On the decidability of model checking LTL fragments in monotonic extensions of Petri nets Electronic Communications of the EASST Volume 64 (2013) Proceedings of the XIII Spanish Conference on Programming and Computer Languages (PROLE 2013) On the decidability of model checking LTL fragments in monotonic extensions of Petri nets Marı́a Martos-Salgado and Fernando Rosa-Velardo 18 pages Guest Editors: Clara Benac Earle, Laura Castro, Lars-Åke Fredlund Managing Editors: Tiziana Margaria, Julia Padberg, Gabriele Taentzer ECEASST Home Page: http://www.easst.org/eceasst/ ISSN 1863-2122 http://www.easst.org/eceasst/ ECEASST On the decidability of model checking LTL fragments in monotonic extensions of Petri nets Marı́a Martos-Salgado1 and Fernando Rosa-Velardo2∗ 1 mrmartos@ucm.es Universidad Complutense de Madrid 2 fernandorosa@sip.ucm.es Universidad Complutense de Madrid Abstract: We study the model checking problem for monotonic extensions of Petri Nets, namely for two extensions of Petri nets: reset nets (nets in which places can be emptied by the firing of a transition with a reset arc) and ν -Petri nets (nets in which tokens are pure names that can be matched with equality and dynamically created). We consider several fragments of LTL for which the model checking problem is decidable for P/T nets. We first show that for those logics, model checking of reset nets is undecidable. We transfer those results to the case of ν -Petri nets. In order to cope with these negative results, we define a weaker fragment of LTL, in which negation is not allowed. We prove that for that fragment, the model checking of both reset nets and ν -Petri nets is decidable, though with a non primitive recursive complexity. Finally, we prove that the model checking problem for a version of that fragment with universal interpretation is undecidable even for P/T nets. Keywords: LTL, model checking, Petri nets, decidability, complexity 1 Introduction Temporal logics [4] have been established as a very expressive formalism for the specification of properties of computational concurrent systems. Model checking is the problem of deciding if a given system satisfies a given temporal formula. For infinite state systems the model checking problem is undecidable in general [15]. A very well known formalism for infinite state concurrent systems is that of Petri nets [6]. Among them, place/Transition nets (P/T nets) are potentially infinite state, but their expressive power is be- low Minsky machines (e.g., reachability is decidable for them [8]). Decidability and complexity of the model checking problem for P/T nets are well studied, and the corresponding decidability frontiers are well settled [13, 9, 12, 8]. Roughly speaking, model checking of P/T nets is undecid- able for any branching-time logic, while for linear time logics, “event-based” LTL is decidable, though “state-based” LTL is undecidable. In the last two decades, several monotonic extensions of Petri nets have appeared in the lit- erature. These extensions usually consist either on the extension of the firing rule of P/T nets, ∗ Authors supported by the Spanish projects STRONGSOFT TIN2012-39391-C04-04 and PROMETIDOS S2009/TIC-1465. 1 / 18 Volume 64 (2013) mailto:mrmartos@ucm.es mailto:fernandorosa@sip.ucm.es On the decidability of model checking LTL fragments in monotonic extensions of Petri nets or on the use of colours, that is, distinguishable tokens. We consider two simple extensions of P/T nets, one in each group: reset nets [7] and ν -Petri nets (ν -PN) [21]. In reset nets the firing of a transition can empty some places. Their modeling capabilities are discussed for instance in [14]. Tokens in ν -PNs are pure names, that can be created fresh, moved along the net and used to restrict the firing of transitions with name matching. Names can be seen as process identifiers [19], so that ν -PN can serve as the basis of models in which an unbounded number of components (which are in turn unbounded) synchronize. For example, they can be used to model resource-constrained workflow nets, an extension of workflow nets in which an arbitrary number of instances of the workflow can be executed concurrently [11]. In [5], they are used to give a semantics to an extension of BPEL [16] with instance isolation. In this paper we study the decidability of the model checking problem of these models. More precisely, we consider the logics for which model checking of P/T nets is decidable, and we study their decidability for the two extensions. In particular, we study LT L f , which is the fragment of LTL that uses only first as basic predicate [9], L (F), the fragment of LTL in which negation is only applied to basic predicates (not to operators), and the operators are X (next), F (eventually), ∧ and ∨ [12]; and L (GF), which is the fragment of LTL in which the only allowed composed operator is GF (globally future), the operators are F, ∨ and ∧ and negation is only applied to basic predicates [13]. Unfortunately, we conclude that the decidability results for P/T nets cannot be adapted, so that model checking for any of the logics considered is undecidable. In particular, we reduce LT L f model checking of lossy inhibitor nets, which is undecidable, to LT L f model checking of reset nets. Moreover, we prove that repeated coverability and reachability, which are undecidable for reset nets, can be expressed in L (GF) and L (F) respectively. As a first step to mitigate the previous undecidability result, we consider a fragment of LTL weaker than all the logics considered so far in which, in particular, we do not allow negations. We call that logic Fcov. We prove that the model checking problem for this logic is decidable for both models. In some of the subclasses of LTL considered in the literature [13, 12] a formula is said to be satisfied if there exists one run that satisfies it, as opposed to the more standard definition of LTL in which all runs are required to satisfy the formula. Even though the two interpretations are equivalent when negation can be used without restriction, this is not the case for the considered subclasses of LTL, neither for Fcov. We justify this definition by proving that already for P/T nets, Fcov model checking is undecidable under the universal interpretation. Table 1 summarizes the results on model checking of