphic in SymbGraphsD. To show that symbolic graphs are an adhesive HLR category, first, we have to define our no- tion of M-morphism over symbolic graphs. We consider that M-morphisms are monomorphisms where the formulas constraining the source and target graphs are equivalent (in most cases they will just be the same formula). The intuition of this definition is based on the use of our cate- gory of symbolic graphs to define graph transformation. More precisely, we think that the most reasonable formulation of graph transformation rules in our context is based on defining a graph transformation rule as an E-graph transformation rule, together with a set of formulas that glob- ally constrain and relate all the variables in the rule. This is equivalent to consider that the left and right-hand sides (and also the interface) of a rule are constrained by the same set of formulas. Definition 8 (M-morphisms) An M-morphism h : 〈G, Φ〉→〈G′, Φ′〉 is a monomorphism such that LG ∼= LG′, i.e. hL is a bijection, and D |= h(Φ) ⇔ Φ′. It is not difficult to see that M-morphisms satisfy the required properties. Then, to define pushouts and pullbacks in SymbGraphsD we use pushouts and pullbacks in E−Graphs, re- spectively. More precisely, the pushout of 〈G1, Φ1〉 h1 ←〈G0, Φ0〉 h2 →〈G2, Φ2〉 is a graph 〈G3, Φ3〉, where G1 g1 → G3 g2 ← G2 is the pushout of G1 h1 ← G0 h1 → G2 and Φ3 is the conjunction of g1(Φ1) and g2(Φ2). The case of pullbacks is similar, but the pullback of 〈G1, Φ1〉 g1 →〈G3, Φ3〉 g2 ←〈G2, Φ2〉 is the graph 〈G0, Φ0〉, where G1 h1 ← G0 h2 → G2 is the pullback of G1 g1 → G3 g2 ← G2 and Φ0 is the Proc. GraMoT 2010 8 / 25 ECEASST disjunction of h1(Φ1) and h2(Φ2). However, since G0 may include a strict subset of the variables of Φ1 and Φ2, in this case Φ0 is existentially quantified by the variables not in G0. Proposition 1 SymbGraphsD has pushouts and pullbacks. To see that pushouts and pullbacks preserve M-morphisms we just have to do some basic logical deduction. If the diagram below is a pushout and h1 is an M-morphism then we have to prove that D |= Φ2 ⇔ (g2(Φ2)∧g1(Φ1)). But, since h1 is an M-morphism we may consider without loss of generality that h1 is the equality on variables and Φ0 = Φ1. Moreover, we may also consider without loss of generality that g2 is also the equality on variables and that h2 and g1 coincide when restricted to the variables. As a consequence, what we would need to prove is that D |= Φ2 ⇔ (Φ2 ∧h2(Φ0)), since g2(Φ2) = Φ2 and h2(Φ0) = g1(Φ1). But this is obvious, since we know that D |= Φ2 ⇐ h2(Φ0). The case of pullbacks is slightly more complex because of the existential quantifiers in Φ0. 〈G0, Φ0〉 h1 // h2 �� 〈G1, Φ1〉 g1 �� 〈G2, Φ2〉 g2 // 〈G3, Φ3〉 Proposition 2 Pushouts and pullbacks preserve M-morphisms. Finally, to prove the van Kampen property we show that a cube in SymbGraphsD is a van Kampen square if and only if the underlying cube in E−Graphs is also a van Kampen square. To do this, again we just need to do some basic logical reasoning. As a consequence we have: Theorem 2 SymbGraphsD is adhesive HLR. 4 Symbolic graphs and attributed graphs In this section we present the relation between the categories of symbolic and attributed graphs over a given data algebra. On one hand, we will see that every symbolic graph may be seen as denoting a class (a subcategory) of attributed graphs, which may be considered its semantics. On the other hand, we will see that every attributed graph can be represented in a canonical way by a symbolic graph, which means that, for a given data algebra, the category of attributed graphs can be seen as a subcategory of the corresponding category of symbolic graphs. Definition 9 (Semantics of symbolic graphs) Given a symbolic graph 〈G, Φ〉 over a data alge- bra D, its semantics is a class of attributed graphs defined as follows: Sem(〈G, Φ〉) = {〈σ (G), D〉 | σ : LG → D and D |= σ (Φ)} where σ (G) denotes the graph obtained according to Def. 2. For example, given the symbolic graph below: 9 / 25 Volume 30 (2010) Symbolic Attributed Graphs x y zd1 d2 d3 with d3 ≤ d1 + d2 we have that its semantics would include the following attributed graphs: 27 45 3712 15 18 6 7 88 25 4 Conversely, we can identify every attributed graph AG with a grounded symbolic graph whose semantics consists only of AG. More precisely a grounded graph is a symbolic graph 〈G, Φ〉 that includes a variable xv for each element v of the data algebra and where the only substitution σ : LG → D such that D |= σ (Φ) is defined for each variable xv as σ (xv) = v. Definition 10 (Grounded symbolic graphs) A symbolic graph 〈G, Φ〉 over a data algebra D is grounded if 1. LG includes a variable, which we denote by xv, for each value v ∈ D, and 2. For every substitution σ : LG → D, such that D |= σ (Φ), we have σ (xv) = v, for each variable xv ∈ LG. Moreover, we define GSymbGraphsD as the full subcategory of SymbGraphsD consisting of all grounded graphs. Notice that if 〈G, Φ〉 is grounded and σ : LG → D is a substitution such that D |= σ (Φ) then σ∗ : G → σ (G) is an isomorphism. It should be obvious that the semantics of a grounded graph includes exactly one attributed graph, and that grounded graphs are closed up to isomorphism. Moreover, we can see that for every attributed graph AG there