1. FS416_Stettler © Matteo Johannes Stettler ISSN: 1832-5203 DOI: https://doi.org/10.22439/fs.vi33.6798 Foucault Studies, No. 33, 1-23, December 2022 https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0/ ARTICLE The Use and Misuse of Pleasure: Hadot Contra Foucault on the Stoic Dichotomy Gaudium-Voluptas in Seneca MATTEO JOHANNES STETTLER Deakin University, Australia ABSTRACT. Chapter II of Foucault's The Care of the Self, 'The Cultivation of the Self,' is arguably one of the most controversial sections of the entire History of Sexuality. The diatribe over this chap- ter was initially mounted by Pierre Hadot's critical essay 'Reflections on the Idea of the 'Cultivation of the Self." Therein, Hadot objects to Foucault’s dissolution of the Stoic doctrinal antinomy be- tween voluptas ('pleasure') and gaudium ('joy') and, thereby, to the relegation of the latter notion to the subordinate status of 'another form of pleasure', on the one side, and of Seneca himself to the problematic rank of a sort of Epicurean on the other. The present investigation aims to unveil this aspect of the Foucault-Hadot querelle as only a pseudo-controversy engendered by Seneca recur- ring to two different terminological registers throughout his writings: the so-called verbum publi- cum and the significatio Stoica. Keywords: Pierre Hadot, Michel Foucault, Seneca, pleasure, joy, philosophy as a way of life. INTRODUCTION Chapter II of Foucault's The Care of the Self, 'The Cultivation of the Self,' is undoubtedly one of the most suggestive and controversial sections of the entire History of Sexuality mul- tivolume series. Suggestive, first, for it is philosophically situated at the intersection of an "ever-increasing tension" in Foucault's late research intentions: as Gros notes, that of "writ- ing a reorganized history of ancient sexuality in terms of the problematic of techniques of the self" and, on the other hand, "to study these techniques for themselves, in their historic- ethical dimensions."1 Controversial, second, for it eventually came at the center of many 1 Frédéric Gros, "Course Context," in The Hermeneutics of the Subject: Lectures at the Collège de France 1981-1982 (2005), 513-514. From Elden’s remarkable reconstruction in Foucault’s Last Decade, we apprehend that the second of these projects, originally envisioned by Foucault as “a book separate from the sex series” with the title Le Souci de Soi, never saw the light at the time of his premature passing. Michel Foucault, "On the Genealogy of Ethics: An Overview of Work in Progress," in Ethics: Subjectivity and Truth; The Essential Works of Michel Foucault 1954-1984 Vol. I, ed. Paul Rabinow (1997), 255. Besides Chapter II and III of the eventually The Use and Misuse of Pleasure Foucault Studies, No. 33, 1-23. 2 discussions in contemporary literature. The diatribe was ignited early on by Foucault's coe- val and conational philosopher and classicist Pierre Hadot and his critical essay 'Reflections on the Idea of the 'Cultivation of the Self',' explicitly conceived, as its title suggests, as a di- rect rejoinder to this precise chapter of Foucault's The Care of the Self.2 Amid various cri- tiques, Hadot rejects Foucault's presentation of Hellenistic-Roman ethics (and, more criti- cally, of Stoic ethics) as "an ethics of the pleasure one takes in oneself."3 He objects to Fou- cault’s dissolution of the Stoic antinomy between voluptas ('pleasure') and gaudium ('joy'), and, thereby, the relegation of the notion of gaudium to the subordinate status of "another form of pleasure", on the one side, and of Seneca himself to the problematic rank of an Epi- curean of sorts on the other.4 On this precise point of contention of the Hadot-Foucault que- relle, contemporary scholarship fragmented into a variety of more or less diverse interpreta- tive positions, depending on their respective reception of Hadot's contentions. Re-echoing Hadot's own concerns, Davidson has argued that "it is misleading for Foucault to speak of the joy described by Seneca as 'a form of pleasure,'" concluding that "Hadot's interpretation of these ancient texts is the historically accurate interpretation."5 Montanari instead received Hadot's critique as fundamentally unwarranted as, he argues, Foucault did sufficiently man- age to differentiate the notions of voluptas and gaudium by assigning them diverse modes of manifestation (exogenous vs. endogenous).6 published The Care of the Self, traces of this material are to be found in Foucault’s 1981-1982 Lectures at the Collège de France (The Hermeneutics of the Subject), the content of which, as Elden noted, “is much closer to what Foucault originally envisioned Le Souci de Soi would do than the actually published book of that title is.” Elden, Foucault's Last Decade, 170. 2 Note that elsewhere Hadot sets himself to “observe to what extent our [sc. his and Foucault’s] interests and concerns converged by comparing the summaries of Foucault’s 1981-82 course at the Annuaire du Collège de France and [his own] article ‘Exercices spirituels.’” Pierre Hadot, "An Interrupted Dialogue with Michel Foucault: Convergences and Divergences," in The Selected Writings of Pierre Hadot: Philosophy as Practice, ed. Matthew Sharpe and Federico Testa (2020), 228. As Gros noted, The Hermeneutics indeed “appears as a con- siderably expanded and developed version of one small chapter in The Care of the Self entitled ‘The Culture of the Self’” (in Burchell’s English translation), or, alternatively, ‘The Cultivation of the Self’ (in Hurley’s). Gros, "Course Context," 508. 3 Pierre Hadot, Philosophy as a Way of Life: Spiritual Exercises from Socrates to Foucault (1995), 207. A reconstruc- tion of Hadot and Foucault’s respective position on this issue has recently been advanced by Cassiana Lopes Stephan, "Pierre Hadot e Michel Foucault: sobre a felicidade estoica e a experiência da alegria," Sapere Aude 7:13 (2016). A classical contribution on the dialogue between Michel Foucault and Pierre Hadot more gener- ally remains Thomas Flynn, "Philosophy as a Way of Life: Foucault and Hadot," Philosophy and Social Criticism 31:5-6 (2005). On Hadot’s and Foucault’s different conceptualizations of the spiritual exercises of the ancients, see Elettra Stimilli, "Esercizi spirituali o tecniche di vita? Pierre Hadot e Michel Foucault a confronto," Pensiero: rivista di filosofia 46:1/2 (2008). More recently also Laura Cremonesi, "Pierre Hadot and Michel Foucault on Spiritual Exercises: Transforming the Self, Transforming the Present," in Foucault and the History of Our Present, ed. Sophie Fuggle, Yari Lanci and Martina Tazzioli (2015). 4 Hadot, Philosophy as a Way of Life, 207. 5 Arnold I. Davidson, "Ethics as Ascetics: Foucault, the History of Ethics, and Ancient Thought," in The Cambridge Companion to Foucault, ed. Gary Gutting (2005), 129 and 144, n23. 6 Moreno Montanari, Hadot e Foucault nello specchio dei Greci: La filosofia antica come esercizio di trasformazione (2009), 25-27. Other aspects of the Hadot-Foucault querelle are discussed by the same author in "La Filosofia antica come esercizio spirituale e cura di sé nelle interpretazioni di Pierre Hadot e Michel Foucault," Studi Urbinati, B - Scienze Umane e Sociali 80 (2010). MATTEO STETTLER Foucault Studies, No. 33, 1-23. 3 However, the scholar who went the furthest in exploring this issue is undoubtedly Ir- rera, who devoted to it an entire article. 7 According to the latter, not only does Hadot himself often fail to distinguish gaudium from voluptas in his own historical-doctrinal re- construction of the philosophical works of antiquity,8 but, as the scholar is keen to qualify, in Hadot's own framework, the only way in which this distinction could possibly hold is by "anchor[ing] the notion of practice to theories that are prior and foundational to it," such as his alleged "theory of universality as normative exteriority."9 This realization brings Irrera to draw far-reaching conclusions for what concerns Hadot and Foucault's different method- ological approaches, that is, the historical-doctrinal and the genealogical method, respec- tively: It is clear that the taxonomic activity of the historian of philosophy, however sup- ported by honest, meticulous and anyhow necessary philological work, can be per- formed only starting from the choice of determined paradigms – in this [sc. Hadot’s] case, a theory of transcendence – a choice that sublimates into methodo- logical praxis, and finally hides behind the alleged neutrality and non-judgmental character of philological analysis, or behind the more or less objective exposition of undisputable historical-doctrinal contents. The special Foucaultian method of inquiry [sc. the genealogical method] does without just these issues, and distin- guishes itself from Hadot's, or any other historian of philosophy's, intentions of historical-doctrinal reconstruction.10 However correct Irrera might be in pointing out that Hadot himself often employs the no- tions of 'joy' and 'pleasure' somewhat interchangeably in his works, that Hadot's historical- doctrinal method – or, possibly even more radically, any historical-doctrinal method – of studying ancient philosophical texts should suffer from such severe theoretical biases strikes us as a radical and quite indefensible claim. As Hadot made clear on several occasions throughout his oeuvre, in fact, his method of inquiry – heavily influenced by the 'second' Wittgenstein of the Philosophical Investigations as it was11 – was originally devised precisely to 7 Orazio Irrera, “Pleasure and Transcendence of the Self: Notes on 'A Dialogue Too Soon Interrupted' Between Michel Foucault and Pierre Hadot,” Philosophy and Social Criticism 36:9 (2010); Cf. Federico Testa, "Towards a History of Philosophical Practices in Michel Foucault and Pierre Hadot," PLI: the Warwick Journal of Philosophy (2016), 169, n2 8 Following Irrera, on this point, see also Matthew Sharpe, "Towards a Phenomenology of Sagesse: Uncovering the Unique Philosophical Problematic of Pierre Hadot," Angelaki 23:2 (2018), 129. 