P/T nets, reset nets and ν -PNs. By “+” (resp. -) we denote that the model checking problem for the considered logic is decidable (resp. undecidable). If the references of the results are not given, then the result is either new (the ones with signs in bold letters) or follows directly from other results of the table. Outline: The rest of the paper is structured as follows. Section 2 presents some basic results and notations we use throughout the paper. Section 3 proves undecidability of the model checking problem for the considered logics, for reset nets and ν -PN. Section 4 defines Fcov and proves decidability of the model checking problem for reset nets and ν -PN, and undecidability for P/T nets in the universal case. In Section 5 we present our conclusions. Proc. PROLE 2013 2 / 18 ECEASST P/T Reset ν -PN LT L - [9] - - LT L f + [9] - [3] - L (GF) + [13] - - L (F) + [12] - - Fcov + + + ∀Fcov - - - Table 1: Summary of results. Those in bold signs are the new contributions of this paper. 2 Preliminaries A quasi order (qo) is a reflexive and transitive binary relation. For a qo ≤, we write a < b if a ≤ b and b 6≤ a. Labelled transition systems. A transition system is a tuple S = (S,L,→,init), where S is a (possibly infinite) set of states, L is a set of labels, init ∈ S is the initial state and →⊆ S × L × S 1. Given two states s1,s2 ∈ S and a ∈ L, we write s1 a → s2 instead of (s1,a,s2) ∈→, and s1 → s2 if s1 b → s2 for some b ∈ L. We denote by → ∗ the reflexive and transitive closure of → and by →+ the transitive closure of →. A run π of S is any sequence s0 a0 → s1 a1 → s2... such that si ai → si+1 for i ≥ 0. We define the length of a run π as n ∈ N if π = s0 a0 → s1 a1 → ... an → sn is a finite run, and ∞ if π is an infinite run. The reachability problem consists in deciding for a given state s f whether init →∗ s f . If S is endowed with a qo ≤ we can define the coverability problem, that consists in deciding, given s f ∈ S, whether some s ≥ s f is reachable. Then, we say that s covers s f . The repeated coverability problem is the problem of deciding whether a given state is covered infinitely often in some infinite run starting in init, that is, for a given s there is an infinite run init →+ s1 → + s2 → + ... such that s ≤ si for all i ≥ 1. Multisets. Given a (possibly infinite) arbitrary set A, we denote by A⊕ the set of finite multisets over A, that is, the mappings m : A → N for which su p p(m) = {a ∈ A | m(a) > 0} is finite. When needed, we identify each conventional set with the multiset defined by its characteristic function, and use set notation for multisets when convenient, with repetitions to account for multiplicities greater than one. Moreover, given two sets A and B, and an injection α : A → B, sometimes we interpret α as the function α : A⊕ → B⊕ such that given MA ∈ A, α(MA) = MB, where for each b ∈ B, MB(b) = n > 0 if there exists a ∈ A with α(a) = b and MA(a) = n, and MB(b) = 0 otherwise. Given two multisets m1,m2 ∈ A ⊕ we denote by m1 +m2 the multiset defined by (m1 +m2)(a) = m1(a) + m2(a). We define multiset inclusion as m1 ⊆ m2 if m1(a) ≤ m2(a) for all a ∈ A. If m1 ⊆ m2, we can define m2 − m1, taking (m2 − m1)(a) = m2(a)− m1(a). We denote by /0 ∈ A ⊕ the empty multiset, given by /0(a) = 0 for all a ∈ A. Petri nets. A Place/Transition net (P/T net for short) is a tuple N = (P,T,F) where P is a finite set of places, T is a finite set of transitions (with P ∩ T = /0) and F : (P × T ) ∪ (T × P) → N is 1 We use transition labels to homogeneously define logics based on states and events. 3 / 18 Volume 64 (2013) On the decidability of model checking LTL fragments in monotonic extensions of Petri nets • •a ab•• p q r t → • •a a• p q r t Figure 1: The firing of a transition in a P/T net. the flow function. Given t ∈ T , the multiset of preconditions of t is •t ∈ P⊕ given by (•t)(p) = F(p,t). Analogously, the postconditions of t are given by (t•)(p) = F(t, p). A marking is any m ∈ P⊕. For Petri nets we consider the order between markings given by multiset inclusion. This order defines the standard coverability problem for Petri nets. We say that a transition t is enabled at a marking m if for each p ∈ P, m(p) ≥ F(p,t). In that case, t can be fired from m, reaching a new marking m′, which is denoted by m t → m′, where m′ is given by m′(p) = (m(p)− F(p,t)) + F(t, p). The reachability, the coverability and the repeated coverability problems are all decidable for P/T nets [8]. In the rest of this paper, we represent places as circles, transitions as rectangles, the flow function as arrows and markings as tokens inside places. The arcs which represent the flow function are not labelled by any constant representing the corresponding values of F . That is because for all p ∈ P, t ∈ T with an arc going from p to t (resp. from t to p) in figures, we assume F(p,t) = 1 (resp. F(t, p) = 1). Example 1 In the P/T net in the left-hand side of Fig. 1, transition t is enabled, so it can be fired reaching the marking depicted in the right-hand side. Tokens have been consumed from p and r, and a token has been produced in q. As there is not a priority order over transitions, note that from the marking represented in the left-hand side, the other transition could have been fired instead of t, reaching a marking with a token in each place of the net. Now, we explain two extensions of P/T nets, namely reset nets and inhibitor nets. Both of them are defined from P/T nets by adding special arcs: reset arcs, which empty a place, and inhibitor arcs, which add to the enabling conditions the requirement that a certain place is empty. For both extensions, the concepts of preconditions, postconditions and marking are analogous to those for P/T nets. A reset net is a tuple N = (P,T,F,R), where (P,T,F) is a P/T net and R ⊆ P × T is a relation containing the so called reset arcs. The enabled transitions at a marking are defined as for P/T nets. An enabled transition t can be fired from a marking m reaching m′ given by: m′(p) = { (m(p)− F(p,t))+ F(t, p) if (p,t) /∈ R F(t, p) if (p,t) ∈ R Notice that if (p,t) ∈ R and F(t, p) = 0 (i.e., t does not put any token in p) then p has no tokens after the firing of t (hence p is reset). Example 2 Focus on Fig. 2. The double arc represents a reset arc from place r to t, that is, (r,t) ∈ R. Then, transition t is enabled in the