is a unique grounded symbolic graph (up to isomorphism) GSG(AG) such that Sem(GSG(AG)) consists of AG. In particular, the E-graph associated to GSG(AG) is obtained substituting every data value v in a set of labels by a variable xv, and the set of formulas in the symbolic graph consists of an equation xv = v, for each value v in D. Definition 11 Given an attributed graph AG = 〈G, D〉, we define the grounded symbolic graph associated to AG, GSG(AG) as the symbolic graph 〈G′, Φ〉, where: • The set of labels X of the E-graph G′ consists of a variable xv for each element v ∈ D. • G′ = f∗(G), where f : D → X is a substitution such that for every v ∈ D, f (v) = xv. • Φ = {xv = v | v ∈ D}. Proposition 3 1. If SG is grounded then Sem(SG) consists exactly of one attributed graph. Proc. GraMoT 2010 10 / 25 ECEASST 2. Grounded symbolic graphs are closed up to isomorphism. 3. For each attributed graph AG = 〈G, D〉, Sem(GSG(AG)) = {AG}. Proof. 1. If SG = 〈G, Φ〉 is grounded, by definition we know that Sem(SG) is not empty, since Φ is satisfiable in D. Moreover, If AG1, AG2 ∈ Sem(〈G, Φ〉) then this means that there are substitutions σ , σ ′ : LG → D such that D |= σ (Φ) and D |= σ ′(Φ). But if 〈G, Φ〉 is grounded this means that LG = {xv | v ∈ D} and for each v ∈ D: σ (xv) = v and σ ′(xv) = v. But this implies that σ = σ ′ and therefore AG1 = AG2. 2. Let SG = 〈G, Φ〉 be a grounded graph and let SG′ = 〈G′, Φ′〉 be isomorphic to SG. This means that there is an E-graph isomorphism h : G → G′ such that D |= Φ ⇔ h(Φ′). But this implies that hL : LG → LG′ is a bijection and if σ ′ : LG′ → D is a substitution such that D |= σ ′(Φ′) then σ ′◦h : LG → D is a substitution such that D |= σ ′◦h(Φ), and this means that for every v ∈ D σ ′◦h(xv) = v. Therefore, if for every v ∈ D we call yv the variable h(xv) then we have that, for each v ∈ D, σ ′(yv) = v, which means that SG′ is grounded. 3. It should be obvious that, by construction, GSG(AG) is grounded and, moreover, AG ∈ Sem(GSG(AG)). Now, suppose that SG0 = 〈G0, Φ0〉 is a symbolic graph such that AG =〈G, D〉∈ Sem(SG). Let us prove that SG and GSG(AG) = 〈G′, ΦAG〉 are isomorphic. First of all, we know that G = σ∗0 (G0) for a substitution σ0 such that D |= σ0(Φ0). But, since SG0 is grounded, σ ∗ 0 is an isomorphism. For similar reasons, we know that f∗ : G → G′ is also an isomorphism therefore f∗◦σ∗0 : G0 → G ′ is an E-graph isomorphism. Finally, it is easy to see that D |= Φ ⇔ f ◦σ0(Φ0). In particular, if σ is a substitution such that D |= σ (Φ) we have to prove that D |= σ ◦ f ◦σ0(Φ0) or, equivalently, that σ ◦ f ◦σ0 = σ0. But this is obvious since, on one hand, by construction, v∈D: f (v) = xv, and, on the other hand, we know that for every v ∈ D: σ (xv) = v, which means that f = σ−1. Conversely, if σ is a substitution such that D |= σ ◦ f ◦σ0(Φ0) we can prove similarly that this implies that D |= σ (Φ). It should also be obvious that the encoding of attributed graphs in terms of symbolic graphs defined by GSG can be applied to all kinds of attributed graphs, i.e. not only to attributed graphs defined over a data algebra D, but also to term-attributed graphs or to term-attributed graphs de- fined over a specification SP. However, in the latter case, we prefer to define a different encoding which may actually be seen as a variation of GSG, that we call its symbolic representation, de- noted SR, and which will be used in the following section. In particular, if G is a term-attributed graph defined over a specification SP, we define SR(G) as follows. First, we assume that we have a function that chooses a term from every congruence class of terms in TSP. We call this function a choice function. Then, the symbolic representation of G would be 〈G′, Φ′〉, where G′ is obtained replacing each label a in G (i.e. each congruence class in TSP) by the variable xt , where t is the term chosen by the choice function when applied to a, and where Φ′ consists of all the equations in SP and all the equations xt = t for each term t returned by the choice function. 11 / 25 Volume 30 (2010) Symbolic Attributed Graphs Definition 12 Given a specification SP = (Σ∪X , Φ), such that there is an initial algebra TSP in the category of SP-algebras, we say that ch : TSP → TΣ∪X is a choice function for TSP if for every element |t′|∈ TSP if ch(t) = t ′ then TSP |= t = t ′, where |t′| denotes the congruence class of t′ with respect to the congruence defined by SP. Given SP, an attributed graph AG = 〈G, TSP|Σ〉, and a choice function ch for TSP we define the symbolic representation of AG with respect to ch, SRch(AG) as the symbolic graph 〈G ′, Φ′〉, where: • The set of labels of the E-graph G′ is X ∪Y , where Y is disjoint with X and it consists of a variable ych(a) for each element a ∈ TSP such that a /∈{|x| | x ∈ X}. • G′ = f∗(G), where f : TSP → Y is a substitution such that for every a ∈ TSP, if a /∈{|x| | x ∈ X} then f (a) = ych(a). Otherwise, f (|x|) = x. • Φ′ = Φ∪{ych(a) = t | ych(a) ∈Y ∧ch(a) = t}. This means that G′ includes as labels the variables in X and a variable ya for every element a in TSP which is not the congruence class of a variable in X . This means that the substitution f is a bijection. As a consequence, for every attributed graph AG = 〈G, TSP|Σ〉, if SRch(AG) = 〈G ′, Φ′〉 then