9 Irrera, “Pleasure and Transcendence of the Self,” 1008. “Given Hadot’s own non-Heideggerian thinking of presence,” Sharpe recently wondered “how Hadot might have responded to this critique.” Matthew Sharpe, "Introduction: Situating Hadot Today," in The Selected Writings of Pierre Hadot: Philosophy as Practice, ed. Matthew Sharpe and Federico Testa (2020), 8. Interestingly, Irrera’s position was already sketched early on by Simonazzi, in the provisional conclusions of his study: “The activity of research should […] deepen […] the theme […] of the necessity, in Seneca’s stoicism itself, to ‘conquer’ […] a universal point of view, only starting from which, perhaps Hadot would argue, it is possible to distinguish between the concept of voluptas and gaudium.” Moreno Simonazzi, La formazione del soggetto nell'antichità: La lettura di Michel Foucault e di Pierre Hadot (2007), 194. Translation mine. 10 “Pleasure and Transcendence of the Self,” 1008-9. 11 On the influence that Wittgenstein’s thought exercised on Hadot, see his introductory remarks in Pierre Hadot, Wittgenstein et les limites du langage (2004). On the theme, also Sandra Laugier, "Pierre Hadot as a The Use and Misuse of Pleasure Foucault Studies, No. 33, 1-23. 4 repossess the philosophical works of antiquity from the hands of fundamentalist interpreters and to re-situate them in the "living praxis" from which they originally emanated.12 The whole purpose of Hadot's methodological approach, to turn Irrera's claim on its head, is de- claredly to anchor the notion of theory to a series of practices that are prior and foundational to it, those being the famous spiritual exercises which gave to his entire body of work perhaps its most recognizable leitmotif.13 As Hadot explains in The Present Alone is Our Happiness, that of Wittgenstein's 'language games' is an idea that had guided all my works. When one is in the presence of a text, or an utterance, it is not sufficient to take this text or this utterance in the absolute, as though it had not been uttered by someone in particular, under particular circum- stances, on a particular day, during a particular period and in a determinate con- text. This is a weakness of religious fundamentalists, and is in fact shared by many historians of philosophy or by philosophers who conduct themselves as funda- mentalists. They approach a text as though it was the word of the gospel, as though God had pronounced it, and cannot be restituted in space and time. On the con- trary, the historical and psychological perspective is very important in the history of philosophy, because it is always a question of re-placing the claims of philoso- phers into the social, historical, traditional, and psychological context in which they were written.14 As we shall contend contra Irrera, Hadot can reclaim a sharp distinction between the Stoic notions of ‘joy’ and ‘pleasure’ – or, equivalently, can negate to the Stoic notion of gaudium the status of ‘another form of pleasure’ – not so much because of an unescapable theoretical bias that would supposedly vitiate from the onset his historical-doctrinal method of analysis, as, quite contrarily, because of his failure to apply also in this case his historical- doctrinal methodology of analysis itself. In the present investigation, we thus follow closely Hadot's own "methodological imperative"15 and attempt to re-situate Seneca's use of the terms voluptas and gaudium in the rhetorical context of the two terminological registers that the Stoic philosopher introduces in his Epistula 59:16 the exoteric verbum publicum (literally, reader of Wittgenstein," Paragraph 34, no. 3 (2011). Wittgenstein’s influence on Hadot did not go undetected by Arnold I. Davidson, "Introduction: Pierre Hadot and the Spiritual Phenomenon of Ancient Philosophy," in Philosophy as a Way of Life: Spiritual Exercises from Socrates to Foucault, ed. Arnold I. Davidson (1995), 18-19. More recently, also José Miguel Fernández, “Spiritual Exercises and Language Games: The Influence of Wittgenstein’s Later Philosophy of Language on Pierre Hadot’s Approach to Ancient Philosophy as a Way of Life,” Littera Scripta. Revista Filosofía 3 (2022). 12 Pierre Hadot, The Selected Writings of Pierre Hadot. Philosophy as Practice, trans. Matthew Sharpe and Federico Testa (2020), 57; also 84. 13 Hadot tells us exactly so also in the opening comments of What is Ancient Philosophy? (2004), 3. “Philosoph- ical discourse,” he writes there, “originates in a choice of life and an existential option – not vice versa.” 14 Pierre Hadot, The Present Alone is Our Happiness: Conversations with Jeannie Carlier and Arnold I. Davidson (2009), 134-135. On this methodology, see also Hadot’s considerations in Philosophy as a Way of Life, 61. Also the ‘Postscript’ to ibid., 280. 15 Hadot, What is Ancient Philosophy?, 274. 16 For Seneca’s writings, the present investigation refers to the latest English translations of The Complete Works of Lucius Annaeus Seneca by The University of Chicago Press. For the Epistulae morales ad Lucilium (Epis- tulae hereafter), I refer to Margaret Graver and A.A Long, Seneca, Letters on Ethics: to Lucilius (2015). For the MATTEO STETTLER Foucault Studies, No. 33, 1-23. 5 'public word') and the esoteric significatio Stoica ('Stoic meaning'). By doing so, we will be able to reconcile, on the very same textual ground, Hadot’s and Foucault's respective ac- counts of Seneca's notion of gaudium – as seemingly referring to the significatio Stoica of 'joy' and the verbum publicum of 'pleasure,' respectively –, and thereby unveil this front of the Hadot-Foucault querelle as a 'pseudo-problem' engendered by Seneca's recourse to different terminological registers.17 As we shall try to demonstrate, depending on the specific rhetori- cal circumstances of each one of his utterances, Seneca refers to that joyful emotion ensuing from virtue either with the Stoic doctrinal meaning of 'joy' (gaudium) or with the vulgar meaning of 'pleasure' (voluptas), thus respectively erecting or collapsing at liberty the tradi- tional Stoic distinction between gaudium and voluptas. This being its program, the present in- vestigation is thus structured as follows: first, we introduce Foucault's analysis in the critical chapter II of The Care of the Self (Section I); second, I discuss in detail Hadot's criticism, as ap- peared in 'Reflections on the Idea of the 'Cultivation of the Self" (Section II); third, I will put to the test Foucault’s and Hadot's respective interpretations by consulting Seneca's writings (Section III). I. FOUCAULT'S TAKE: THE HEDONISTIC STRUCTURE OF THE GRECO- ROMAN SUBJECT Chapter II of the Care of the Self opens with Foucault’s chronicle of a significant phenome- non that emerged in the transition from the Classical to the Imperial era: the unprece- dented degree of intensity reached by the problematization of the aphrodisia. Far from re- flecting the coercive intervention of institutional authorities or the promulgation of more restrictive moral codes – such as those eventually in effect in the successive Christian epoch –, let alone the manifestation of an ascending individualistic preoccupation, Fou- cault prompts us to comprehend the tenor of this renovated emphasis on sexual austerity in the Imperial era in terms of the strengthening of the structure of reflexivity proper to the Greco-Roman self-constituting ethical subject – or, in his terms, of "an intensification of the relation to oneself by which one constituted oneself as the subject of one's acts."18 Although retaining its genus in Greek culture, such a phenomenon, as Foucault chronicles, reached its apex of intensity and valorization – in other terms, enjoyed its “golden age” – precisely in the Hellenistic-Roman ethos of the “cultivation of the self.”19 De vita beata (De vita hereafter) we refer to ‘On the Happy Life,’ as contained in the volume Elaine Fantham et al., Seneca, Hardship and Happiness (2014). For the Latin, our texts of reference are L. D. Reynolds, L. Annaei Senecae Ad Lucilius Epistulae Morales, II vols. (1965) and Pierre Grimal, L. Annaei Senecae De vita beata. Sénèque, Sur le bonheur (1969). For the Epistulae, references are given, as conventional, to the number of the letter and the paragraph. For the De Vita, similarly, references are given to the chapter and the paragraph. 17 I use Wittgenstein’s term ‘pseudo-problem’ only in sensu lato to signify, as Gill noted, a question to which we should not attempt to find an answer but that we should try to dissolve in the realm of language. Jerry H. Gill, “Wittgenstein and the Function of Philosophy,” Metaphilosophy 2:2 (1971), 137. 18 Michel Foucault, The Care of the Self: Volume 3 of the History of Sexuality (1990), 41. 19 Foucault, The Care of the Self: Volume 3 of the History of Sexuality, 45. On what Foucault calls “the period of the golden age of the culture of the self,” see also The Hermeneutics of the Subject: Lectures at the Collège de France, 1981-82, 30ff. The Use and Misuse of Pleasure Foucault Studies, No. 33, 1-23. 