Critical Review Aristotle on False Reasoning: Language and the World in the Sophistical Refutations SCOTT G. SCHREIBER Albany: State University of New York Press, 2003. Pp. xvi +248. Hardcover: ISBN 0-794-5659-5, US$68.50; paperback: ISBN 0-7914-5660-9, US$22.95. Reviewed by George Boger 1. Overview Schreiber's examination of Aristotle's treatment of the 'traditional' fallacies in Sophistical Refutations (SR) is well worth the attention of logicians, philosophers, argumentation theorists, and classicists who desire a better understanding of Aris- totle's ancient accomplishments relating to logic and argumentation. While Schreiber occasionally engages contemporary argumentation theorists l about fallacious rea- soning and their assessment of Aristotle, his principal concern is historical and not directly to resolve modern problems concerning a typology of mistakes. Thus he early establishes the error of reducing all sophistical argumentations to linguistic problems. Nevertheless, because he emphasizes the non-formal aspects of falla- cious reasoning, he might strike a chord with argumentation theorists. Sti11, he does not aim to accommodate modern predilections but to make clear Aristotle's "philosophical justification ... for his classification offallacies" (xiv), which he successfully argues is "principled and nonarbitrary" (7). He accomplishes this through numerous analyses of each kind of fallacy according to a comprehensive method that includes: (1) considering Aristotle's understanding of the relationship between language and nature; (2) embracing Aristotle's notion of explanation; (3) recognizing the role Aristotle assigns to resolution for categorizing a fallacy; (4) working with the definitions of a syllogism and a refutation; and (5) invoking the principle of parsimony implicitly operative in Aristotle's system of categorization. The principle of parsimony helps to sift out problems relating the discussions in SR to discussions in Topics, On Interpretation, Categories, and Rhetoric. Accord- ingly, Schreiber carefully 'parses' each of Aristotle's examples and nicely accom- modates their re-presentations to a modern English-speaking reader. This is no mean accomplishment, and Schreiber in the process displays familiarity with the ancient Greek language. However, while in general sympathy with Aristotle, he is not an apologist for his errors. Such close examination of Aristotle's discussion of fallacious reasoning, which Schreiber calls "false reasoning", reveals some impor- tant lapses in his thinking. In particular, he notices some discrepancies in Aristo- tle's treatment of the fallacies in SR and between SR and other treatises in the Organon. As a consequence, working interpretively within Aristotle's philosophy, ©In/ormalLogicVoI.23,No.l (2003): pp.77-90. 78 George Boger he makes some important adjustments to his categorization while not discounting the cogency of his determinations. In this sense, then, Schreiber contributes to our knowledge of Aristotle's logic while not running afoul of becoming an' Aristo- telian' in the vein of so many contemporary authors who misrepresent Aristotle's logic in introductory textbooks. Schreiber has organized his discussion of the fallacies along the lines estab- lished by Aristotle as modified by his interpretive posture. After a short preface (xiii-xv) and an informative introduction (1-7) where he outlines his approach, the book is divided into three parts of nine chapters. Part I examines the fallacies due to language: Chapter 1 treats the power of names (11-18); Chapter 2, homonymy and amphiboly (19-36); Chapter 3, form of expression (37-54); and Chapter 4, composition, division, and accent (55-76). Part 2 consists in a single chapter on resolving false arguments (79-93). Part 3 examines the fallacies faIling outside of language: Chapter 6 is on begging the question and non-cause as cause (97-112); Chapter 7 treats accident and consequent (113-139); Chapter 8, secundum qUid (141-151); and Chapter 9, many questions (153-166). There is a brief section entitled "Conclusion and Summary" that acts as a kind of final chapter (167- 171).In addition there are four short but informative appendices (173-190) treat- ing, respectively, paralogisms in Aristotle, words and counters-Platonic anteced- ents, Aristotle on KUpWV predication, and Platonic and Academic background to secundum quid. Notes (191-232) are gathered as endnotes and followed by a small bibliography and an index of names. There is an only modestly useful subject index: there are no entries, for example, for 'protasis', 'proposition', 'premise', 'multiple reference', 'language convention' and 'relevance', all of which Schreiber treats, nor for many of his subsection headings; however, the contents (vii-x) could serve as an auxiliary index. In addition, there is no index of passages cited, which are numerous and which appear in the endnotes. A glossary of Aristotle's logical terminology would be a nice addition. 