G and G′ are isomorphic E-graphs. It may be noted that we have not stated over which algebra D the symbolic graph SRch(AG) is defined. The reason is that we may consider that SRch(AG) is a symbolic graph over any Σ-algebra D. Anyhow, if we consider that SRch(AG) is defined over TSP|Σ then SRch(AG) is a grounded graph in SymbGraphsTSP|Σ , i.e. SRch(AG) is an object in GSymbGraphsTSP|Σ . This means that, following Proposition 3, SRch(AG) and GSG(AG) are isomorphic graphs in SymbGraphsTSP|Σ . According to Proposition 3, we can identify each attributed graph with a grounded sym- bolic graph, and vice versa. Therefore, we may ask whether AttGraphsD is isomorphic to GSymbGraphsD. The answer is negative since GSG cannot be made injective on morphisms as the following counter-example shows. Example 1 Let D be a data algebra consisting of two values of the same sort, which we call a and b. Let AG be an attributed graph having no graph nodes and no graph edges (i.e. the graph structure of AG is empty, which means that it consists only of the label nodes a and b). As a consequence, GSG(AG) = 〈G, xa = a∧xb = b〉, where G is an E-graph consisting only of the label nodes xa and xb. Now, there are four morphisms, f1, f2, f3 and f4, from AG to itself: • f1(a) = a, f1(b) = b. • f2(a) = a, f2(b) = a. • f3(a) = b, f3(b) = b. • f4(a) = b, f4(b) = a. However the only morphism from GSG(AG) to itself is the identity. For example we may see that the mapping g : {xa, xb}→{xa, xb}, defined g(xa) = xa, g(xb) = xa, does not define a Proc. GraMoT 2010 12 / 25 ECEASST symbolic graph morphism. In particular, if g is a morphism it should hold that D |= (xa = a∧xb = b) ⇒ g(xa = a∧xb = b). But this is equivalent to D |= (xa = a∧xb = b) ⇒ (xa = a∧xa = b), which is obviously false. The problem in the above counter-example is that we assume that we can define any mapping between the elements of the algebra, while for the variables of the grounded graphs we are forced to map the variable xv associated to a value to the corresponding variable associated to the same value. This problem disappears if the value algebra is finitely generated. In that case, we know that the only homomorphism of an algebra into itself is the identity causing that morphisms on attributed graphs should be the identity on data values. This means that, if D is finitely generated then the categories AttGraphsD and GSymbGraphsD are equivalent. Moreover, this kind of restriction is quite reasonable since, otherwise, the algebra would include values which we cannot refer to. Nevertheless, as we will see in the following section, attributed graph transformation rules are usually defined over non-finitely generated algebras. Proposition 4 If D is finitely generated then AttGraphsD and GSymbGraphsD are equivalent. Proof. First, we will show that GSG can be extended to a functor and, then, that GSG is full, faithful and essentially surjective. Let f : 〈G1, D〉→〈G2, D〉 be an attributed graph morphism. Since D is finitely generated, falg is the identity and fgraph is an E-graph morphism. Hence, if f : D → XD is a substitution defined for every v ∈ D as f (v) = xv, and Φ = {xv = v | v ∈ D} we know that GSG(〈G1, D〉) = 〈 f (G1), Φ〉 to GSG(〈G2, D〉) = 〈 f (G2), Φ〉. We define GSG( f ) as follows: • For every x ∈{VG, EG, ENL, EE L}: GSG( f )x = fx. • GSG( f )L is the identity. Then, it is routine to prove that GSG( f ) is indeed a symbolic graph morphism. To prove that GSG is full, we have to show that if AG1 = 〈G1, D〉 and AG2 = 〈G2, D〉 are two attributed graphs and h : GSG(AG1) → GSG(AG2) is a symbolic graph morphism then there exists an attributed graph morphism f : AG1 → AG2 such that GSG( f ) = h. But it is enough to define f as follows: • For every x ∈{VG, EG, ENL, EE L}: fx = hx. • falg (and, therefore, fL) is the identity. To prove that GSG is faithful we have to show that GSG is injective on morphisms, but this is straightforward by construction. Finally, to prove that GSG is essentially surjective, we have to show that for every grounded graph SG there is another grounded graph SG′, which is isomorphic to SG, and an attributed graph AG such that GSG(AG) = SG′. But by Prop 3 we know that Sem(SG) is not empty and that if AG ∈ Sem(SG) satisfies that GSG(AG) = SG. 13 / 25 Volume 30 (2010) Symbolic Attributed Graphs 5 Symbolic graph transformation and attributed graph transfor- mation In this section we compare attributed graph transformation with symbolic graph transformation. This comparison may seem trivial: if attributed graphs may be seen as a special case of symbolic graphs then we can conclude that attributed graph transformation is a special case of symbolic graph transformation. However things are not so obvious. As we have seen, if the given data algebra D is finitely generated, we can identify attributed graphs over D with grounded symbolic graphs over D. This means, in that case, that if transformation rules are spans of M-morphisms in AttGraphsD then these transformation rules can be considered equivalent to spans of M- morphisms in GSymbGraphsD, and the application of these rules to a graph AG in AttGraphsD is equivalent to the transformation of GSG(AG) by the corresponding rules in GSymbGraphsD. The problem is that if the graphs that we want to