6 Critically, in the last section of the chapter, Foucault contends that this art of existence – an art that, in the distinctively Hellenistic-Roman phenomenon of the 'cultivation of the self', developed from, and came to rest upon, the Greek injunction heautou epimeleisthai ('care for oneself') – was grounded on the principle of epistrophe eis heauton ('conversion to self').20 In the wake of Hadot's pioneering work on conversion,21 Foucault qualifies that such conversio ad se, in late antiquity, asked of Greco-Roman selves a radical transfor- mation of the way in which they attended to specific activities and directed their attention so that they might continually take care of themselves.22 This intense and continuous form of ethical reflexivity, although being inscribable within the same horizon of the Pagan "ethics of control," Foucault specifies, finds in the Imperial era its articulation in modes and domains other than that, respectively, of the Greek self-agon and of an ontology of forces: that is, in his own words, other than "the agonistic form of a victory over forces difficult to subdue and of a dominion over them."23 Foucault thus identifies two modes assumed by such ethical reflexivity in late antiquity: what we might refer to as the politico-juridical and the hedonistic modes of ethical self-possession – only the latter of which constitutes relevant material for the present reflection. Drawing a parallel with the preceding "heautocratic structure of the subject" in effect in classical Greece,24 Foucault notes that in the Hellenistic period the experience of self that forms itself in this possession is not simply that of a force overcome, or a rule exercised over a power that is on the point of rebelling; it is the experience of a pleasure that one takes in oneself. The individual who has finally succeeded in gaining access to himself is, for himself, an object of pleasure.25 Having identified in this hedonism the constitutive principle of the Greco-Roman subject, Foucault does not recast the traditional Stoic antinomy between gaudium (or laetitia) and voluptas in its historical-doctrinal significance – that is, the contraposition between the do- mains of eupatheia and pathos –, but alongside three axes, only two of which hitherto iden- tified by scholars: that is, in terms of (1) the moral genetics of these two states of the soul (endogenous vs. exogenous), as Montanari already noted;26 in terms of (2) the temporal 20 Foucault, The Care of the Self: Volume 3 of the History of Sexuality, 64-65. 21 In The Hermeneutics, Foucault acknowledges explicitly his debt to Hadot’s 1953 article ‘Epistrophè et metanoia dans l'histoire de la philosophie,’ which he considers as “an absolutely fundamental and important analysis.” Foucault, The Hermeneutics of the Subject: Lectures at the Collège de France, 1981-82, 216. Hadot’s text has recently been published with an English translation by Andrew Irvine as “Epistrophe and Metanoia in the History of Philosophy,” Philosophy Today 65:1 (2021). Hadot has produced two other texts expressly de- voted to the notion of conversion, only one of which has been translated into English to date. Pierre Hadot, "Conversion," in The Selected Writings of Pierre Hadot (London: Bloomsbury, 2020). See also the shorter Pierre Hadot, "Conversio," in Discours et mode de vie philosophique, ed. Xavier Pavie (2014). 22 Foucault, The Care of the Self: Volume 3 of the History of Sexuality, 64-65. 23 Ibid., 65. 24 Ibid., 70. 25 Ibid., 66. See also Foucault, The Hermeneutics of the Subject: Lectures at the Collège de France, 1981-82, 214. There Foucault writes, in reference to one of the defying axis of the Greco-Roman model of the conversio ad se: “You experience a pleasure in yourself, an enjoyment or delight.” 26 Montanari, Hadot e Foucault nello specchio dei Greci, 25-27. MATTEO STETTLER Foucault Studies, No. 33, 1-23. 7 modes of their manifestation (stable vs. unstable), as Irrera pointed out;27 and, as I shall add, also in terms of (3) their qualities (serene vs. violent). As Foucault writes, in a passage that is worth reporting at length: this "pleasure that one takes in oneself, for which Seneca usually employs the word gaudium or laetitia, […] is defined by [1] the fact of not being caused by anything that is independent of ourselves and therefore escapes our control. […] It is characterized as well by [2] the fact that it knows neither degree nor change, but is given as a 'woven fabric,' and once given no external event can rend it. […] [It] is a state that [3] is neither accompanied nor followed by any form of disturbance in the body or mind.28 According to Foucault's reconstruction, gaudium or, equivalently, laetitia, is thus a form of pleasure that is (1) endogenously generated, (2) temporally stable, and (3) qualitatively nonviolent. This state of the animus, Foucault is keen to observe, for Seneca, can be con- trasted "point by point"29 – that is, on the (1) endogenous-exogenous, (2) stable-unstable and (3) violent-nonviolent axes – with another sort of pleasure, which thus presents itself as (1) exogenously generated, (2) temporally unstable, and (3) qualitatively violent. In Seneca's writings, the term voluptas, Foucault writes, in fact denotes a pleasure [1] whose origin is to be placed outside us and in objects whose presence we cannot be sure of: a pleasure, therefore, [2] which is pre- carious in itself, undermined by the fear of loss, and [3] to which we are drawn by the force of a desire that may or may not find satisfaction.30 "In place of this kind of [3] violent, [2] uncertain, and [1] conditional pleasure," that is, voluptas, Foucault concludes, supporting his contention by referring to Seneca's Epistula 23, "access to self is capable of providing a form of pleasure that comes, [3] in serenity and [2] without fail, of [1] the experience of oneself,"31 namely, gaudium. If Foucault seems to be aware of this threefold distinction traceable between gaudium and voluptas, we now have to ask, as Irrera himself did,32 why he insists on considering them just two 'different forms of pleasure,' as Hadot lamented. Can there be, ultimately, any justification for the Foucauldian historical-doctrinal indifference to the Stoic dichotomous domains of eu- patheia and pathos? As we shall now consider, for Hadot, surely there is not. 27 “Pleasure and Transcendence of the Self,” 997. 28 Foucault, The Care of the Self: Volume 3 of the History of Sexuality, 66. Additions mine. Note that the order of the phrases of this passage has been re-arranged to provide a more linear exposition of the threefold axis that, according to Foucault, characterizes the Stoic notion of gaudium. 29 Ibid. 30 Ibid. Additions mine. 31 Ibid. Additions mine. 32 “Pleasure and Transcendence of the Self,” 997. The Use and Misuse of Pleasure Foucault Studies, No. 33, 1-23. 8 II. HADOT'S REBUTTAL: THE PURITY OF INTENTION OF THE STOIC MORAL CONSCIENCE Hadot presented his critical 'Reflections on the Idea of 'The Cultivation of the Self" on the occasion of the Rencontre Internationale given in Paris between the 8th and the 11th of Janu- ary 1988 to commemorate the fourth anniversary of Foucault's death.33 Having taken note of Foucault's references to his early works,34 Hadot seized that opportunity to "offer a few remarks with a view to delineating the differences of interpretation […] which separate us, above and beyond our points of agreements," as he himself puts it.35 As anticipated in the introductory section, Hadot rejects Foucault's construal of Greco-Roman ethics (and, more critically, Stoic ethics) as "an ethics of the pleasure one takes in oneself" – a position which, to his regard, presents "a great deal of inexactitude."36 Challenging him on the same textual ground – Seneca's Epistula 23 –, Hadot finds Foucault “a little off-hand [un rien désinvolte]”37 at the moment in which he allegedly conflates the notions of voluptas and gaudium, thereby consigning, on the one side, the notion of gaudium to the subordinate status of "another form of pleasure," and, on the other, Seneca himself to the inappropriate rank of a sort of Epicurean.38 As Hadot points out in his last interviews, when asked to summarize the distance that separated him from Foucault: My first divergence concerns the notion of pleasure. For Foucault, the ethics of the Greco-Roman world is an ethics of pleasure that one takes in oneself: This could be true for the Epicureans, who Foucault ultimately speaks of rather lit- tle. But the Stoics would have rejected this idea of an ethics of pleasure. They were careful to distinguish pleasure and joy.39 Far from being a sterile philological cavil, for Hadot, the Stoics carefully delimited both conceptually and terminologically the sphere of hedone ('pleasure') from the domain of 33 Hadot’s article first appeared in English as Pierre Hadot, “Reflections on the Notion of 'The Cultivation of the Self',” in Michel Foucault, Philosopher (1992). Three years later, it was eventually republished in Philosophy as a Way of Life (1995) – with the relevant exclusion of the report of the discussion following Hadot’s presen- tation. 34 Foucault mentions Hadot both in The Use of Pleasure, and, more critically, in a fundamental note of The Care of the Self. In the former, he confesses to have “benefited greatly” from Hadot’s works. Michel Foucault, The Use of Pleasure: Volume 2 of the History of Sexuality (1990), 8; also 271. In the second, Foucault refers the reader back to Hadot’s early collection of essays Exercices spirituels et philosophie antique for “an interesting discussion of these themes” revolving around the cultivation of the self. Foucault, The Care of the Self: Volume 3 of the History of Sexuality, 243. 35 Philosophy as a Way of Life, 206. 36 Ibid., 207. That Hadot’s critique of Foucault is in turn “a matter of factual inexactitude” was more recently Giorgio Agamben’s claim in The Use of Bodies: Homo Sacer IV (2016), 99. Contra the latter’s intervention in the Hadot-Foucault querelle, see recently Matthew J Sharpe and Matteo J Stettler, "Pushing Against an Open Door: Agamben on Hadot and Foucault," Classical Receptions Journal 14:1 (2022). 37 Hadot, Pierre. “Foucault dans le texte,” Philosophie Magazine 36 (2018), 91. Translation mine. Excerpt from Pierre Hadot, La philosophie comme manière de vivre (2001), 214-215. 38 Philosophy as a Way of Life, 207. Similarly, see also Hadot, "The Figure of the Sage in Greek and Roman Antiquity," 199. 39 Hadot, The Present Alone is Our Happiness: Conversations with Jeannie Carlier and Arnold I. Davidson, 136. MATTEO STETTLER Foucault Studies, No. 33, 1-23. 