marking represented in the net in the left-hand side Proc. PROLE 2013 4 / 18 ECEASST • •a ab•• p q r t′ t → • •a a• p q r t′ t Figure 2: The firing of a transition in a reset net. ab ab a bc be p1 p3 p2 p4 xy xν1 y ν1ν2 → aa ad a c de (d,e fresh) p1 p3 p2 p4 xy xν1 y ν1ν2 Figure 3: A simple ν -PN of the figure, and it can be fired, reaching the marking depicted in the right. All tokens in place r have been consumed in the firing of t due to the presence of the reset arc. Note that transition t′ is also enabled in the marking represented in the net in the left-hand side. Transitions with reset arcs do not have any priority over the rest of the enabled ones. Therefore, transition t′ could be fired from the first marking too. An inhibitor net is a tuple N = (P,T,F,I) where N = (P,T,F) is a P/T net, and I ⊆ P × T is a relation containing the inhibitor arcs (also called zero tests). We say that a transition t is enabled at a marking m if: • for each p ∈ P, m(p) ≥ F(p,t) and • for each (q,t) ∈ I, m(q) = 0 (place q is empty). Then, t can be fired from m, reaching the marking m′ given by m′(p) = (m(p)−F(p,t))+F(t, p) (as for P/T nets) 2. Inhibitor nets with two inhibitor arcs are already Turing complete [15], though, interestingly, inhibitor nets with only one inhibitor arc are not [18]. ν -PN. Another way in which P/T nets are extended in the literature is by considering distinguish- able tokens. Perhaps the most simple extension of P/T nets with (arbitrarily many) distinguish- able tokens are ν -Petri Nets [21], that encompass unboundedly many names (via a mechanism for fresh name creation) and the unbounded occurrence of each name. Let Var be a set of variables, and ϒ ⊂ Var a set of special variables for fresh name creation. A ν -Petri Net (ν -PN for short) is a tuple N = (P,T,F), where P and T are finite disjoint sets, and F : (P × T ) ∪ (T × P) → Var⊕ labels every arc by a multiset of variables. We denote pre(t) = ⋃ p∈P su p p(F(p,t)) (the set of variables in pre-arcs) and post(t) = ⋃ p∈P su p p(F(t, p)) (the set of variables in post-arcs). We also take Var(t) = pre(t)∪ post(t). 2 Actually, it is straightforward to simulate a reset arc using inhibitor arcs, in a way preserving reachability, cover- ability and repeated coverability. 5 / 18 Volume 64 (2013) On the decidability of model checking LTL fragments in monotonic extensions of Petri nets Let Id be an infinite set of names. A marking of a ν -PN is a mapping M : P → Id⊕ assigning to each place the multiset of tokens currently in it. We take Id(M) = ⋃ p∈P su p p(M(p)), that is, the set of names in M. Given a transition t ∈ T of a ν -PN, a mode for t is any injection σt : Var(t) → Id. As modes are injections, we can match names with equality (just by using the same variable more than once) and with inequality (by using different variables). We say that a transition t is enabled with a mode σt for a marking M, if for each ν ∈ ϒ, σt(ν) /∈ Id(M) and for all p ∈ P, σt(F(p,t)) ⊆ M(p). Then, t can be fired, and a new marking M′ is reached, given by M′(p) = (M(p)− σt(F(p,t)))+ σt(F(t, p)) for all p ∈ P. In that case we write M t → M′. Example 3 Fig. 3 depicts the ν -PN N given by N = ({p1, p2, p3, p4},{t},F) with F(p1,t) = {x,y}, F(p2,t) = {y}, F(t, p3) = {x,ν1}, F(t, p4) = {ν1,ν2}, and for (n,m) ∈ {(p3,t),(p4,t), (t, p1),(t, p2)}, F(n,m) = /0. We assume that ν1,ν2 ∈ ϒ. The initial marking is given by M0(p1) = {a,b}, M0(p2) = {b,c} and M0(p3) = M0(p4) = /0. The transition is fired with re- spect to a mode σ given by σ(x) = a, σ(y) = b, σ(ν1) = d and σ(ν2) = e. Note that names d and e are not in the initial marking, and therefore they are created new. Intuitively, each name in a marking of a ν -PN can represent a different process running in the same net. Therefore, we can represent the synchronization between processes and the creation of new ones. Given a marking M of a ν -PN and a set I of names, a renaming of M is any injection α : Id(M) → I. We say that M ⊑ M′ ⇔ there is a renaming α of M such that α(M)(p) ⊆ M′(p) for all p ∈ P. With this order, coverability is decidable for ν -PN, though reachability is undecidable for them [21]. Example 4 The marking M given by M(p1) = /0, M(p2) = /0, M(p3) = {a,d}, M(p4) = {a,c} is covered by the marking M′ on the right-hand side of Fig. 3. Note that, although there is not a token of name a in place p4, with the order we have defined, M is covered by M ′ by considering the renaming α , such that α(a) = d, α(d) = a and α(e) = c. Finally, note that both models induce labelled transition systems in the obvious way: the states of the labelled transition systems are the markings of the nets, the set of labels is the set of transitions, and if M is the set of markings of the net, the transition relation →⊆ M × T × M is the one such that m1 t →m2 in the net ⇔ (m1,t,m2) ∈→. 3 Model checking of Petri net extensions Temporal logics are used to specify dynamic properties of systems. They consider a set of atomic propositions (which express atomic properties), the boolean operators and several temporal oper- ators and path quantifiers, which allow us to express temporal properties. There are mainly two kinds of temporal logics: linear time logics and branching time logics. The properties that are expressed in branching time logics are about the computation tree [1], while the ones expressed in linear time logics are about the runs [17] (where we consider the notion of run defined in the preliminaries). In this paper we focus on linear time logics because model checking of P/T nets Proc. PROLE 2013 6 / 18 ECEASST with branching time logics is undecidable, even for very simple fragments [9]. The basic temporal operators used in temporal logics are X, F and U3. The most representative example of a linear time logic is LTL. Definition 1 An LTL formula is either an atomic proposition or a formula of the form ¬ϕ , ϕ ∧ ψ , ϕ ∨ ψ , Xϕ , Fϕ , or ϕ Uψ , where ϕ and ψ are LTL formulae. First, we explain the semantics of the temporal operators informally. LTL formulae are inter- preted over maximal runs, i.e., runs that are either infinite, or end in a deadlock state. Let ϕ be an LTL formula, S a transition system and π a maximal run starting in s. We write S ,π � ϕ to denote that π satisfies ϕ : • S ,π � Xϕ (next) holds if the property ϕ holds in the state that follows s in π . • S ,π � Fϕ (eventually) holds if the property ϕ holds in some state of π . • S ,π � ϕ Uψ (until) holds if there is a state of the run π such that ψ holds in that state, and ϕ holds at every preceding state on the run. We also define G (globally) as Gϕ = ¬F¬ϕ , so that S ,π � Gϕ holds if ϕ holds in every state of π . Now, we give the formal semantics of temporal operators. Let π = s0 a1 → s1 a2 → ... be a finite or infinite run of length n ∈ N∪{∞}. For n > 0, π i is defined as the suffix of the run π starting by the i-th state si. We suppose that the states and the actions of a system are labelled by the atomic propositions that they satisfy, that is, if a state s (or an action a) satisfies an atomic proposition p, then p ∈ L(s) ( p ∈ L(a) resp.), where L(s) (L(a)) represents the labels of s (a). The formal definition of the semantics of the previous operators is inductively defined as [4]: • T ,π � p ⇔ p ∈ L(s0)∨π 1 is defined (that is, the length of π is greater than 0) and ∈ L(a1). • T ,π � ¬ϕ1 ⇔ T ,π 2 ϕ1. • T ,π � ϕ1 ∨ ϕ2 ⇔ T ,π � ϕ1 or T ,π � ϕ2. • T ,π � ϕ1 ∧ ϕ2 ⇔ T ,π � ϕ1 and T ,π � ϕ2. • T ,π � Xϕ1 ⇔ π 1 is defined and T ,π 1 � ϕ1. • T ,π � Fϕ1 ⇔ there exists a k ≥ 0 such that T ,π k � ϕ1. • T ,π � Gϕ1 ⇔ for all i ≥ 0 such that π i is defined, T ,π i � ϕ1. • T ,π � ϕ1Uϕ2 ⇔ there exists a k ≥ 0 such that π k is defined, T ,π k � ϕ2 and for all 0 ≤ j < k,T ,π j � ϕ1. 3 Even though F can be defined in terms of U, we prefer to include it as a primitive temporal quantifier, since we will later disallow U. 7 / 18 Volume 64 (2013) On the decidability of model checking LTL fragments in monotonic extensions of Petri nets Note that in the previous definition, we assign the propositions they satisfy to both the states and the transition labels (a), defined for the labelled transition systems. The atomic propositions usually considered for P/T nets, are given by the following predicates: • cov(m), where m is a marking: cov(m) holds in π if the first marking in π covers m. • first(t), where t is a transition: first(t) holds in π if the first transition fired in π is t. Some works consider the atomic propositions ge(p,n) and en(t) [9]. The first one expresses that there are at least n tokens in place p, and the second states that t is enabled. We will not consider them since they are equivalent to cov({ n p,..., p}) and cov(•t), respectively. According to the standard definition, a system S satisfies an LTL formula ϕ , denoted by S |= ϕ iff every maximal run of the system starting in the initial state init satisfies it (universal interpretation). The model checking problem consists in deciding, given S and ϕ , whether S |= ϕ . The model checking problem is equivalent to deciding, given S and ϕ , the existence of one run starting in init satisfying the formula (existential interpretation), provided negation can be used without restriction, since S |= ϕ (under the universal interpretation) iff S 6|= ¬ϕ (under the existential interpretation). We consider different LTL fragments, built depending on which predicates and operators we consider. Definition 2 We consider the following fragments of LTL: • LT L f , the fragment of LTL that uses only first as basic predicate [9], • L (F), the fragment of LTL in which negation is only applied to basic predicates (not to operators), and the operators are X, F, ∧ and ∨ [12], • L (GF), the fragment of LTL in which the only allowed composed operator is GF, the operators are F, ∨ and ∧ and negation is only applied to basic predicates [13]. Example 5 The formula Ffirst(t), which expresses that t is eventually fired, is in L (F), but Gfirst(t) = ¬F¬first(t), which expresses that t is always fired, is not. The formula first(t) → GFfirst(t), which expresses that if t is the first transition being fired then t is fired infinitely often, is in L (GF), but Ffirst(t) → GFfirst(t) = ¬Ffirst(t)∨ GFfirst(t), which expresses that if t is eventually fired, then it is fired infinitely often, is not. In LT L f negation can be used without restriction, so that the universal and the existential inter- pretations are equivalent (i.e., their model checking decision problems are equivalent). However, this is not the case for L (F) and L (GF). Actually, they are defined using the existential inter- pretation in [12, 13]. For the subclasses of LTL considered, we have the following results. • LTL model checking is undecidable (with both first and cov), but LT L f model checking is decidable (with cov only) [9]. • L (F) model checking is decidable [12] (with existential interpretation), • L (GF) model checking is decidable [13] (with existential interpretation). Proc. PROLE 2013 8 / 18 ECEASST 3.1 Model checking of reset nets Let us show that the three logics which are decidable for P/T nets become undecidable for reset nets. Let us first consider LT L f . In [3] the model checking problem of LT L f is studied for lossy vector addition systems (lossy VAS) with tests for zero, which is proved to be undecidable. Let us see that we can adapt that result for reset nets. Let us first define the lossy version of a transition system in general. Definition 3 Given a transition system S = (S,→,init) and a quasi-order ≤ over S, the lossy version of S is Sl = (S,→l,init), where s1 →l s2 if and only if there exists two states s ′ 1 and s ′ 2 such that s1 ≥ s ′ 1 → s ′ 2 ≥ s2. A lossy Petri net is the lossy version of some Petri net. In the lossy version of a transition system, states can be spontaneously decreased. In the case of Petri nets, tokens may be lost just before or after a transition is fired. Example 6 Focus on Fig. 2. In the lossy version of the P/T net obtained by replacing the reset arc by a plain arc, despite r is not reseted by any reset arc of t, the second marking could be reached from the first one by first losing a token from r and then firing t. Reset nets can simulate lossy inhibitor nets, as we prove next. This fact is used in the proof of the next result. Proposition 1 LT L f model checking is undecidable for reset nets. Proof. We reduce LT L f model checking for lossy inhibitor nets, which is undecidable [3], to the same problem for reset nets. Let N = (P,T,F,I) be an inhibitor net. We define the reset net N′ = (P,T,F,I). We are going to prove that there is a surjective function between the runs of N and N′ that preserves the sequence