transform are in AttGraphsD, usually, the trans- formation rules will not be spans of M-morphisms in AttGraphsD, but in AttGraphsD′, where D′ is some free algebra over D and, hence, different from D. That is, typically, transformation rules over attributed graphs are defined using term attributed graphs. In order to compare attributed and symbolic graph transformation we start giving an example of symbolic graph transformation rules and symbolic graph transformation. Example 2 Let us suppose that we are dealing with a class of graphs whose edges have an attribute that represents the distance between the source and target nodes. For instance, the graph G0 below may be an example of a graph in this class: a b c d 10 20 10 15 30 More precisely, let us consider that the underlying algebra in this class of graphs is the algebra D of natural numbers, defined over the signature Σ: Sorts nat, bool Opns 0 : nat suc : nat → nat true, f alse : bool + : nat ×nat → nat ≤: nat ×nat → bool We can see the above graph as a grounded symbolic graph. In this case we would need to replace the values which are bound to the edges of the graph by the variables x10, x15, x20, and x30, respectively, and we would need to include the formula (x0 = 0)∧(x1 = 1)∧(x2 = 2)∧···∧(x10 = 10)∧···∧(x15 = 15)∧···∧(x20 = 20)∧···∧(x30 = 30)∧ . . . . However, since Proc. GraMoT 2010 14 / 25 ECEASST we know that grounded symbolic graphs and attributed graphs are equivalent, for readability, we will directly use the attributed graph representation. Let us also suppose that we want to compute the distance of the shortest paths between any two nodes. The symbolic graph transformation rule p, depicted below, describes how a new distance can be computed: d1 d2 L 1 2 3 1 2 3 1 2 3 d1 d2 K with d3 = d1 + d2 d3 d1 d2 R If we match 1 with d, 2 with c, and 3 with b, and the variables d1, d2, and d3 with 10, 15, and 25, respectively2 , then we can apply this rule to the above graph, because 25 = 10 + 15 holds in D3, which is the translation of the rule condition, when d1, d2, and d3 are replaced by their corresponding matches. Therefore, we would transform G0 into G1: a b c d 10 20 10 15 25 30 Similarly, matching 1 with a, 3 with b, and 2 with c, and the variables d1, d2, and d3 with 10, 15, and 25, respectively, as before, it would be possible to apply the above transformation rule, getting the graph G2: a b c d 10 20 10 15 25 30 25 2 To be more precise, we would match d1, d2, and d3 with the variables x10, x15, and x25, respectively. 3 Again, to be more precise, the condition that holds is (x10 = 10)∧(x15 = 15)∧(x25 = 25)∧ . . . implies (x25 = x10 + x25) 15 / 25 Volume 30 (2010) Symbolic Attributed Graphs Now, if we want to get rid of all the edges between two given nodes, except of the one labelled with the smallest distance, we could use the rule p′ depicted below4: d1 d2 L′ d1 1 2 1 2 1 2 K′ with (x1 ≤ x2) = true d1 R′ We can apply the above rule to the graph G2, matching nodes 1 and 2 to nodes a and c, and variables d1 and d2 to 25 and 30, respectively, and also matching the edges bound to the former variables to the corresponding edges in G2 bound to 25 and 30. The result would be G3: a b c d 10 20 10 15 25 25 Remark 1 Obviously, symbolic graph transformation rules may be applied not only to grounded symbolic graphs, but to arbitrary symbolic graphs. Actually, the fact that the category of sym- bolic graphs is adhesive HLR ensures that the fundamental theory of graph transformation [4] applies to symbolic graph transformation. However, in practice, it may be impossible to apply a graph transformation rule to an arbitrary symbolic graph, even if seems very reasonable. For instance, we may expect that it should be possible to apply the rule p, depicted above, to the symbolic graph G depicted below on the left, yielding the graph on the right: x y 1 2 3 with x < y x y z 1 2 3 with x < y∧z = x + y However, this is not possible. The first problem we find to apply the rule p to G is that if G only includes the variables x and y then the variable d3 in the rule could only be matched 4 A different alternative for the same problem would be to use some NACs in the first rule to avoid creating more than one edge between any two nodes Proc. GraMoT 2010 16 / 25 ECEASST to x or y. Moreover, it would be unclear where do the variable z in G′ comes from. We can overcome this problem by assuming that G already included the variable z, although it was not explicitly depicted because it was not bounded to any node or edge in G. Actually, we could think that a symbolic graph is supplied with an unlimited number of variables. However this is not the main problem. We cannot apply p to G because x < y does not imply z = x + y in D. This problem is solved in [18], where a new form of symbolic graph transformation, called lazy graph transformation, is studied. More precisely, using lazy graph transformation, G′ would be obtained applying p to G in the obvious way. Now, let us describe how we can define attributed graph transformation rules having a similar effect to the symbolic rules in Example 2. Example 3 Let us suppose that we want to describe the same procedure as in Example 2 for computing shortest paths, but now using attributed graph transformation