9 eupatheia ('good feeling')40 precisely because they abstained from grounding the realm of moral life on the principle of pleasure. According to Hadot, the Stoics jealously endeav- oured to preserve “the purity of intention of the moral conscience," thus inaugurating that trajectory of moral reflections which eventually culminated with Kant and modern deon- tological ethics.41 From the point of view of Hadot's historical-doctrinal reconstruction, in the ultimate analysis, "it seems difficult to accept that the philosophical practice of the Stoics […] was nothing but […] a pleasure taken in oneself," as Foucault allegedly main- tained42 Two main conclusions may be drawn from this preliminary analysis. On the one side, while differentiating the two notions alongside the three axes described above, Foucault does expand the semantic scope of the notion of pleasure to embrace both voluptas and gaudium/laetitia, as Hadot lamented – whether rightly or not is a matter to be ascertained in due time. On the other, however, Foucault does not seem to be committed to the view for which this latter 'form of pleasure' qua gaudium is to be understood as the ultimate end of the Stoic moral life, that is, its summum bonum ('the supreme good'), as it was for the Epicureans. Foucault settled this issue early on in the imputed chapter 'The Cultivation of the Self,' where he made clear that it is "[the] relation to self that constitutes the end of the conversion and the final goal of all the practices of the self,"43 and not that 'form of pleas- ure' that is associated with the self's successful access to itself, namely gaudium. In this 40 Philosophy as a Way of Life, 207. The somewhat confusing contraposition of eupatheia and hedone is Hadot’s, even though, for a Stoic, it would make more sense contraposing the domains of pathos and eupatheia on the one side, and the spheres of hedone and chara on the other. Chara (‘joy’) is in fact only one of the three eupatheiai (‘good feelings’), alongside boulesis (‘wish’) and eulabeia (‘caution’). While hedone (‘pleasure’) is one of the four patheiai (‘passions’), alongside epithumia (‘desire’), phobos (‘fear’), and lupe (‘pain’). On this, see Julias Annas, Hellenistic Philosophy of Mind (1992), 104 and 114. 41 Philosophy as a Way of Life, 207. Translation modified. I’ve rendered Hadot’s French conscience with the English ‘conscience,’ rather than ‘consciousness.’ Pierre Hadot, Exercices spirituels et philosophie antique (2002), 325. 42 Philosophy as a Way of Life, 208. 43 Foucault, The Care of the Self: Volume 3 of the History of Sexuality, 65. That this is the case can be best appre- ciated by looking at one of Foucault’s most interesting case studies in the Hellenistic-Roman practices of the self, that of the hupomnemata. “Such is the aim of the hupomnemata,” Foucault writes in his essay ‘Self Writing,’ “to make one’s recollection of the fragmentary logos […] a means of stablishing a relationship of oneself with oneself, a relationship as adequate and accomplished as possible.” Michel Foucault, "Self Writing," in Ethics: Subjectivity and Truth, ed. Paul Rabinow (1997), 211. Similarly, see also Foucault, "On the Genealogy of Ethics: An Overview of Work in Progress," 272. It is worth noting that it is at this point that Hadot’s critique of Foucault on the Stoic notion of gaudium gets entangled with his wider critique of Foucault’s lack of consid- eration for the Stoic notion of cosmic consciousness. That these two Hadotian lines of argument are “inter- connected” was noted by Irrera, “Pleasure and Transcendence of the Self,” 996. Following the latter, see also Stephan, “Pierre Hadot e Michel Foucault: sobre a felicidade estoica e a experiência da alegria,” 234. Some- what similarly, also according to Wimberly: “From Hadot’s perspective, Foucault’s aims would seem to be heading in the wrong direction, toward voluptas and away from the Universal.” Cory Wimberly, "The Joy of Difference: Foucault and Hadot on the Aesthetic and the Universal in Philosophy," Philosophy Today 53:2 (2009), 199. Simonazzi proposed a similar reading of the debate when he wrote that “he [sc. Hadot] states that ‘Foucault presents the ethics of the Greco-Roman world as an ethics of pleasure that one takes in oneself,’ while, on the contrary, according to Hadot, the main purpose of this ethics is to go beyond the individual self.” Simonazzi, La formazione del soggetto nell'antichità: La lettura di Michel Foucault e di Pierre Hadot, 121. While agreeing with Irrera et al. on this point, we think nonetheless that Hadot’s criticism on Foucault’s misuse of the notion of pleasure might find its separate resolution. The Use and Misuse of Pleasure Foucault Studies, No. 33, 1-23. 10 sense, for Foucault, the practices of ethical self-constitution of the Stoics were not solely concerned with that pleasure that one takes in oneself, as Hadot wrongly presumed, but they also procured 'a form of pleasure' – as seen above, a very specific one –, issuing as a by-product of a successful ethical reflexivation, that is, of the establishment of a stable and accomplished relationship of the self with itself.44 As we shall see in the following, this reading is substantiable by solid textual references. III. SENECA'S TERMINOLOGICAL REGISTERS: VERBUM PUBLICUM AND SIGNIFICATIO STOICA Anyone even remotely acquainted with later antiquity, even a self-declared novice Hel- lenist or Latinist like Foucault himself,45 would certainly concur with Hadot in claiming that the Stoic summum bonum – that in which, according to the philosophers of the Porch, felicitas ('happiness') resides – "does not consist in pleasure but in virtue itself, which is its own reward."46 “True happiness [vera felicitas]," as Seneca asserts unmistakably in the De Vita, "is located in virtue."47 Nonetheless, we must grant Foucault that Seneca was one of those Stoic philosophers who regularly confronted Epicurus in his writings and who availed himself abundantly – and, as we shall see, often not unproblematically – of the notion of voluptas, even on those occasions in which, from the point of view of the Stoic doctrine, one would have expected the recourse to the more traditional term gaudium.48 A primary point of reference concerning these notions – a reference left unnoticed by both Foucault and Hadot – is provided by Seneca's Epistula 59.49 There, after having employed the term voluptas to denote the 'great pleasure' (magna voluptas) that he derived from Lu- cilius' correspondence, as we shall see, Seneca disambiguates the term by explicitly 44 That, for the Stoics, gaudium accompanies virtuous actions without being itself the objective of said actions is what Hadot himself tells us elsewhere. Pierre Hadot, The Inner Citadel: The Meditations of Marcus Aurelius (1998), 240. That chara is a by-product of virtue, a so-called epigennema, can be seen in SVF III 76. 45 “I am neither a Hellenist nor a Latinist” was Foucault’s disclaimer in The Care of the Self: Volume 3 of the History of Sexuality, 7. 46 Pierre Hadot, “Reflections on the Idea of the 'Cultivation of the Self',” in Philosophy as a Way of Life: Spiritual Exercises from Socrates to Foucault (1995), 207. 47 Seneca, De vita beata, 16.1. 48 As DeLacy noted, in discussing the role of poetry in Stoic literature: “[t]he term hedone is also used in a favourable sense, even in contexts where strict usage would have required chara.” Phillip DeLacy, "Stoic Views of Poetry," The American Journal of Philology 69:3 (1948), 250. Similarly, see also Monroe C. Beardsley, Aesthetics from Classical Greece to the Present (2015), 71. Following the latter, see Jennifer A. McMahon, "Beauty as Harmony of the Soul: the Aesthetic of the Stoics, in Proceedings of the 8th International Conference of Greek Studies 2009, ed. Marietta Rosetto, Michael Tsianikas, George Couvalis and Maria Palaktsoglou (2012), 57. On Seneca’s notion of gaudium and its relation to the Stoic tradition, see Margaret Graver, "Anatomies of Joy: Seneca and the Gaudium Tradition," in Hope, Joy, and Affection in the Classical World, ed. Ruth R. Caston and Robert A. Kaster (2016). 49 The relevance of this passage is highlighted by Evenepoel, "The Stoic Seneca on virtus, gaudium and voluptas," 46-47. By the same author, see also "Seneca on virtus, gaudium and voluptas: Some Additional Observations," Antiquité Classique 85 (2016). MATTEO STETTLER Foucault Studies, No. 33, 1-23. 11 distinguishing the two terminological registers by which he usually speaks of it: what he calls 'the common parlance' (verbum publicum) and the 'Stoic meaning' (significatio Stoica).50 A. VOLUPTAS: PLEASURE QUA FALSE JOY Voluptas, taken in its common connotation, Seneca qualifies to Lucilius, is "the word we gen- erally use to refer to a glad feeling of the mind [animi hilarem adfectionem]."51 Conversely, in the Stoic doctrine – or, as Seneca himself writes, "if we make words adhere to our statutes [nostrum album]"–, the term voluptas comes to acquire its distinctive negative acceptation, de- noting something that, ultimately, "is discreditable [rem infamem esse]"52 – a "fault [vitium]."53 Even a pleasure as innocent as that derived from a friend's correspondence – a surge con- ventionally deemed honourable by ordinary individuals – is enough of a reason, in the con- text of Epistula 59, for awakening Seneca's suspicion and, ultimately, for issuing a warning against a potential falsum bonum ('false good'): I was not wrong to say that I derived great pleasure [magnam...voluptatem] from your letter. For even though the untrained person may be rejoicing for an honora- ble reason, still I refer to his emotion [adfectum] as pleasure [voluptatem], because it is unruly and swift to revert to the opposite state, and because it is set in motion by belief in a false good and is uncontrolled and excessive.54 Significantly, at the end of Epistula 59, Seneca borrows a line from Virgil's Aeneid to define voluptates as falsa gaudia ('deceiving or false joys'). Addressing his contempt to voluptas-seek- ing individuals, Seneca writes: When people have worn themselves out with wine and lust; when their vices outlast the night; when the pleasures [voluptates] they have consumed beyond the narrow limits of the body begin to suppurate; then in their misery they speak aloud that familiar line of Virgil: 50 Seneca, Epistulae morales ad Lucilium, 59.1. Seneca’s distinction of these two terminological registers should certainly be read on the background of his use of philosophical language. Regarding the latter, as Armisen- Marchetti concluded, “Seneca’s effort oscillates, in a constant dialectic, between a necessary technicality and a desired simplicity. A necessary technicality: Seneca has an excellent knowledge of stoicism and he is careful to render its concepts with scrupulous precision. But also a deliberate simplicity: the philosopher does not want to deviate from common language […]. The simplicity of the discourse is a response to the requirements of ancient philosophical teaching and the direction of conscience.” Mireille Armisen-Marchetti, “La langue philosophique de Sénèque: entre technicité et simplicité,” Antike und Abendland 42:1 (1996), 84. Translation mine. While the term significatio Stoica does not seem to compare elsewhere in Seneca’s writings (or in any other Stoic Latin text), as far as I could ascertain, Seneca uses the term verbum publicum in De beneficiis, VI, 34.3, in reference to the standard and commonplace greeting ‘Good day.’ More interestingly, Seneca distin- guishes the verbum proprium and the verbum quasi publicum for the notion of ‘friend’ in Epistulae, 3, 1. 51 Seneca, Epistulae morales ad Lucilium, 59.1. 52 Ibid., 59.2. 53 Ibid., 59.1. That in this passage the term hedone is given “some definite technical sense” was also noted by Richard P. Haynes, "The Theory of Pleasure of the Old Stoa," The American Journal of Philology 83:4 (1962), 417. However, there seems to be nothing to indicate that Seneca’s distinction between the verbum publicum and the significatio Stoica belonged to the Stoa as a whole, however certainly possible that might be. 54 Epistulae morales, 59.4. The Use and Misuse of Pleasure Foucault Studies, No. 33, 1-23. 12 For you know how we spent that night, our last, amid deceiving joys.55 Indulging themselves, they spend every night amid deceiving joys [falsa gaudia], as if it were indeed their last.56 It would thus seem that, when understood in its traditional Stoic acceptation, any form of voluptas – from the simplest (that derived from a friend's letter) to the wildest (spending nights of unconsidered self-indulgence) –, for Seneca, denotes an amenability to seek after a falsum bonum, and it is thus best characterized as a falsum gaudium. In such capacity, as Hadot correctly maintained, voluptas seems to be irremediability set against gaudium.57 B. GAUDIUM/LAETITIA: JOY QUA TRUE PLEASURE According to Seneca, the term gaudium, intended in its Stoic acceptation, is brought forth solely by acting in conformity to virtus, that is, to the verum bonum ('true good'):58 "joy [gaudium] pertains only to the wise person, for it is the elevation of a mind toward goods that are real and its own."59 Even though only the sage, the Stoic ideal of perfection,60 would be able to experience this status animi in his own or in his Stoic companion's virtuous con- duct,61 as Seneca points out in Epistula 59, referring now to the common and vulgar accepta- tion of the term gaudium, in our ordinary speech we often say that we are overenjoyed [magnum gaudium] that one person was elected consul, or another was married or that his wife has given birth, events which, far from being causes for joy [gaudia], are frequently the beginnings of future sorrow. For it is an attribute of joy that it never ceases or turns into its opposite.62 55 Aeneid, 6.513-514. 56 Epistulae morales, 59.17-18. 57 For the opposition voluptas-gaudium, see SVF III 431-4, and 438. Cf. also Seneca, De vita beata, 3, 4. 58 Cf. pleasure as falsum bonum (‘false good’) in Seneca Epistulae morales, 59.4. For gaudium as deriving from virtuous conduct, see also Cicero, De finibus, V, 69. 59 Epistulae morales ad Lucilium, 59.2. 60 It was a rather conventional feature of Hellenistic-Roman ethical reflections to be framed around the words and deeds of the sage, who functioned as the very “transcendental ideal” for people to conform with. Philosophy as a Way of Life, 57. See especially Hadot, “The Figure of the Sage in Greek and Roman Antiquity,” But also Hadot, What is Ancient Philosophy?, 220. 61 Seneca, De vita beata, 4.4. Also according to Graver: “Unlike the ordinary flawed person who delights wrongly in empty things, the wise person who is the Stoic ideal […] would experience joy in his own char- acter and good deeds or those of virtuous friends. […] To experience it [sc. joy], Lucilius must perfect his character since only a fully virtuous and wise person possesses the genuine goods that are the proper object of joy.” Graver and Long, Seneca, Letters on Ethics: to Lucilius, 517. Seneca repeats several times in the Epistulae that joy is a state of the soul reserved to the sage. See Epistula 27, 3-4; 72, 4-5; and 124, 23-24. 62 Epistulae morales, 59.2. Also Graver reminds us of what “distinguishes joy as a philosophical idea from joy in the common or pretheoretical sense of that word. While both Greek and Latin speakers could in general speak of joy or rejoicing (χαρά/χαίρειν, gaudium/gaudere) as what anyone might experience in response to perceived good fortune, Stoic philosophers restricted those terms to their normative inquiry into the inner experience of the optimal agent,” that is the sage. Graver, "Anatomies of Joy: Seneca and the Gaudium MATTEO STETTLER Foucault Studies, No. 33, 1-23. 13 It is exactly this gaudium, as technically understood by the Stoics (that is to say, the verum gaudium originating in virtus), rather than the one commonly conceived by ordinary people (that is to say, the falsum gaudium deriving from the vain goods of fortune),63 that Seneca is exhorting Lucilius to learn how to experience in the much-discussed Epistula 23, the inter- pretation of which Hadot and Foucault so profoundly disagreed over. “Don't rejoice in empty things [Ne gaudeas vanis]," Seneca reminds his pupil there; this is the fundamentum ('foundation') – or, better, as Seneca immediately qualifies, the culmen ('pinnacle') – of any good mind (mens bona).64 At a first reading, it would thus seem that Hadot is quite justified in calling out Foucault on his interpretation of this Epsitula, for, as the former argued, there "Seneca explicitly opposes voluptas and gaudium – pleasure and joy – and one cannot, there- fore, speak of 'another form of pleasure,' as does Foucault […] when talking about joy."65 And yet, although gaudium, or laetitia,66 does remain Seneca's doctrinal term for the joy ensu- ing from virtue, in the very context of Epistula 23, this status animi is successively counted among the ranks of other voluptates in a manner that seems to depose in favour of the Fou- cauldian interpretation. In fact, in discouraging Lucilius from chasing any of the goods of fortune, Seneca tells his pupil that he is not depriving him of voluptates ('pleasures'), for he still wishes that his heart may be filled with laetitia – a statement which would seem to im- plicate that, for the purposes of the present utterance, this joyful state associated with virtue might, after all, be regarded as ‘another form of pleasure,’ as Foucault claimed: Do this above all, dear Lucilius: learn how to experience joy [disce gaudere]. Do you now suppose that because I am removing from you the things of fortune and think you should steer clear of hopes, those sweetest of beguilements, I am taking away many pleasures [multas voluptates]? Not at all: what I want is that gladness [laetitia] should never be absent from you. I want it to be born in your own home – and that is what will happen if it comes to be inside of you. Other delights [ceterae hilaritates] do not fill the heart; they are trivial feelings that merely smooth the brow. Surely you don't think that every person who smiles is rejoicing [gaudere]! The mind must Tradition," 133. See also the scholar’s comments on Seneca’s Epistula 23 in Graver and Long, Seneca, Letters on Ethics: to Lucilius, 517. 63 Note that the emotion which Seneca referred to with the significatio Stoica of the term voluptas (Epistula 59, 18-18) and the one referred to with the verbum publicum of the term gaudium (Epistula 59, 2) can be both char- acterized as a falsum gaudium because both are unstable emotions susceptible of eventually turning into their opposite, while for Seneca the verum gaudium is an uninterrupted and unchanging emotion. This seems to suggest that the emotion that ordinary people vulgarly call gaudium corresponds to what the Stoics doctri- nally designate as voluptas. As we shall see, exactly the opposite seems to hold for the significatio Stoica of the term gaudium, to which Seneca sometimes refers with the non-doctrinal meaning of the term voluptas. See especially footnote n72 infra. 64 Epistulae, 23, 1. 65 Philosophy as a Way of Life, 207. 66 As both Foucault and Hadot recognized, Seneca seems to refer indistinctively to the joy provoked by con- ducting oneself in accordance with virtus as either gaudium or laetitia. See Seneca, De vita beata 4.4; 15.2; and 22.3. Note that in Tusculanae IV, 66, Cicero distinguishes gaudium from laetitia, the latter characterizing an exaggerated form of joy. The Use and Misuse of Pleasure Foucault Studies, No. 33, 1-23. 