of labels of runs and therefore, since the only atomic proposition in LT L f is first, given an LT L f formula ϕ , N |= ϕ iff N′ |= ϕ . Notice that since N′ is a reset net, checks for zero have been replaced by resets, that is, an inhibitor arc from a place p to a transition t in N is replaced by a reset arc from p to t in N′. The following holds: • m1 t →m2 in N ⇒ there is an m ′ 2 ≥ m2 such that m1 t →m′2 in N ′: the preconditions and effects of the firings of t in N and N′ are the same, except for the fact that we have replaced inhibitor arcs by reset arcs. Therefore, when a transition with an inhibitor arc in N is firing in N′, the corresponding place is reseted instead of being checked for zero. If there are tokens in such a place, all the tokens in it are removed, so there exist a possibility of losing tokens in our simulation if the place was not empty. If t has no inhibitor arc, and m1 t →m2 in N, t is enabled at m1 in N ′, and it can be fired reaching a marking greater or equal than m2, because some token may have been lost in the firing in N. Now, suppose that t has some inhibitor arcs, and m1 t →m2 in N. First of all, note that if a transition is enabled in N at a marking, it is enabled in N′ at the same marking. Moreover, the places with inhibitor arcs leading to t are empty in that marking. Therefore, when t is fired from m1 in N ′, these places are reset (hence staying empty). Therefore, the only differences in the effects of the firing of t in both nets come because of lossiness. In 9 / 18 Volume 64 (2013) On the decidability of model checking LTL fragments in monotonic extensions of Petri nets t t • • t t t •• •• t t t • • t t t A1 A2 B1 B2 m1 m′1 m ′ 2 m21 m22 m1 m′1 m ′ 12 m2 m′21 m′22 Figure 4: From lossy inhibitor nets to reset nets particular, since t may loose tokens in N, but not in N′, m1 t →m′2 in N ′, with m′2 ≥ m2. For example, focus on the left-hand side of Fig. 4. In the inhibitor nets depicted in this figure, given a place p and a transition t, we represent (p,t) ∈ I by an arc from p to t, with a circle in the place p. The marking m1 in the first lossy inhibitor net in A1 may evolve to m21 or m22 (m22 has lost the token). The corresponding reset net, depicted in A2 can only evolve t the marking m′2. However, note that m ′ 2 covers both m21 and m22. • m1 t →m2 in N ′ ⇒ m1 t →m2 in N: In particular, if N ′ resets a place, N can first loose tokens, thus emptying it, and then test for zero in that place. Therefore, the transition is fireable in N (because the preconditions of the firings of t in N and N′ are the same, except for the lossiness and the inhibitor arcs) and the place is empty at the end of both firings. Focus on the right-hand side of Fig. 4. Transition t is fireable from the marking m1 in the reset net in B1, reaching the marking m2. Despite t is not fireable from m ′ 1 = m1, the lossy inhibitor net may lose tokens, reaching m′12, from which t can be fired, reaching the markings m′21 or m ′ 22. Therefore, there is a surjective function between the runs of N and N′ that preserves the sequence of labels of runs. Note that this holds because reset nets are monotonic, so transitions which are fired in N at a marking m which has lost tokens, can be fired from the corresponding marking m′ of N′, without loss of tokens, because m′ ≥ m. Since the only atomic proposition in LT L f is first, N |= ϕ iff N′ |= ϕ and we conclude. Let us now focus on the two other fragments of LTL. The case for L (GF) is straightforward: Proposition 2 L (GF) model checking of reset nets is undecidable. Proof. It is enough to consider that GFcov(M), which is a formula in L (GF), expresses the repeated coverability problem, which is undecidable for reset nets [2]. Proc. PROLE 2013 10 / 18 ECEASST However, not only that fragment, but the weaker fragment L (F), which is decidable for P/T nets [12], is undecidable for reset nets. The following proof uses ideas from [12], in which L (F) model checking is reduced to reachability for P/T nets. Proposition 3 L (F) model checking of reset nets is undecidable. Proof. We reduce reachability, which is undecidable for reset nets [2], to model checking some formula in L (F). Let N = (P,T,F,R) be a reset net and m a marking of N. We can compute the set of the least markings greater than m.4 Indeed, that set is just {mp | p ∈ P}, where mp is given by mp(q) = m(q) for q 6= p and mp(p) = m(p) + 1. For example, the set of the least markings greater than the marking depicted in the net in the left-hand side of Fig. 2 is {mp,mq,mr}, where mp = {p, p,r,r}, mq = {p,q,r,r} and mr = {p,r,r,r}. Then, m is reachable in N iff there is a reachable marking m′ that covers m, but does not cover any mp, because this would imply that in each place p, m′ has exactly m(p) tokens (because it does not cover mp). Therefore, m is reachable in N iff the formula F(cov(m)∧ ∧ p∈P ¬cov(mp)) is satisfied. The previous proof is based on obtaining a formula which expresses the reachability problem. In order to obtain this formula, there is an important property that reset nets satisfy: Given a marking m, we are able to compute a finite set of markings S = {m1,...,mn} such that for each mi ∈ S, mi ⊃ m and if m ′ ⊃ m, then there is mi ∈ S such that m ′ ⊇ mi. Intuitively, we can compute the finite set of “the smallest markings greater than m”. As we can build that set, a marking m f coincides with m if and only if m f covers m and m f does not cover any marking of S. 3.2 Model checking of ν -PN We first recall from [21] how ν -PN can simulate reset nets (see Fig. 5, where the double arrow represents a reset arc). For each place p of a reset net N we consider a copy of it and a new place p′ in the ν -PN N′ we build. The main idea of the construction is to store in place p′ a single token of the colour that we consider valid in the current marking for place p of N′. That is, the tokens in p of the colour of the token in p′ will be considered valid, and the rest of the tokens in p will be considered garbage. For example, in the ν -PN of Fig. 5, there are two valid tokens in place r, because the colour of the token in r′ is b. The construction of N′ guarantees that for each place p of N, the place p′ of N′ contains a single token at any time. The firing of any transition ensures that the token being used in the place p of N′ coincides with