rules. In this case, rule p for computing a new distance between two nodes could be: d1 d2 L 1 2 3 1 2 3 1 2 3 d1 d2 K d1 + d2 d1 d2 R The first thing that we should note is that the graphs G0, G1, G2 and G3 in Example 2 are defined over the algebra D of natural numbers, which means that they include the natural numbers and the booleans as label nodes, even if they are not depicted in the above figures. But the graphs L, K, and R in the transformation rule p are not defined over the same algebra. The reason is that the labels d1, d2, or d1 + d2 are not in D, since they are not natural numbers. The simplest solution that we can use here, is to consider that L, K, and R are term-attributed graphs over the algebra TΣ({d1, d2}), i.e. the term algebra over the variables d1 and d2. These graphs would include as label nodes all the possible Σ-terms over these two variables, even if they are not depicted explicitly. Now, according to the example, when we apply p to G0 in Example 2 we define a morphism m from L into G matching 1 with d, 2 with c, and 3 with b. Obviously, m would also match the edges in L with the edges in G in the expected way and it would also match d1 with 10 and d2 with 15. But this is not all. The match m includes a Σ-homomorphism malg from TΣ({d1, d2}) to D matching not only d1 with 10 and d2 with 15, but also each possible term over d1 and d2 with its corresponding value, after assigning to d1 and d2 the values 10 and 15, respectively. This means that, for instance, m would also match suc(d1) with 11 or suc(d1) ≤ suc(suc(d2 )) to t. In particular, m would also match d1 + d2 with 25, even if d1 + d2 is not explicitly depicted in L, i.e. we need to compute the resulting value of d1 + d2 when defining the match, before computing the transformation. The fact that the values of the underlying algebra are considered (label) nodes of the attributed 17 / 25 Volume 30 (2010) Symbolic Attributed Graphs graphs, together with the fact that match morphisms must be homomorphisms for the algebra part, allow us to do some kind of conditional graph transformation without using a negative application condition (NAC) [3, 9], but using term-attributed graphs over a given specification, as discussed in Section 2.3. For example, we can have an attributed graph transformation rule p′′, similar to rule p′ in Example 2, for deleting all edges between two nodes except the one labelled with the shortest distance. In particular, p′′, could be the rule below: d1 d2 L′ d1 K′ 1 2 1 2 1 2 d1 R′ when defined over the algebra TSP|Σ, where SP is defined: SP = Sorts nat, bool Opns 0 : nat d1, d2 : nat suc : nat → nat true, f alse : bool + : nat ×nat → nat ≤: nat ×nat → bool Axms (d1 ≤ d2) = true For instance the application of p′′ to the graph G2 in Example 2 matching node 1 to node a and node 2 to node c would necessarily match d1 to 25 and d2 to 30 yielding the graph G3, also in Example 2. Therefore, we can consider that, in a transformation system for attributed graphs over a Σ- algebra D, each rule r is a span on the category AttGraphsDr , where Dr = TSPr|Σ and SPr is a specification SPr = (Σr, Φr), such that Σr = Σ∪X and Φr is a set of Σr-equations or conditional equations, since this ensures the existence of initial algebras. Under this assumption, we may see that attributed graph transformation systems can be seen as a special case of symbolic graph transformation system. The idea is that every rule r as above can be represented by a symbolic transformation rule r′, using the symbolic representation of the graphs in r. More precisely: Definition 13 Given a specification SP = (Σ∪X , Φ), such that there is an initial algebra TSP, a choice function ch for TSP, and an attributed graph transformation rule r = (〈L, TSP|Σ〉 ←֓ 〈K, TSP|Σ〉 →֒ 〈R, TSP|Σ〉), we define the symbolic representation of r with respect to ch, SRch(r) as the symbolic transformation rule r′ = 〈L′ ←֓ K′ →֒ R′, Φ′〉 where: • 〈L′, Φ′〉 = SRch(〈L, TSP|Σ〉), Proc. GraMoT 2010 18 / 25 ECEASST • 〈K′, Φ′〉 = SRch(〈K, TSP|Σ〉), • 〈R′, Φ′〉 = SRch(〈R, TSP|Σ〉). Remark 2 The inclusions K′ ⊆ L′ and K′ ⊆ R′ are a consequence, first, of the fact that we assume that K ⊆ L and K ⊆ R5; second, of the definition of how a label substitution is applied to an E-graph; and third of the fact that the use of the choice function ensures that the substitution of values in TSP|Σ by variables in Y is the same on the three graphs L ′, R′, and K′. Moreover, it may be noticed that, by definition of the choice functions, diagrams (1), (2), (3), and (4) below are pushouts, where f∗L , f ∗ K , and f ∗ R are, respectively, the isomorphisms relating L, K, and R with L′, K′, and R′, and where f∗−1L , f ∗−1 K , and f ∗−1 R are their inverses: L (1)f∗L �� K (2) ? _oo � � // f∗K �� R f∗R �� L′ (3)f∗−1L �� K′ (4) ? _oo � � // f∗−1K �� R′ f∗−1R �� L′ K′? _oo � � // R′ L K? _oo � � // R Theorem 3 Let r = (AL ← AK → AR) be an attributed graph transformation rule, where AL, AK, and AR are attributed graphs over TSP|Σ and SP = (Σ∪X , Φ), let ch be a choice function for TSP, and let r ′ = SRch(r), then for every attributed graph AG = 〈G, D〉 and every morphism m : AL → AG there is a morphism m′ : 〈SRch(AL), Φ′〉→ GSG(AG) such that AG is transformed into AH by r with match m, i.e. AG⇒mr