14 be energetic and confident; it must be upright, superior to every trial. Believe me, real joy [verum gaudium] is a serious matter .67 This is not the only occasion in the entire Senecanian corpus in which, somewhat confus- ingly, the Stoic philosopher opts to refer to an eupatheia (such as the gaudium or laetitia deriv- ing from virtue) using the term that traditionally connotes its opposite state of the soul, that is a pathos (such as voluptas), thus suspending, at least terminologically, the doctrinal an- tinomy between them. As Bocchi most interestingly noted, 68 that seems to occur also in the Naturales quaestiones, 6, 2, 2, where Seneca elaborates as follows on an exhortation delivered to the Trojans by Aeneas in the Virgilian epic: "If you want to be afraid of nothing [si vultis nihil timere] regard everything as something to be afraid of [cogitate omnia esse metuenda]."69 Interestingly, on this occasion, Seneca recurs to using, evidently in its untechnical accepta- tion, the term metus ('fear'), the pathos of a future evil, in order to refer to its rationally justi- fied correspondent: namely, cautio ('caution'), the eupatheia of an apparent future evil. As Bocchi pointed out when commenting on this passage of the Quaestiones naturales, with an observation that we wish to extend here also to the Epistulae – two texts which, relevantly enough, were addressed to Lucilius –, Seneca most likely resorts to using metus and voluptas to designate their corresponding eupatheiai because he lacks the appropriate terms for what Graver calls the 'progressor emotions' of the proficiens,70 as both gaudium and cautio are tradi- tionally considered unachievable by the latter and to belong only to the Stoic sage. In the Quaestiones naturales, as Bocchi noted, "Seneca, unable to use cautio for ordinary cases, finds himself without a term that expresses the attitude of serene expectation of future events typ- ical of those who are not completely immune to the passions: therefore, the philosopher's choice falls on a term [sc. metus] that is at this point used with implied correction."71 A simi- lar consideration, we would like to suggest, holds for the term gaudium in the Epistulae: given that Seneca could not possibly use it for ordinary cases such as Lucilius', he finds him- self lacking the term to express precisely that rationally justified state of enjoyment of a pre- sent good (namely, virtuous conduct) experienced sporadically by an individual who is still working his or her way through the path of wisdom: thus, he resorts to using its correspond- ing pathos, namely voluptas, in a non-doctrinal sense, that is, in a significatio non Stoica or in its verbum publicum.72 67 Epistulae, 23, 3-4. 68 Ibid. 69 Seneca, Quaestiones naturales, V, 2, 2. Translation by Harry M Hine, Seneca, Natural Questions (2010). 70 Margaret Graver, Stoicism and Emotion (2007), 191-121. Brennan similarly referred to these states of the proficiens’ soul as ‘veridical emotions.’ Tad Brennan, "The Old Stoic Theory of Emotions," in The Emotions in Hellenistic Philosophy, ed. Juha Sihvola and Troels Engberg-Pedersen (1998). Graver explains the origin of these emotions elsewhere. See "Pre-emotions and Reader Emotions in Seneca: De ira and Epistulae morales," 293. 71 Bocchi, "A proposito di Seneca critico: l'ambivalenza al servizio dell'allegoria," 228, n17. Translation mine. That gaudium “pertains only to the wise person” we have seen above at Epistulae, 59, 2. That also cautio be- longs exclusively to the sage can be gathered, according to Bocchi, by reading Epistulae 85, 26, where such state of the soul is characterized as vitare mala. Ibid. 72 Referring to the joy that he derived from reading Lucilius’ correspondence with the non-doctrinal meaning of the term voluptas is, I think, exactly what we find Seneca doing at first in the opening of Epistula 59, 1, where that state of the soul is defined as an adfectio hilaris animi (‘glad feeling of the mind’). Importantly, hilaritas continua et laetitia (‘an unceasing cheerfulness and joy’) is exactly the way in which Seneca refers in MATTEO STETTLER Foucault Studies, No. 33, 1-23. 15 Several other examples of the same lexical procedure can be detected in other Sene- canian writings, especially in the De vita beata.73 At the beginning of this work, we find Sen- eca expanding the Stoic standard definition of the happy life – that is, “the life in agreement with its own nature [vita conveniens naturae suae]”74 – into six different definitions, for, as he explains, recurring to the simile of the army, on which we shall have to return, Our good [bonum nostrum] can also be defined in a different way – that is, the same proposition can be grasped with different words. Just as one and the same army is spread out more widely one moment and compacted more tightly the next, […] but no matter how it has been ordered it has the same strength and the same will to stand up for the same cause – so the definition of the highest good [summi boni] can sometimes be spread out and extended, and at other times be compressed and collected into itself.75 As Asmis has argued, one of Seneca's aims in laying down these six definitions – on the spe- cific content of which we shall not linger here – was to provide a correction to that “en- trenched perception” whereby the Stoic virtus was “a stern and cheerless ideal – hardly such as to make a person happy.”76 To do so, as the scholar claims, Seneca decides to place in al- most all his definitions of the Stoic vita beata much emphasis on the joy ensuing from virtu- ous conduct, as against the triviality of bodily pleasures. In the first definition, thus Seneca tells us that "when pleasures and pains have been rejected, a huge joy [ingens gaudium] comes in to replace those things that are trivial and fragile and actually prompt self-disgust – a joy unshaken and unvarying."77 In the second, he assures us that "the mind looking down on the things of fortune" does so "joyous in virtue [virtute laetus]."78 Similarly, in the fifth def- inition, Seneca doubles down on the difference between joy and pleasure: virtue is always accompanied by "an unceasing cheerfulness [hilaritas continua] and a joy [laetitia] that is deep and comes from deep within"79 – a state of the soul with which "the tiny, trivial and imper- manent movements of that meager thing, the body" cannot certainly rival.80 Interestingly, however, the contraposition between the stable joys attending to virtue and the fleeting pleasures deriving from the goods of fortune does not prevent Seneca from mixing things up terminologically in the fourth definition, where he refers to the former state of the soul (which is doctrinally referred to as gaudium) by using the doctrinal term traditionally a doctrinal manner to the joy ensuing from virtue in De vita beata, 4, 4. This seems to be the case, even though later on in the very same Epistula, Seneca evidently shifts terminological register, referring to the doctrinal meaning of the term voluptas. Cf. Seneca, Epistulae morales ad Lucilium, 59.4. On this complicated passage of Epistula 59, where Seneca evidently struggles to find the right vocabulary to correspond with Lucilius, see Graver, “Pre-emotions and Reader Emotions in Seneca: De ira and Epistulae morales,” 294-295. 73 That there exists “a non-technical and less connoted acceptation of the term [voluptas], as a generic synonym of gaudium” in Seneca’s De clementia, I, 1, 1, was Malaspina’s claim. Ermanno Malaspina, L. Annaei Senecae De clementia libri duo: Prolegomeni, testo critico e commento (2005), 233. Translation mine. 74 Seneca, De vita beata, 4, 3. 75 Ibid., 4, 1. 76Elizabeth Asmis, “Seneca's On the Happy Life and Stoic Individualism,” Apeiron 23:4 (1990),2 232 77Ibid., 3, 4. 78 Ibid., 4. 2. 79 Ibid., 4. 4. 80 Ibid. The Use and Misuse of Pleasure Foucault Studies, No. 33, 1-23. 16 reserved for the latter (voluptas, although with the qualifier vera), thus suspending termino- logically their dichotomous relationship: "One may also define it [sc. the Stoic summum bo- num] in such a way as to say that that human being is happy [beatum] […] to whom true pleasure will be scorning pleasures [cui vera voluptas erit voluptatum contemptio]."81 At this point in the argumentation of the De vita beata, there intervenes a fictitious inter- locutor with patent Epicurean sympathies who advances his reserves on the Stoic definitions of the happy and virtuous life that Seneca has just laid out. While recasting the old-age con- flict with the Epicureans concerning the incompatibility of virtue and pleasure, Seneca ends up conceding to his interlocutor that voluptates may even be part of the Stoic conception of the happy life, provided that they have "the same status for us as auxiliaries and light-armed soldiers have in an army camp, where they must serve rather than give orders."82 Interest- ingly, for our purposes, pressed by his fictitious interlocutor to address another Epicurean position, namely, "do not cultivate virtue for any other reason than that you hope for some pleasure from it," Seneca resorts once again to defying the joy attached to virtue with that term that in the Stoic doctrine traditionally designates its corresponding pathos, namely, vo- luptas, which is thus here evidently employed in its significatio non Stoica: First, just because virtue is going to provide some pleasure [voluptatem] does not mean that this is the reason why it is sought. It does not provide pleasure, you see, but provides it also. Nor does it toil for pleasure: rather, its toil will attain this as well, even though it is seeking something else.83 To this, Seneca suggestively adds the following rhetorical image of cultivation ('of the self,' one might be tempted to add), which seems to corroborate Foucault's take on the so-called hedonistic structure of the Greco-Roman subject, as above analyzed: Just as in a field that has been plowed for corn some flowers grow up in between, yet all that work was not undertaken for this little plant, however much it pleases the eyes (the sower had another outcome in mind, and this supervened) – so too, pleasure [voluptas] is not the reward or the motive of virtue but an accessory [ac- cessio]; and it is not approved of because it gives pleasure, but, if approved of, it gives pleasure also.84 81 Ibid., 4. 2. As Asmis already noted, “In this gnomic statement (4, 2), Seneca exceptionally uses the term voluptas instead of gaudium to refer to the joy of a virtuous mind, in order to score a rhetorical point.” Asmis, “Seneca's On the Happy Life and Stoic Individualism,” 232, n46. To this reading, Dyson has objected in “Pleasure and the Sapiens: Seneca De vita Beata 11.1,” Classical Philology 105:3 (2010), 315, n11. For a similar use of voluptas, see Epistulae morales ad Lucilius, 18, 10. See also solida voluptas in Ad Helviam matrem de conso- latione, 5, 5. Cf. also De beneficiis, 7, 2, 3-4, where the Stoic and Epicurean voluptates are compared: “the pleas- ure that is worthy of a human being and worthy of a real man is not to fill up the body […]; it is freedom from disturbances.” Translation by Miriam T. Griffin, Seneca, On Benefits (2011). For a similar usage, see also De beneficiis 4, 13, 1-2. 82 De vita beata, 8, 2. Cf. footnote n85 infra. 83 Ibid., 9.1. Hadot mentions this passage in The Inner Citadel: The Meditations of Marcus Aurelius, 240. As Irrera rightly noted, here “Hadot talks indifferently about pleasure, rather than only about joy.” Irrera, “Pleasure and Transcendence of the Self,” 1004. 