that in p′ (by labelling both arcs with the same variable xp). Every time a transition resets a place p of N, the token in p′ is replaced by a fresh one, so that no token remaining in place p of N′ can be used from then on. For example, suppose we fire transition t in Fig. 5. Then, a new colour is put in r′, and therefore the tokens of name b in r cannot be used anymore. Therefore, this simulation can introduce some garbage tokens (those in p when p is reset). Given a marking m we define m′ by arbitrarily choosing a different name ap ∈ Id for each p ∈ P, and taking m′(p′) = {ap}, and m ′(p) = {ap, m(p)... ,ap}. Then, if m0 is the initial marking of N, N ′ 4 In order theory that set is called the cover of m, though we prefer not to overload that term here. 11 / 18 Volume 64 (2013) On the decidability of model checking LTL fragments in monotonic extensions of Petri nets • •a ab•• p q r t → a aa a c cbbb a p q r p′ r′ q′ t xp xq xp xq xr ν xr xq xq xr Figure 5: A reset net and the corresponding ν -PN. The double arrow represents a reset arc with initial marking m′0 simulates N. The previous simulation preserves all behavioral properties. Then, the following is a straightforward consequence of Prop. 1. Corollary 1 LT L f model checking is undecidable for ν -PN. The previous simulation also preserves coverability. More precisely, if a marking m is cover- able in the reset net N, then the marking m′ of N′ defined above is coverable too. The markings in the simulation may contain some garbage, which is created when we simulate the firing of a reset, because instead of removing all tokens of some place p, we change the name of the token in p′, making all tokens in p become garbage. However, the presence of that garbage is irrelevant for coverability. In particular, we have the following. Proposition 4 Repeated coverability is undecidable for ν -PN. Proof. It is enough to consider that repeated coverability is undecidable for reset nets [2], and that the previous simulation preserves repeated coverability. We prove that m can be repeatedly covered from m0 in N iff M ′ can be repeatedly covered from m′0 in N ′. Indeed, if m is repeatedly covered there is a run m0 → + m1 → + m2 → + ... of N such that mi ≥ m for all i ≥ 1. By construc- tion of N′, there is a run m′0 → + M1 → + M2 → + ... of N′ such that Mi ≥ m ′ i ≥ m ′ for all i ≥ 1, so m′ is repeatedly covered. Moreover, Mi coincides with m ′ i when considering only the “valid tokens” of Mi (and after possibly renaming the names carried by the tokens). The converse is analogous. Once we know that repeated coverability is undecidable, undecidability of L (GF) model checking is trivial. Corollary 2 L (GF) model checking of ν -PN is undecidable. Next, we see the undecidability of L (F) model checking for ν -PN. Proposition 5 L (F) model checking of ν -PN is undecidable. Proof. The proof is analogous to the one of the same result for reset nets. We reduce reachability in ν -PN, which is undecidable [21], to the model checking problem for some formula in L (F). Let N = (P,T,F) be a ν -PN. Given a marking M, we can compute the finite set of the least markings greater than M. Indeed, given p ∈ P and c ∈ Id(M)∪{b}, with b /∈ Id(M), we define Proc. PROLE 2013 12 / 18 ECEASST Mpc given by Mpc(q) = M(q) if p 6= q and Mpc(p) = M(p)+{c}. Then, the set we are looking for is {Mpc | p ∈ P,c ∈ Id(M)∪{b}}. For example, consider a net with two places p and q, and a marking M with one token a in p and empty in q. The set of the least markings greater than this marking is {Mpa,Mpb,Mqa,Mqb}, where Mpa(p) = {a,a}, Mpa(q) = /0, Mpb(p) = {a,b}, Mpb(q) = /0, Mqa(p) = {a}, Mqa(q) = {a}, Mqb(p) = {b} and Mqb(q) = {a}. Therefore, M is reachable in N iff N |= F(cov(M)∧ ∧ p,c ¬cov(Mpc)), and we conclude. 4 A decidable fragment In the previous section we have proved the undecidability of model checking of reset nets and ν -PN for some logics, whose model checking problem is known to be decidable for P/T nets. In this section we define a restriction of L (F), thus obtaining a fragment that is less expressive than all the logics considered here. Definition 4 Fcov is the fragment of L (F) in which negation is not allowed. In this logic we can express bounded repeated coverability. However, Fcov cannot express properties like ¬cov(M). In particular, the formula F(cov(M) ∧ ∧ p∈P ¬cov(Mp)) which ex- presses reachability, is not a formula of Fcov. As for L (F), we consider existential interpretation, so that a formula is satisfied if some maximal run starting in the initial marking satisfies it. We will see that Fcov model checking is decidable both for reset nets and for ν -PN. Later, we will consider ∀Fcov, the version of Fcov with universal interpretation, and we will prove that ∀Fcov model checking is undecidable even for P/T nets. Proposition 6 Fcov model checking of reset nets is decidable. Proof. Let N = (P,T,F,R) be a reset net and φ a formula in Fcov. We proceed by induction on the nesting of operators F in φ . If φ is a boolean combination of formulae of the form cov(m), it is trivial to decide whether φ is satisfied because multiset inclusion is decidable. Let us suppose that we can check each formula with at most n > 0 nested F operators. Let φ be a boolean combination of formulae of the form cov(m) and Fϕ , where ϕ has at most n nested F operators, and let us see that we can decide whether each of those formulae Fϕ is satisfied (and hence, whether φ is satisfied). Using standard techniques, we can write Fϕ as F( ∨ i(( ∧ j cov(mi j)) ∧ ( ∧ k Fϕik))), where ϕik are formulae of Fcov with at most n − 1 nested operators. That formula is equivalent to the formula ∨ i F(( ∧ j cov(mi j)) ∧ ( ∧ k Fϕik)), that is, a disjunction of formulae of the form F(cov(m1)∧ ... ∧ cov(mq)∧ Fϕ1 ∧ ... ∧ Fϕr), where q and r are not simultaneously zero, and each ϕk has at most n − 1 nested operators. Let us distinguish the following two cases: (a) If q = 0 the formula is of the form F(Fϕ1 ∧ ...∧ Fϕr), which is equivalent to Fϕ1 ∧ ...