AH , if and only if GSG(AG)⇒ m′ r′ GSG(AH). Conversely, for every morphism m′ : 〈SRch(AL), Φ′〉→ GSG(AG) there is a morphism m : AL → AG such that GSG(AG) ⇒m ′ r′ GSG(AH) if and only if AG ⇒ m r AH . Proof. Let us assume that AL = 〈L, TSP|Σ〉, AK = 〈K, TSP|Σ〉, AR = 〈R, TSP|Σ〉), and r ′ = 〈L′ ←֓ K′ →֒ R′, Φ′〉, and let us consider the following diagram in E−Graphs: L′ (3)f∗−1L �� K′ (4) ? _oo � � // f∗−1K �� R′ f∗−1R �� L (5)m �� K (6) ? _oo � � // �� R �� G (7)g∗L �� I (8) ? _ h1 oo � � h2 // g∗K �� H g∗R �� G′ I′? _ h′1 oo � � h′2 // H′ where (5) and (6) are the pushouts defining the application of r to AG with match m, 〈G′, Ψ〉 = GSG(AG),〈I′, Ψ〉 = GSG(〈I, TSP|Σ〉), 〈H′, Ψ〉 = GSG(〈H, TSP|Σ〉), g∗L, g ∗ K , g ∗ R are, respectively, the isomorphisms relating G, I, H with G′, I′, H′, and finally the morphisms h′i, for i = 1, 2 are 5 Since the morphisms relating L and R are M-morphisms, without loss of generality, we may assume that they are the identity on the algebra part and an inclusion on the graph part 19 / 25 Volume 30 (2010) Symbolic Attributed Graphs defined as follows. For every element e ∈ I′ which is not a label, h′i(e) = hi(e), and for every label e, h′i(e) = e. It is routine to see that, by definition of GSG and as a consequence of the fact that h1 and h2 are M-morphisms, h ′ 1 and h ′ 2 are morphisms and, moreover, diagrams (7) and (8) not only commute but are pushouts. Therefore, since we know that diagrams (3) and (4) are pushouts, then diagrams (3)+(5)+(7) and (4)+(6)+(8) are also pushouts. Therefore, if we define m′ = g∗L ◦m◦ f ∗−1 L and we show that m ′ is a morphism in SymbGraphsD the first part of the theorem will be proved. Therefore, we have to prove that D |= Ψ ⇒ m′(Φ′). We now that Φ′ = Φ∪{ya = t | ya ∈Y ∧ch(a) = t} and Ψ = {xv = v | v ∈ D} We also know that the only substitution σ such that D |= σ (Ψ) is defined ∀v ∈ D : σ (xv) = v. Therefore, we have to show that D |= σ (m′(Φ′)) or, equivalently, D |= σ (m′(Φ)) and D |= σ (m′({ye = t | ye ∈ Y ∧ch(e) = t})). Finally, by definition, on the one hand, we have that for every a ∈ TSP|Σ we have m ′(ya) = xv, where m(a) = v, which means that σ (m′(ya)) = m(a), and on the other hand, for each x ∈ X , σ (m′(x)) = m(x). Now, let t1 = t2 be an equation in Φ. Since malg is a Σ-homomorphism and TSP satisfies this equation, we have that D |= m(t1) = m(t2), implying D |= σ (m′(t1)) = σ (m′(t2)). Let ya = t and ch(a) = t. Then, on the one hand, we have that σ (m′(ya)) = m(a) and, on the other, since ch(a) = t we have that in a = |t|, implying σ (m′(t)) = m(a). Therefore, σ (m′(ya)) = σ (m′(t)). The proof of the second part of the theorem is similar to the proof of the first part. We only have to consider the diagram below: L (1)f∗L �� K (2) ? _oo � � // f∗K �� R f∗R �� L′ (9)m′ �� K′ (10) ? _oo � � // �� R′ �� G′ (11)g∗−1L �� I′ (12) ? _ h′1 oo � � h′2 // g∗−1K �� H′ g∗−1R �� G I? _ h1 oo � � h2 // H The theorem above shows that attributed graph transformation can be seen as a special case of symbolic graph transformation. One may wonder whether both kind of transformations can be considered equivalent in the sense that every symbolic graph transformation rule r can be coded into an attributed graph transformation rule r′ such that the application of r to a grounded graph produces the same effect as the application of r′ to the corresponding attributed graph. The an- swer is negative as the counter-example below shows, which means that symbolic transformation rules have more definitional power than attributed graph transformation rules. Proc. GraMoT 2010 20 / 25 ECEASST Example 4 Let us suppose that the following symbolic graph SG is the left-hand side of a symbolic graph transformation rule r: x y with (x = 0)∨(y = 0)∨(x = y) where the signature of the data domain is: Sorts nat Opns 0 : nat suc : nat → nat and where the given data algebra D is the algebra of natural numbers. This means that, if r could be represented by an attributed graph transformation rule r′, then r′ would include as a left-hand side an attributed graph AG like: a1 a2 where a1 and a2 are elements of some Σ-algebra A. Moreover, there should exist a match m from SG into any grounded symbolic graph SG′ if and only if there exists an equivalent match m′ from AG into the corresponding attributed graph. In particular, given the symbolic graph: x y with (x = n1)∧(y = n2) where n1 and n2 are two natural numbers, there should exist a homomorphism from A to D mapping a1 to n1 and a2 to n2 if and only if n1 = 0 or n2 = 0 or n1 = n2. Let us see that this is impossible. In particular, first, we will see that a1 and a2 cannot be the value of a ground term (i.e. they cannot be obtained applying the suc operation some number of times to 0. Then, we will see that neither a1 nor a2 can be obtained applying any number of times the suc operation to some other value in the algebra. But, then this means that we can match a1 and a2 to any pair of natural numbers, which implies that for instance we can match a1 to 2 and a2 to 1, violating the condition in the symbolic graph. First, we may notice that we may assume without loss of generality that A satisfies the axiom: e : suc(x) = suc(y) ⇒ x = y since for every homomorphism h : A → D there is a unique homomorphism h′ : A/ ≡e→ D