84 De vita beata, 9.1. MATTEO STETTLER Foucault Studies, No. 33, 1-23. 17 As his present purpose is that of addressing exclusively the consequentialist conception of virtue held by the Epicureans and thus the relationship that should ideally intervene be- tween virtue and its corresponding state of the soul (whether it be pleasure for the Epicure- ans or joy for the Stoics), rather than the very definition of the summum bonum (pleasure for the Epicureans, virtue for the Stoics), Seneca finds it fitting here to temporarily archive the Stoic doctrinal antinomy between gaudium and voluptas in order to put into better focus his point and make his case in favor of the Stoic deontological view of virtue: if the Epicureans sought virtue for the status animi that it produces, namely, voluptas, the Stoics, he tells us, pursue virtue for itself, quite independently from its epigennema ('by-product') or, as we are told here, its accessory (accessio), which Seneca decides on this occasion to designate with the non-doctrinal term voluptas (rather than gaudium).85 CONCLUSION It is our contention that one way in which we might make sense of Seneca's terminological liberality in referring to the joy attached to virtue – the very problematic passage from his usage of voluptas in its verbum publicum, to which Foucault seems to refer, to that of gaudium in its significatio Stoica, as seemingly brandished by Hadot – lies in a passage of the De vita that significantly precedes the above quoted definition of the Stoic happy life, where this eupatheia is referred to as vera voluptas.86 There, as we have seen, Seneca claims that the Stoic summum bonum – which is usually defined as "the life in agreement with its own nature [vita conveniens naturae suae]" – “can also be defined in a different way – that is, the same proposition can be grasped with different words."87 We are inclined to argue that something similar might be said for the definition of that state of the soul that, ac- cording to the Stoic doctrine, always accompanies the possession of virtue, namely joy. 88 85 Evenepoel is of the same impression when he lists De vita beata, 9, 1-2, as one of those occasion in which Seneca refers to the joy brought about by virtuous conduct as voluptas. Evenepoel, "The Stoic Seneca on virtus, gaudium and voluptas," 47. Cf. Asmis, "Seneca's On the Happy Life and Stoic Individualism," 239: “In his flower image, Seneca is not describing joy, but the short-lived, intermittent pleasures that follow upon the attainment of natural ends. As in his comparison of pleasures to auxiliaries [De vita beata, 8, 2], he views pleasures as spontaneous, unsought ‘accessions’, or epigennemata, that come when we ‘preserve’ natural en- dowments.” Yet, as the scholar knows well, also chara is for the Stoics an epigennema. Asmis must have evi- dently been confused by Seneca’s use of the term voluptas in a non-doctrinal manner to refer to the joy deriv- ing from virtue, even though she is well aware that Seneca “exceptionally” does so for rhetorical purposes. Ibid., 232, n46. In conclusion: what Seneca “subverts” here is thus not his “doctrine,” as Asmis thinks, but only his doctrinal terminological register (that is, his significatio Stoica). Ibid., 239. On the relationship be- tween the epigennemata of pleasure and joy, see Anthony A Long, "Aristotle's Legacy to Stoic Ethics," Bulletin of the Institute of Classical Studies 15 (1968), 80 86 It must be noted that it is precisely this sort of “contradictions, and lack of rigor and coherence” of the philosophical works of Greco-Roman antiquity that originally prompted Hadot to interpret ancient philoso- phy as a set of spiritual exercises and, ultimately, as a ‘way of living.’ Hadot, Philosophy as a Way of Life: Spiritual Exercises from Socrates to Foucault, 61. For this, I sense, Hadot’s rigidity in the interpretation of Sen- eca’s technical vocabulary, and, thereby, his associated critique of Foucault’s flexibility, is even more lamen- table. 87 Ibid. 4, 1. 88 The validity of this assumption rests on the fact that, in De vita, Seneca defines almost each one of the six definitions of the Stoic summum bonum in terms of the joy that accompanies it. As much as the Stoic good The Use and Misuse of Pleasure Foucault Studies, No. 33, 1-23. 18 In fact, such a definition also seems to be a fluid and dynamic one and to be graspable with different verba: very much like Seneca's metaphorical army, the definition of the joy deriving from virtue may itself assume diverse configurations – at times expanding its semantic coverage to be assimilated to the notion of voluptas, as reflected in the Foucauld- ian interpretation, at others, compressing it, so as to re-establish the doctrinal antinomy between gaudium and voluptas that is so central to Hadot's reading of Stoic ethics – every time depending on the circumstances of each specific utterance and the interlocutors in- volved therein. As we have seen, in the Epistulae,89 – a text which is significantly addressed to the pro- ficiens Lucilius –, Seneca cannot help but designate in a non-doctrinal manner the so-called 'progressor emotion' of joy experienced by his pupil with its corresponding pathos, namely, voluptas, as the state of gaudium remains, from a doctrinal point of view, the pre- rogative of the Stoic sage. Whenever a point of contention with the Epicurean school is instead being debated, such as in De vita, we found Seneca similarly resorting to defying the joy attending to virtue with the vulgar acceptation of the term voluptas. In those cases in which what is at stake is the difference between the Stoic and Epicurean summum bo- num, Seneca usually refers to the restraining of pleasures as being itself the source of a higher and more noble form of voluptas: namely, vera voluptas.90 The same holds for those passages in which he is addressing the difference between the consequentialist and deon- tological conceptions of virtue held by the Epicureans and the Stoics, respectively. There Seneca finds it similarly useful to temporally suspend the doctrinal antinomy gaudium- voluptas and to refer in a non-technical way to the accessio of virtue as a form of voluptas in order to get his point across better to his hostile interlocutor.91 Conversely, when his discourse is centered around the figure of the Stoic sage, and it is not addressed to interlocutors extraneous to the School of the Porch, Seneca does not hesitate to employ the term gaudium in its significatio Stoica to refer to the unceasing joy that always accompanies virtue, thus fully adhering to the doctrinal antinomy gaudium- voluptas.92 If the pieces of evidence collected so far are sound, and our reasoning on the latter is correct at least as much as we hope they both are, then the double semantic regis- ter with which Seneca quite liberally employs the notion of gaudium and voluptas through- out his writings has allowed us to reconcile on the same textual ground Hadot’s and Fou- cault's respective accounts of the joyful state ensuing from virtue, the former being seem- ingly guided by the doctrinal acceptation of the term gaudium, the latter by the vulgar acceptation of the term voluptas. It is worth noting, in conclusion, that such results have (i.e., virtue) can be defined pointing to a virtuous individual “to whom true pleasure [that is, joy] will be scorning pleasures,” we are legitimated in assuming that Seneca’s following considerations concerning the fluid and dynamic definition of the Stoic ‘good’ shall apply as well to the state accompanying it, that is, joy. De vita beata, 4, 2. 89 Seneca, Epistulae morales ad Lucilium, 23, 3-4. 90 De vita beata, 4, 2. See solida voluptas in Ad Helviam, 5, 5. The contrast between Stoic and Epicurean pleasures in De beneficiis 4, 13, 1-2; 7, 2, 3-4. 91 De vita beata, 9, 1. 92 Epistulae, 59, 2. MATTEO STETTLER Foucault Studies, No. 33, 1-23. 19 been reached by attending closely to Hadot's own historical-doctrinal method of reading ancient texts (and not casting doubts on its presuppositions, as Irrera did) – a method which, however, the French scholar himself, like those fundamentalist philosophers and historians of philosophy that he so harshly reproached, has failed to stand by on this oc- casion. References Agamben, Giorgio, The Use of Bodies: Homo Sacer IV. Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2016. Annas, Julia. Hellenistic Philosophy of Mind. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1992. Armisen-Marchetti, Mireille, "La langue philosophique de Sénèque: entre technicité et simpli- cité," Antike und Abendland 42:1 (1996), 76-84. https://doi.org/10.1515/9783110241549.76 Asmis, Elizabeth, "Seneca's On the Happy Life and Stoic Individualism," Apeiron 23:4 (1990), 219-256. https://doi.org/10.1515/APEIRON.1990.23.4.219 Beardsley, Monroe C., Aesthetics from Classical Greece to the Present. Tuscaloosa: University of Alabama Press, 2015. Bocchi, Giuseppe, "A proposito di Seneca critico: l'ambivalenza al servizio dell'allegoria," in Analecta Brixiana, ed. Alfredo Valvo and Gian Enrico Manzoni, 221-231. Milano: Vita e Pen- siero, 2004. Brennan, Tad, "The Old Stoic Theory of Emotions," in The Emotions in Hellenistic Philosophy, ed. Juha Sihvola and Troels Engberg-Pedersen, 21-70. Dordrecht: Springer Netherlands, 1998. Cremonesi, Laura, "Pierre Hadot and Michel Foucault on Spiritual Exercises: Transforming the Self, Transforming the Present," in Foucault and the History of Our Present, ed. Sophie Fuggle, Yari Lanci and Martina Tazzioli, 195-209. London: Palgrave Macmillan UK, 2015. Davidson, Arnold I., "Introduction: Pierre Hadot and the Spiritual Phenomenon of Ancient Philosophy," In Philosophy as a Way of Life: Spiritual Exercises from Socrates to Foucault, ed. Arnold I. Davidson, 1-45. Oxford: Blackwell Publishing, 1995. Davidson, Arnold I., "Ethics as Ascetics: Foucault, the History of Ethics, and Ancient Thought," In The Cambridge Companion to Foucault, ed. Gary Gutting, 123-148. New York: Cambridge University Press, 2005. DeLacy, Phillip, "Stoic Views of Poetry," The American Journal of Philology 69:3 (1948), 241-271. https://doi.org/10.2307/291357 Dyson, Henry, "Pleasure and the Sapiens: Seneca De vita Beata 11.1," Classical Philology 105:3 (2010), 313-318. https://doi.org/10.1086/658630 Elden, Stuart, Foucault's Last Decade. Cambridge: Polity, 2016. Evenepoel, Willy, "The Stoic Seneca on virtus, gaudium and voluptas," L'Antiquité Classique 83:1 (2014), 45-78. https://doi.org/10.3406/antiq.2014.3847 Evenepoel, Willy, "Seneca on virtus, gaudium and voluptas: Some Additional Observations," Antiquité Classique 85 (2016), 211-216. https://doi.org/10.3406/antiq.2016.3893 Fantham, Elaine, Harry M. Hine, James Ker, and Gareth D. Williams. Seneca, Hardship and Happiness. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2014. The Use and Misuse of Pleasure Foucault Studies, No. 33, 1-23. 20 Fernández, José Miguel, “Spiritual Exercises and Language Games: The Influence of Wittgenstein’s Later Philosophy of Language on Pierre Hadot’s Approach to Ancient Philosophy as a Way of Life,” Littera Scripta. Revista Filosofía 3 (2022), 1-22. Flynn, Thomas, "Philosophy as a Way of Life: Foucault and Hadot," Philosophy and Social Crit- icism 31:5-6 (2005), 609-622. https://doi.org/10.1177/0191453705055492. Foucault, Michel, The Care of the Self: Volume 3 of the History of Sexuality. New York: Vintage Books, 1990. Foucault, Michel, The Use of Pleasure: Volume 2 of the History of Sexuality. New York: Vintage Books, 1990. Foucault, Michel, "On the Genealogy of Ethics: An Overview of Work in Progress," in Ethics: Subjectivity and Truth; The Essential Works of Michel Foucault 1954-1984 Vol. I, ed. Paul Rab- inow, 253-280. New York: The New Press, 1997. Foucault, Michel, "Self Writing," in Ethics: Subjectivity and Truth, ed. Paul Rabinow, 207-222. New York: The New Press, 1997b. Foucault, Michel, The Hermeneutics of the Subject: Lectures at the Collège de France, 1981-82. New York: Picador, 2005. Gill, Jerry H., "Wittgenstein and the Function of Philosophy," Metaphilosophy 2:2 (1971), 137- 149. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9973.1971.tb00234.x Graver, Margaret, Stoicism and Emotion. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2007. Graver, Margaret, "Anatomies of Joy: Seneca and the Gaudium Tradition," in Hope, Joy, and Affection in the Classical World, ed. Ruth R. Caston and Robert A. Kaster, 123-142. New York: Oxford University Press, 2016. Graver, Margaret, "Pre-emotions and Reader Emotions in Seneca: De ira and Epistulae morales," Maia: Rivista di letterature classiche 69:2 (2017), 281-296. Graver, Margaret, and A.A Long, Seneca, Letters on Ethics: to Lucilius. Chicago: Chicago Uni- versity Press, 2015. Griffin, Miriam T., Seneca, On Benefits. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2011. Grimal, Pierre, L. Annaei Senecae De vita beata. Sénèque, Sur le bonheur. Paris: Presses Universi- taires de France, 1969. Gros, Frédéric, "Course Context," in The Hermeneutics of the Subject: Lectures at the Collège de France 1981-1982, 507-550. New York: Picador, 2005. Hadot, Pierre, "Reflections on the Notion of 'The Cultivation of the Self'," in Michel Foucault, Philosopher, 225-232. Exeter: Harvester Wheatsheaf, 1992. Hadot, Pierre, Philosophy as a Way of Life: Spiritual Exercises from Socrates to Foucault. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers, 1995. Hadot, Pierre, "Reflections on the Idea of the 'Cultivation of the Self'," in Philosophy as a Way of Life: Spiritual Exercises from Socrates to Foucault, 206-213. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers, 1995. Hadot, Pierre, The Inner Citadel: The Meditations of Marcus Aurelius. Cambridge: Harvard Uni- versity Press, 1998. Hadot, Pierre, Exercices spirituels et philosophie antique. Paris: Albin Michel, 2002. MATTEO STETTLER Foucault Studies, No. 33, 1-23. 21 Hadot, Pierre, What is Ancient Philosophy?. Cambridge and London: The Belknap Press of Har- vard University, 2004. Hadot, Pierre, Wittgenstein et les limites du langage. Paris: Vrin, 2004. Hadot, Pierre, The Present Alone is Our Happiness: Conversations with Jeannie Carlier and Arnold I. Davidson. Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2009. Hadot, Pierre, "Conversio," in Discours et mode de vie philosophique, ed. Xavier Pavie, 133-137. Paris: Les Belles Lettres, 2014. Hadot, Pierre, "Foucault dans le texte," Philosophie Magazine 15 (2018), 91. Hadot, Pierre, "Conversion," in The Selected Writings of Pierre Hadot, ed. Matthew Sharpe and Federico Testa, 90-103. London: Bloomsbury, 2020. Hadot, Pierre, "An Interrupted Dialogue with Michel Foucault: Convergences and Diver- gences," in The Selected Writings of Pierre Hadot: Philosophy as Practice, ed. Matthew Sharpe and Federico Testa, 227-234. London and New York: Bloomsbury Academic, 2020. Hadot, Pierre, "The Figure of the Sage in Greek and Roman Antiquity," in The Selected Writings of Pierre Hadot: Philosophy as Practice, ed. Matthew Sharpe and Federico Testa, 186-206. Lon- don and New York: Bloomsbury Academic, 2020. Hadot, Pierre, The Selected Writings of Pierre Hadot. Philosophy as Practice. London and New York: Bloomsbury Academic, 2020. Hadot, Pierre, "Epistrophe and Metanoia in the History of Philosophy," Philosophy Today 65:1 (2021), 201-210. Haynes, Richard P., "The Theory of Pleasure of the Old Stoa," The American Journal of Philology 83:4 (1962), 412-419. Hine, Harry M., Seneca, Natural Questions. Chicago and London: The University of Chicago Press, 2010. Irrera, Orazio, "Pleasure and Transcendence of the Self: Notes on 'A Dialogue Too Soon Inter- rupted' Between Michel Foucault and Pierre Hadot," Philosophy and Social Criticism 36:9 (2010), 995-1017. Laugier, Sandra, "Pierre Hadot as a reader of Wittgenstein," Paragraph 34:3 (2011), 322-337. Long, Anthony A., "Aristotle's Legacy to Stoic Ethics," Bulletin of the Institute of Classical Studies 15 (1968), 72-85. Malaspina, Ermanno, L. Annaei Senecae De clementia libri duo: Prolegomeni, testo critico e com- mento. Alessandria: Ed. dell'Orso, 2005. McMahon, Jennifer A., "Beauty as Harmony of the Soul: the Aesthetic of the Stoics," in Proceedings of the 8th International Conference of Greek Studies 2009, ed. Marietta Rosetto, Michael Tsianikas, George Couvalis and Maria Palaktsoglou, 54-63. Modern Greek: Adelaide, 2012. Montanari, Moreno, Hadot e Foucault nello specchio dei Greci: La filosofia antica come esercizio di trasformazione. Milano: Mimesis Edizioni, 2009. Montanari, Moreno, "La Filosofia antica come esercizio spirituale e cura di sé nelle interpret- azioni di Pierre Hadot e Michel Foucault," Studi Urbinati, B - Scienze Umane e Sociali 80 (2010), 343-353. https://doi.org/10.14276/2464-9333.189 The Use and Misuse of Pleasure Foucault Studies, No. 33, 1-23. 22 Reynolds, L. D., L. Annaei Senecae Ad Lucilius Epistulae Morales. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1965. Sharpe, Matthew, "Towards a Phenomenology of Sagesse: Uncovering the Unique Philosoph- ical Problematic of Pierre Hadot," Angelaki 23:2 (2018), 125-138. Sharpe, Matthew, "Introduction: Situating Hadot Today," in The Selected Writings of Pierre Hadot: Philosophy as Practice, ed. Matthew Sharpe and Federico Testa, 1-29. London: Blooms- bury Academic, 2020. Sharpe, Matthew and Matteo J. Stettler. "Pushing Against an Open Door: Agamben on Hadot and Foucault," Classical Receptions Journal 14:1 (2022), 120-139. https://doi.org/10.1093/crj/clab007 Simonazzi, Moreno, La formazione del soggetto nell'antichità: La lettura di Michel Foucault e di Pierre Hadot. Roma: Aracne Editrice, 2007. Stephan, Cassiana Lopes, "Pierre Hadot e Michel Foucault: sobre a felicidade estoica e a ex- periência da alegria," Sapere Aude 7:13 (2016), 228-239. https://doi.org/10.5752/P.2177-6342.2016v7n13p228 Stimilli, Elettra, "Esercizi spirituali o tecniche di vita? Pierre Hadot e Michel Foucault a con- fronto," Pensiero: rivista di filosofia 46:1/2 (2008), 95-111. Testa, Federico, "Towards a History of Philosophical Practices in Michel Foucault and Pierre Hadot," PLI: the Warwick Journal of Philosophy (2016), 168-190. Wimberly, Cory, "The Joy of Difference: Foucault and Hadot on the Aesthetic and the Univer- sal in Philosophy," Philosophy Today 53:2 (2009), 191-202. https://doi.org/10.5840/philtoday200953261 Author info Matteo Johannes Stettler mstettler@deakin.edu.au Ph.D. candidate in Philosophy Department of Philosophy Deakin University Melbourne, Australia Matteo Johannes Stettler is a Ph.D. candidate in Philosophy at Deakin University (Australia), and a Deakin University Postgraduate Research Scholarship (DUPRS) holder. He collaborates with the research groups “Philosophy as a Way of Life,” of the Pontificia Università Grego- riana of Rome, and “Forms of Life and Practices of Philosophy” (particularly the “Art of Liv- ing” line of research) of the NOVA Institute of Philosophy (IFILNOVA) of Lisbon, which he visited for a few months in 2022. Stettler has co-authored with Matthew Sharpe specialistic articles for Classical Receptions and Philosophy Today, and he has written essays, book reviews, and translations for a variety of non-specialist journals and magazines. His latest publication is “The τόπος of the Goods of Fortune in Consolatio II and III: How to Console and Exhort Boethius” for Aeuvm. MATTEO STETTLER Foucault Studies, No. 33, 1-23. 23 Acknowledgment A first version of this paper was drafted for a graduate seminar on the second and third vol- umes of Foucault’s History of Sexuality (‘Political Philosophy: Advanced Course’) held by Dr. David Lloyd Dusenbury at KU Leuven (Belgium) in the fall of 2018. During the same year, a revised version of the paper was presented at the 8th HIW Annual Graduate Student Confer- ence hosted by the same institute. The author wants to thank all the participants at the seminar and the conference, as well as the two anonymous reviewers, whose many suggestions helped give this contribution its final form. A special thanks goes to Willy Evenepoel, who kindly rendered himself available to correspond and share with me his authoritative view on Sen- eca’s notions of joy and pleasure.