∧ Fϕr. Hence, we can apply the induction hypothesis to each Fϕk and we are done. (b) If q > 0, we modify N, thus obtaining N′, by adding transitions t1,...,tq,tq+1 and places p0, p1,..., pq as follows. We add p0 as precondition/postcondition of every transition in N. More- over, ti moves a token from pi−1 to pi, provided mi is covered. Finally, tq+1 can be fired only one time (for which we add a new place with a single token initially, as precondition of tq+1), 13 / 18 Volume 64 (2013) On the decidability of model checking LTL fragments in monotonic extensions of Petri nets p0 t1 p1 p2 t2 • paux t3 m1 m2N Figure 6: Construction of N′ in Prop. 6 setting again a token in p0, and having pq as precondition and postcondition. This construction is represented in Fig. 6, for q = 2. Then, N′ behaves as N, but when every mi can be covered, it can sequentially fire t1,...,tq,tq+1. Hence, every mi can be simultaneously covered in N iff pq can be covered in N′. We consider the following two sub-cases: (b.1) If r = 0 then the formula is of the form F(cov(m1)∧ ...∧ cov(mq)) and hence equivalent to Fcov({pq}), which expresses a coverability problem, so that it can be decided. (b.2) Consider now that r > 0. For any formula ϕ , we define ϕ′ as follows: • If ϕ = cov(m) then ϕ′ = cov(m +{pq}). • If ϕ = ϕ1 ∧ ϕ2 then ϕ′ = ϕ′1 ∧ ϕ ′ 2. Analogously, if ϕ = ϕ1 ∨ ϕ2 then ϕ ′ = ϕ′1 ∨ ϕ ′ 2. • If ϕ = Fϕ1 then ϕ′ = Fϕ′1. Then, F(cov(m1)∧ ...∧ cov(mq)∧ Fϕ1 ∧ ...∧ Fϕr) holds in N iff F(Fϕ′1 ∧ ...∧ Fϕ ′ r) holds in N′. Notice that the number of nested F operators is the same for ϕk and ϕ′k. Then, by (a) we are done. The proof of the same result for ν -PNs is analogous to the previous one.5 Proposition 7 Fcov model checking is decidable for ν -PN. Proof. The construction for ν -PN is the same as the previous one. The only difference is that the names in the markings of the formulae need to be handled correctly in N′, by choosing a different variable for each name in a marking to label the arcs. Since in particular Fcov allows us to express coverability, which has a non primitive recursive complexity for reset nets [22] and for ν -PN [21], we have the following: Proposition 8 The complexity of Fcov model checking is non primitive recursive for reset nets and for ν -PN. 5 Actually, the same is true for any model that belongs to the class of Well Structured Transitions Systems, with fairly minor conditions. Proc. PROLE 2013 14 / 18 ECEASST To conclude, let us see that the version of Fcov with universal interpretation, that we denote by ∀Fcov, is undecidable even for P/T nets. Intuitively, formulae in ∀Fcov are global properties of some trace, or equivalently, eventuality properties of every trace. For instance, Fcov(M) expresses that every run starting from the initial marking eventually covers M. We reduce control-state reachability for Two Counter Machines, which is undecidable [15]. A Two Counter Machine (TCM for short) is a tuple C = (Q,{c1,c2},Ins,q0), where Q is a finite set of control states, c1 and c2 are the two counters, Ins is a set of instructions and q0 ∈ Q is the initial state. An instruction can be of the following three forms: Inc(p,i,q), Dec(p,i,q) or Zero(p,i,q), where p,q ∈ Q and i ∈ {1,2}, for the increasing of the counter ci, the decreasing of ci, or check for zero of ci respectively. A configuration of C is given by a tuple 〈q,c1 = n1,c2 = n2〉, where q ∈ Q is the current state, and n1,n2 ∈ N are the current values of the counters. The initial configuration is 〈q0,c1 = 0,c2 = 0〉. In a configuration 〈p,c1 = n1,c2 = n2〉, we may execute Inc(p,i,q) ∈ Ins, reaching 〈q,c1 = n′1,c2 = n ′ 2〉, where n ′ i = ni + 1 and n ′ 3−i = n3−i. If ni > 0 we may execute Dec(p,i,q) ∈ Ins, reaching 〈q,c1 = n ′ 1,c2 = n ′ 2〉, where n ′ i = ni − 1 and n ′ 3−i = n3−i. Finally, if ni = 0, we can execute Zero(p,i,q) ∈ Ins, reaching 〈q,c1 = n1,c2 = n2〉. The control-state reachability problem consists in deciding, given q ∈ Q, whether a configuration of the form 〈q,c1 = n1,c2 = n2〉 is reachable. It is well-known that this is an undecidable problem [15]. Example 7 Consider the TCM C = (Q,{c1,c2},Ins, p), with Q = {p,q,r} and Ins = {Inc(p,c1,q), Inc(q,c2, p),Zero(p,c2,r)}. In order to reach a configuration with state r, the first instruction to be executed must be Zero(p,c2,r). Otherwise, the two first executed instructions are Inc(p,c1,q) and Inc(q,c2, p), so we reach a configuration with c1 = c2 = 1. As there is not a Dec instruction in this machine, after executing this instructions we cannot reach a configuration with c2 = 0 anymore, and therefore we cannot reach state r anymore. We consider only deterministic TCM, that is, TCM such that at each reachable configura- tion there is at most one instruction that can be executed. Moreover, without loss of generality we assume that if Zero(p,i,q) ∈ Ins then there is no other instruction of the form Inc(p′, j,q), Dec(p′, j,q) or Zero(p′, j,q) in Ins, that is, q can only be reached by that instruction (defined as requirement †). Indeed, for each instruction I = Zero(p,i,q) ∈ Ins we can add two states q1,q2, and replace I by Zero(p,i,q1), Inc(q1,i,q2), Dec(q2,i,q). 6 The control-state reachability problem for deterministic TCM is still undecidable. Proposition 9 ∀Fcov model checking of P/T nets is undecidable. Proof. We reduce the control-state reachability problem for deterministic TCM to the model checking problem of a formula in ∀Fcov. Let C = (Q,{c1,c2},Ins,q0) be a deterministic TCM and pend ∈ Q. We use the standard simulation of a TCM by means of a P/T net. We define N = (Q ∪{c1,c2},Ins,F), where: • F(p,Inc(p,i,q)) = 1, F(Inc(p,i,q),q) = 1, and F(Inc(p,i,q),ci) = 1 (a token is moved from p to q, and a token is added to ci). 6 If we allow instructions that do not modify the counter then it is enough to add a single state q1 and an instruction changing the state from q1 to q. 15 / 18 Volume 64 (2013) On the decidability of model checking LTL fragments in monotonic extensions of Petri nets p Inc(p,c1,q) q Inc(q,c2, p) r Zero(p,c2,r) c1 c2 Figure 7: Construction of Prop. 9 for the TCM of Ex. 7 • F(p,Dec(p,i,q)) = 1, F(Dec(p,i,q),q) = 1, and F(ci,Dec(p,i,q)) = 1 (a token is moved from p to q, and a token is removed from ci). • F(p,Zero(p,i,q)) = 1 and F(Zero(p,i,q),q) = 1 (a token is moved from p to q). Moreover, F(n,m) = 0 elsewhere, and the initial marking of N is {q0}. In N, the number of tokens in ci represent the value of the counter ci in C. Increasing and decreasing transitions are simulated faithfully. However, the simulation of a transition Zero(p,i,q) can “cheat”, whenever it is fired with tokens in ci. In that case, notice that the marking {ci,q} can be covered. Moreover, because q cannot be reached using a different instruction (requirement (†) above), we know that if such marking is covered then the current simulation has cheated. Focus on Fig. 7, which represents the net built from the TCM of Ex. 7. Note that transition Zero(p,c2,r) can be fired even after firing Inc(p,c1,q) and Inc(q,c2, p), when c2 is not empty. In this case, this simulation has cheated. We consider ϕ = F(cov(pend)∨ ∨ m∈J cov(m)), where J = {{ci,q} | Zero(p,i,q) ∈ Ins}. Notice that all the cheating runs satisfy ϕ . We prove that pend can be reached in C if and only if N |= ϕ . For the if part, if C reaches pend then the non-cheating run of N eventually covers pend , so that it satisfies ϕ . Since cheating runs always satisfy ϕ , every run of N satisfies ϕ . Conversely, if C does not reach pend then the non-cheating run of N does not satisfy ϕ . 