such that the diagram below commutes: A i �� h // D A/ ≡e h′ 77 ooooooooooooo 21 / 25 Volume 30 (2010) Symbolic Attributed Graphs where ≡e is the congruence on A defined by the axiom e and i is the canonical homomorphism from A into its quotient, mapping every element from A into its congruence class. Vice versa, for every homomorphism h′ : A/ ≡e→ D there is a unique homomorphism h : A → D such that the diagram above commutes. Finally, we know that h(a1) = 0 or h(a2) = 0 or h(a1) = h(a2) if and only if h′(|a1|) = 0 or h ′(|a2|) = 0 or h ′(|a1|) = h ′(|a2|). Therefore, let us assume that A satisfies the above axiom. Now, let us notice that neither a1 nor a2 can be the value of some ground term suc n(0), for 0 ≤ n. The reason is that, otherwise, if n1 = n2 6= n the match would be impossible. We can also see that it is not possible that a1 is the value of some term sucn(a0), for 1 ≤ n and any a0 ∈ A. Otherwise, if n1 = 0 the match would be impossible, against the assumption, since if the match m′ satisfies m′(a0) = n0 then m ′(a1) would be n + n0. For similar reasons, we know that it is not possible that a2 is the value of some term sucn(a0), for 1 ≤ n and any a0 ∈ A. As a consequence, we can see that A′ = A\{a | (a = sucnA(a1))∨(a = suc n A(a2)) for some n ≥ 0} is a subalgebra of A. Suppose, otherwise, that A′ is not a subalgebra of A. This would mean that there is an element a′ ∈ A′ such that sucA(a ′) ∈ A\A′. But this would mean that sucA(a ′) = sucnA(a1) or sucA(a ′) = sucnA(a2). But this would imply one of the following cases: 1. sucA(a ′) = a1 or sucA(a ′) = a2. These two cases are impossible according to what we have proved above. 2. sucA(a ′) = sucnA(a1) or sucA(a ′) = sucnA(a2) for n ≥ 1. However, since A is assumed to satisfy the axiom e, this means that a′ = sucn−1A (a1) or a ′ = sucn−1A (a2), implying that a′ ∈ A\A′, against the hypothesis. As a consequence of the previous facts we know that every homomorphism h : A → D is uniquely determined by a homomorphism h′ : A′ → D and by the values of h(a1) and h(a2), in the sense that given h′, there is a unique h extending h′ satisfying h(a1) = n1 and h(a2) = n2, for any n1, n2 ∈ D, and vice versa. But this implies that there is a morphism m ′ : A → D satisfying m′(a1) 6= m ′(a2). In general, a symbolic transformation rule r′ = 〈L′ ←֓ K′ →֒ R′, Φ′〉 over a Σ-algebra D can be simulated by an attributed graph transformation rule r = (AL ← AK → AR) over a Σ-algebra A, if the specification SP, whose signature is Σ plus the labels in r′ (considered as constants), and whose set of axioms is Φ′, has an initial algebra TSP. The problem in the previous counter- example is that the associated specification has no initial algebra. In particular, to ensure the existence of initial algebras Φ′ should include only equations and conditional equations. 6 Related work and conclusion In this paper we have presented a new approach to deal with attributed graphs based on the new notion of symbolic graphs, showing that the new category is adhesive HLR, which means that it is adequate to define graph transformation. Proc. GraMoT 2010 22 / 25 ECEASST As far as we know, there are essentially three kinds of approaches to define attributed graphs and attributed graph transformation. First, we have the approaches [10, 7] where an attributed graph is a pair (G, D) consisting of a graph G and a data algebra D whose values are nodes in G. Second, we have the approaches [12, 1] where attributed graphs are seen as algebras over a given signature ASIG, where ASIG is the union of two signatures ASSIG, the graph signature and DSIG, the data signature, that overlap in the value sorts. In particular, ASSIG may be seen as a representation of the graph part of an attributed graph. In [2] these two approaches are compared showing that they are, up to a certain point, equivalent. Finally, we have the approach [19] based on the use of labelled graphs to represent attributed graphs, and of rule schemas to define graph transformations involving computations on the labels. That approach has some similarities with our approach, including the simplicity provided by the separation of the algebra and the graph part of attributed graphs. However, that approach has also some drawbacks that are briefly discussed in the introduction. However, a fundamental theory of graph transformation has been formulated only for [7], as a consequence of its characterization as an adhesive HLR category (for more detail see [4]). For this reason, in this paper we have essentially used that approach to study it in connection with our approach based on symbolic graphs. As we have seen, our approach can be considered an abstract version of [7], since we work at the specification level, rather than dealing directly with algebras to define the attributes. How- ever, as we have shown, it has more expressive power than [7] for the definition of graph trans- formation rules. In addition to the expressive power, using symbolic attributed graphs has some other advantages. For instance, in [15] working with symbolic attributed graphs simplifies cer- tain kinds of operations defined on transformation rules. For example, this is the case of the operation that, given two transformation rules r1 and r2, where r1 is a subrule of r2, yields a rule r3 that computes the remainder of r2 with respect to r1, i.e. what has not been computed by r1 but is computed by r2. In particular, when working with symbolic graphs the attribute conditions of r3 are just a simple combination of the attribute conditions of r1 and r2. However, if we would have worked with attributed graphs, computing the attributes for r3 may involve some complex equation solving. Moreover, we think that there are further aspects related to symbolic graph transformations that deserve some further study. In particular, using logical conditions to specify the attributes of a graph may allow us to postpone finding the solution to attribute constraints when performing graph transformation. This can make attributed graph transformation more efficient. In addition, a generalization of this idea would allow us to define a certain form of narrowing that may be useful in connection to several kind of problems. Bibliography [1] M. Berthold, I. Fischer, M.Koch: Attributed Graph Transformation with Partial Attribution. Technical Report 2000-2 (2000). [2] H. Ehrig: Attributed Graphs and Typing: Relationship between Different Representations. Bulletin of the EATCS 82: 175–190 (2004) 23 / 25 Volume 30 (2010) Symbolic Attributed Graphs [3] H. Ehrig, A. Habel: Graph Grammars with Application Conditions. In The Book of L (Grze- gorz Rozenberg and Arto Salomaa, Eds.), Springer (1986), 87–100. [4] Hartmut Ehrig, Karsten Ehrig, Ulrike Prange, Gabriele Taentzer: Fundamentals of Alge- braic Graph Transformation, Springer (2006). [5] Hartmut Ehrig, Annegret Habel, Julia Padberg, Ulrike Prange: Adhesive High-Level Re- placement Categories and Systems. In Graph Transformations, Second International Con- ference, ICGT 2004. Springer Lecture Notes in Computer Science 3256 (2004),144–160. [6] H. Ehrig, B. Mahr: Fundamentals of Algebraic Specifications 1: Equations and Initial Se- mantics. Vol. 6 of EATCS Monographs on Theoretical Computer Science. Springer, 1985. [7] H. Ehrig, U. Prange, G. Taentzer: Fundamental Theory for Typed Attributed Graph Transformation. In Graph Transformations, Second International Conference, ICGT 2004. Springer Lecture Notes in Computer Science 3256 (2004), 161–177. [8] Esther Guerra, Juan de Lara, Fernando Orejas: Pattern-Based Model-to-Model Transfor- mation: Handling Attribute Conditions. In Theory and Practice of Model Transformations, Second International Conference, ICMT 2009, Richard F. Paige (Ed.), Springer Lecture Notes in Computer Science 5563 (2009), pp. 83–99. [9] A. Habel, R. Heckel, G. Taentzer: Graph Grammars with Negative Application Conditions. Fundam. Inform. 26(3/4): 287–313 (1996). [10] R. Heckel, J. Küster, G. Taentzer: Towards Automatic Translation of UML Models into Semantic Domains. In Proc. APPLIGRAPH Workshop on Applied Graph Transformation 2002, pp. 11–22. [11] J. Jaffar, M. Maher, K. Marriot, and P. Stukey. The semantics of constraint logic programs. The Journal of Logic Programming, (37):1–46, 1998. [12] M. Löwe, M. Korff, A. Wagner: An Algebraic Framework for the Transformation of At- tributed Graphs. In Term Graph Rewriting: Theory and Practice. John Wiley and Sons Ltd. (1993) 185–199. [13] S. Lack, P. Sobocinski: Adhesive Categories. In Foundations of Software Science and Computation Structures, 7th International Conference, FOSSACS 2004 (Igor Walukiewicz, Ed.), Springer Lecture Notes in Computer Science 2987 (2004), 273–288. [14] P. Lucio, F. Orejas, E. Pasarella and E. Pino. A Functorial Framework for Constraint Nor- mal Logic Programming. In Algebra, Meaning, and Computation, Essays Dedicated to Joseph A. Goguen on the Occasion of His 65th Birthday, Kokichi Futatsugi, Jean-Pierre Jouannaud, José Meseguer (Eds.), Springer-Verlag Lecture Notes in Computer Science 4060 (2006), 555–577. [15] M. Naeem, R. Heckel, F. Orejas, F. Hermann, Incremental Service Composition based on Partial Matching of Visual Contracts. In Fundamental Approaches to Software Engineering, Proc. GraMoT 2010 24 / 25 ECEASST 13th International Conference, FASE 2010, Springer Lecture Notes in Computer Science 6013 (2010), 123–138. [16] F. Orejas: Attributed Graph Constraints. In Graph Transformations, 4th International Conference, ICGT 2008 (Hartmut Ehrig, Reiko Heckel, Grzegorz Rozenberg, Gabriele TaentzerEds.), Springer Lecture Notes in Computer Science 5214 (2008): 274–288. [17] F. Orejas: Attributed Graph Constraints for Attributed Graph Transformation. Journal of Symbolic Computation. To appear. [18] F. Orejas, L. Lambers: Delaying Constraint Solving in Symbolic Graph Transformation. To appear in ICGT 2010. [19] D. Plump, S. Steinert: Towards Graph Programs for Graph Algorithms. In Graph Trans- formations, Second International Conference, ICGT 2004. Springer Lecture Notes in Com- puter Science 3256 (2004), 128–143. [20] Rozenberg, G. (ed.): Handbook of Graph Grammars and Computing by Graph Transfor- mation, Vol 1 Foundations, World Scientific, 1997. 25 / 25 Volume 30 (2010) Introduction Preliminaries Basic algebraic concepts and notation E-graphs Attributed Graphs The category of symbolic graphs Symbolic graphs and attributed graphs Symbolic graph transformation and attributed graph transformation Related work and conclusion