5 Conclusions and future work Table 1 summarizes the results on model checking of P/T nets, reset nets and ν -PNs. In partic- ular, in this work we have proved the undecidability of the fragments LT L f , L (GF) and L (F) for reset nets and ν -PN. We have defined Fcov, a very simple restriction of LTL that does not allow negations, for which model checking of reset nets and ν -PN is decidable. Actually, we claim this is the case for any model in the class of Well Structured Transition Systems [10] under fairly minor conditions, since the model checking problem can be reduced to a finite number of coverability problems. Moreover, we have proved that if we require that every run starting from the initial marking satisfies a formula, then even for the simple case of Fcov and P/T nets, the corresponding model checking problem is undecidable. Proc. PROLE 2013 16 / 18 ECEASST Further study, in order to define more expressive logics for which the model checking problem is decidable, is needed. A possible direction in such study could be the definition of logics with atomic propositions that are more specific of the particular model. Such direction links with the so called Yen’s logics for P/T nets. In the case of ν -PN, the corresponding logic should be able to express properties about the names in the marking. Language theory was used to prove the difference of expressiveness between reset nets and ν -PNs in [20]. In this sense, it would certainly be interesting to find a logic which distinguishes between reset nets and ν -PNs. Finally, we have proved that the complexity of Fcov model checking is non primitive recursive for reset nets and for ν -PN. However, it would be interesting to perform a finer complexity analysis. Bibliography [1] M. Ben-Ari, Z. Manna and A. Pnueli. “The Temporal Logic of Branching Time”. Acta Informatica 20, 207-226(1983). [2] R. Bonnet. “Theory of Well-Structured Transition Systems and Extended Vector-Addition Systems”. Thèse de doctorat, Laboratoire Spécification et Vérification, ENS Cachan, France (2013). [3] A. Bouajjani and R. Mayr. “Model Checking Lossy Vector Addition Systems”. Interna- tional Symposium on Theoretical Aspects of Computer Science, LNCS vol. 1563, 323-333 (1999). [4] E. M. Clarke, O. Grumberg, and D. A. Peled. “Model Checking”. MIT Press Cam- bridge(1999). [5] G. Decker, M. Weske. “Instance Isolation Analysis for Service-Oriented Architectures”. Proceedings of the 2008 IEEE International Conference on Services Computing, 1, 249- 256 (2008). [6] J. Desel and W. Reisig. Place/transition petri nets. Lectures on Petri Nets I: Basic Models, LNCS vol. 1491, pp.122–173. Springer, 1998. [7] C. Dufourd, A. Finkel, and Ph. Schnoebelen. “Reset Nets Between Decidability and Unde- cidability”. International Colloquium on Automata Languages and Programming, LNCS vol. 1443, 103-115 (1998). [8] J. Esparza and M. Nielsen. “Decidability Issues for Petri Nets”. BRICS Report Series, RS-94-8 (1994). [9] J. Esparza. “On the decidability of model checking for several µ -calculi and Petri nets”. Colloquium on Trees in Algebra and Programming, LNCS vol. 787, 115-129 (1994). [10] A.Finkel, and P.Schnoebelen. Well-Structured Transition Systems Everywhere! Theoretical Computer Science 256(1-2):63-92 (2001). 17 / 18 Volume 64 (2013) On the decidability of model checking LTL fragments in monotonic extensions of Petri nets [11] K. van Hee, A. Serebrenik, N. Sidorova and M. Voorhoeve. Soundness of Resource- Constrained Workflow Nets. Applications and Theory of Petri Nets, LNCS vol. 3536, 250- 267 (2005) [12] R. Howell, L. Rosier and H. Yen. “A taxonomy of fairness and temporal logic problems for Petri nets”. Theoretical Computer Science 82, 341-372 (1991). [13] P. Jančar. “Decidability of a Temporal Logic Problem for Petri Nets.”. Theoretical Com- puter Science 74, 71-93 (1990). [14] C. Lakos, S. Christensen. A General Systematic Approach to Arc Extensions for Coloured Petri Nets. Applications and Theory of Petri Nets. LNCS vol. 815, pp. 338-357 (1994) [15] M. L. Minsky. “Computation: Finite and Infinite Machines” Prentice-Hall (1967). [16] OASIS Web Services Business Process Execution Language Version 2.0. OASIS Standard (2007). http://docs.oasis-open.org/wsbpel/2.0/wsbpel-v2.0.pdf [17] A. Pnueli. “The Temporal Semantics of Concurrent Programs” Theoretical Computer Sci- ence, 13, 1-20(1981). [18] Klaus Reinhardt. “Reachability in Petri Nets with Inhibitor Arcs” Electr. Notes Theor. Comput. Sci. 223: 239-264 (2008). [19] F. Rosa-Velardo and D. de Frutos-Escrig. Name creation vs. replication in Petri Net sys- tems. Fundamenta Informaticae 88(3). IOS Press (2008) 329-356. [20] F. Rosa-Velardo and G. Delzanno. “Language-based Comparison of Nets with Black To- kens, Pure Names and Ordered Data.”. International Conference on Language and Au- tomata Theory and Applications, LNCS vol. 6031, pp. 524-535. Springer (2010) [21] F. Rosa-Velardo and D. de Frutos-Escrig. Decidability and Complexity of Petri Nets with Unordered Data. Theoretical Computer Science 412(34): 4439-4451 (2011) [22] Ph. Schnoebelen. “Revisiting Ackermann-Hardness for Lossy Counter Machines and Reset Petri Nets”. Theoretical Computer Science, LNCS vol. 6281, pp. 616,628 (2010). Proc. PROLE 2013 18 / 18 http://docs.oasis-open.org/wsbpel/2.0/wsbpel-v2.0.pdf Introduction Preliminaries Model checking of Petri net extensions Model checking of reset nets Model checking of -PN A decidable fragment Conclusions and future work