2. Adjustment to Aristotle's categorization Schreiber remarks that he was initially provoked by Aristotle's categorical claim that there are only twelve fallacies. He sensibly follows Aristotle to consider igno- ratio elenchi generic of fallacious reasoning and not itself a thirteenth fallacy. Following Aristotle, then, to divide fallacies into those due to language and those not due to language, Schreiber takes Aristotle's typology as reproduced in the following table (4, 167). This, of course, is all familiar. Once having established Aristotle's program, he proceeds in Part 1 to examine the fallacies due to language with an express pur- pose not only to elucidate Aristotle's thinking but also to indicate something prob- lematic with it. He turns to the pivotal section of his discourse in Part 2, where he lays out the interpretive apparatus of his own modified' Aristotelian' method. This Schreiber's Aristotle on False Reasoning 79 False reasoning I Ignoratio elenchi Due to language: Outside of language ~ Double meaning Non-double meaning I I Homonymy Amphiboly Form of expression Accent Composition Division Begging the question Non-cause as cause Accident Consequent Secundum quid Many questions method affords him a vantage point to review and critique each type offaJlacy due to language. He proceeds in Part 3 to examine the fallacies outside of language using the method established in Part 2. After completing these analyses, he presents his adjustment to Aristotle's categorization (171) as reproduced in the table on the next page. Schreiber's project in Aristotle on False Reasoning is to justify this adjustment to Aristotle's categorization of the fallacies as more faithfully representing both Aristotle's discourse on fallacious argumentation and his incompletely fulfilled in- tention. 3. Schreiber's interpretive apparatus Schreiber identifies the role Aristotle attributes to the resolution of fallacies as central for understanding Aristotle's typology. This approach, not merely consti- tuting Schreiber's interpretive stance but also an integral part of Aristotle's own method, renders Aristotle's typology intelligible and helps to make sense of variant ascriptions when such ascriptions sometimes appear arbitrary. Schreiber identifies two principles underlying Aristotle's analytic method: (I) understanding defective reasoning requires understanding the paradigm of nondefective reasoning; (2) understanding itself requires providing causes--in the 80 George Boger False reasoning I Ignoratio elenchi Due to language: Due to language Outside of language Non-double meaning2 Double meaning I I Accent Homonymy Begging the question Composition/Division Amphiboly Non-cause as cause Form of expression Accident/Consequent Secundum quid Many questions Multiple reference case of reasoning, the causes of both nondefective and defective reasoning. Now, since encountering perplexity motivates the activity of reasoning toward a resolu- tion, a proper resolution must be fully explanatory. And to be fully explanatory, a resolution must explain (1) "why the purported reasoning is not real reasoning", and (2) "why the false reasoning appears to be real reasoning" (81, emphasis added). Schreiber considers the first to be a fairly objective procedure: "reasoning (auAA.oyw~oC; [sullogismos)) is strictly defined, and there are a limited number of ways to violate that definition" (8\). The second he recognizes to be relative to a participant's understanding or misunderstanding of language and nature-just the sources for both correct and incorrect reasoning. In respect of the definition of a sullogismos, which provides the baseline for argument assessment, Schreiber begins immediately with Aristotle's statement in SR. "He defines a syllogism as 'an argument in which, when certain things are set down, something different from the things set down follows necessarily by means of the things set down'" (1). In an endnote to his rendering' s ullogism os , as 'syllogism', Schreiber notes his preference either to transliterate the word as 'syl- logism' or to render it by 'reasoning'. In this respect he reverts to the older prac- tice of such translators as Poste, Forster, and Pickard-Cambridge (prior to Barnes' emendations, Princeton 1984). Moreover, he does not restrict its use to denoting only a three-term valid argument as in Prior Analytics. Nor does he translate it by 'deduction', as is now customary in discussions of Aristotle's formal logic and even in Louis-Andre Dorion's recent French translation (1995), since, as he writes, "not all formally valid deductions constitute syllogisms in Aristotle's sense" (191). Schreiber continues next to distinguish various kinds of syllogism namely, demon- Schreiber's Aristotle on False Reasoning 81 strative, dialectical, peirastic, and eristic. He also refers to ignoratio elenchi in this connection. He does not make reference here, and only sparingly when he treats many questions, to what a proposition (rcP(YC£fOH;; protasis) is, and this is an im- portant omission. Still, he cites Aristotle's definition of a refutation and recognizes it to be a syllogism/reasoning to the contradictory of a given proposition. He then extracts and gathers the features of a refutation as part of his paradigm for assess- ing the error of a fallacy (88, 144). A refutation is a syllogism in which: (l) premises do not include the conclusion; (2) a conclusion follows necessarily from the premises; and (3) a conclusion denies one and the same predicate affirmed in the premises. In respect ofthis last requirement, the predicate denied must be: (3a) the thing signified, not just the name; (3b) the thing signified by the name affirmed in the premises; and (3c) the thing qualified in precisely the same way as it was affirmed in the premises. Now, while a fallacy can be resolved relative to a person or relative to the argument, Aristotle preferred the resolution relative to the argu- ment since this resolution is more widely applicable to other false arguments of the same kind. Schreiber seems to take Aristotle to mean by 'relative to the argument' that an error is objectively located in a 'violation' of syllogistic, that is, of deduc- tive, reasoning as well as in holding mistaken beliefs about nature. Next, in taking a charitable tack toward understanding Aristotle, Schreiber invokes a principle of parsimony-that "if one resolution schema S determines two classes of fallacy where another resolution schema T determines one class, then T is better than S" (85). Schreiber takes it as implicitly operative in Aristotle's analyses and not merely his own interpretive device. The utility of this principle consists in its ability to specify "the defining characteristics of the infimae species of false reasoning" (85). Applying this principle helps to identify how Aristotle categorized each fallacy and thus to make sense of what often appear to be arbi- trary assignments; it goes far to account for the cogency of Aristotle's categoriza- tion. Finally, a crucial part of Schreiber's interpretive apparatus consists in his ap- preciation of the conventional nature and epistemic role of language to represent the world in human cognition. While he does not treat this matter extensively anywhere, he treats it sufficiently well in Chapter I and later in Appendices 2 and 3 for his readers to grasp his intention. Schreiber locates the sources of fallacious reasoning in precisely the places where the cogent reasoning that leads to knowl- edge of the world originates---in the gap between knowing and being that language mediates. 4. Aristotle's principal error Throughout his discourse Schreiber aims to preserve Aristotle's assessment of fallacious reasoning; he believes his adjustments are entirely commensurate with Aristotle's thinking. Aristotle's principal mistake, while he was nevertheless very 82 George Boger attuned to a conventional notion oflanguage and the multivocity of words in their relationships to things, was to fail to recognize the multivocity of "multivocity." Schreiber writes: Given, then, the unlimited number and unknowable nature of individuals, names possessing the power of multiple signification become necessary epistemological tools for understanding. But this sort of multiple significa- tion is nothing more than the power of common predicates to signity multiple individuals. It does not require that common predicates signity multiple kinds of individuals. This latter phenomenon, however, turns out to be one of the chief culprits among Aristotle's examples of fallacies based on linguis- tic double meanings. The power of multiple signification includes for Aristotle both (non-homony- mous) universals that apply to multiple individuals of the same definition and ho- monymous names that signify things having different definitions. The former is a necessary feature of language based on the non isomorphic relationship between names and things signifiable, while the latter is a purely contingent feature of any given language. Yet Aristotle sometimes conjlates the two. In both types of false reasoning, those generated by universals having references to mUltiple individuals and those generated by universals signifying different kinds of individuals, there is a failure to signify the same thing (whether individual or kind) by the same word or phrase, and this seems to have been what impressed Aristotle more than the differ- ence between the two (17, emphasis added). The power of names, in one respect, consists in their having mUltiple significa- tion, that is, a given universal word can signify (l) many different individuals falling under that universal as well as (2) that universal itself under which the individuals fall. This is a necessary and inevitable epistemic feature of language. In another respect, the power of names can consist in a word signifying different kinds of individuals rather than different individuals of the same kind. In short, while Aristotle recognized an essential feature of language to possess words signi- fying universals that refer to the individuals under them-and a feature that locates a source of fallacious reasoning-he missed that such words also signify the universal itself and different individuals of the same kind. "Aristotle would be better served by explicitly differentiating from semantic mUltivocity a second spe- cies of double meaning, namely, where one and the same signifier makes reference to multiple individuals under one universal signifier" (170). According to this ap- proach, we can understand Schreiber's addition of "multiple reference" as a fal- lacy due to language where double meaning is problematic (170-171). 5. Fallacies due to language Aristotle's treatment of homonymy and amphiboly in SR 4 is not especially prob- lematic: an ambiguity due to homonymy occurs when the same name has seman- Schreiber's Aristotle on False Reasoning 83 tic double meaning apart from syntax; an ambiguity due to amphiboly when the same phrase having semantic double meaning because of its constituent names having double syntactic roles. A problem arises when in SR 17 Aristotle confuses the two, even having difficulty classifying a given case. In the 'double Coriscus' case, for example, Aristotle vacillates between the confusing of two different individuals of the same kind having the same name (amphibolous because of syn- tax) and the confusing of two different kinds signified by the same name (ho- monymous). In the case of form of expression, Schreiber follows the usual prac- tice of taking these fallacies to be instances of category mistakes, but he extends this approach to include other confusions arising from not properly understanding nature. Sometimes it is difficult to differentiate form of expression from homonymy and amphiboly. Again we encounter Aristotle's conflating notions ofmultivocity, in this Case not sufficiently recognizing names having the same inflections or the same syntactic positions signifying different kinds of things. In the case of composition and division, linguistic fallacies not involving double meaning, Schreiber rebuts the conventional understanding that these fallacies in- volve confusions of parts and wholes (which would place it outside fallacies due to language), except when the parts/whole problem involves the constituent parts of a proposition. Still, this fallacy does not involve double meaning, and thus it is not reducible to either homonymy or amphiboly. Schreiber shows that Aristotle did not here really distinguish two fallacies but rather two 'opposite' perspectives of the same linguistic problem-now viewed from the vantage point of fallacy resolution. Moreover, Schreiber picks up on Aristotle's closely linking the fallacies of composition and division with those of accent to affirm that these fallacies are best understood as arising in the transition from an oral to a literate language-they "stand as monuments to the changes in Greek orthography beginning in the fourth century" (68). This emphasis on the utterance rather than the written proposition is the major means by which Aristotle distinguishes between errors due to Accent, Composition, and Division and those due to double meaning (homonymy, amphiboly, and form of expression). In the former cases, one fails to recog- nize that a unique signifier is being used with multiple significations. In the latter cases, one fails to recognize that two unique signifiers, each with uni- vocal signification, are being treated as one signifier. In the one, the appear- ance of sy 1I0gistic validity derives from ignorance of multivocity. In the other, the appearance of syllogistic validity derives from ignorance of what individuates a signifier. These different sources of the false appearance are Aristotle's chief means of distinguishing between fallacy types. Isolating these sources is the task of resolving the fallacy. (75-76) Schreiber attributes to Aristotle an understanding that each fallacy due to language derives from violating the refutation-requirement of having a conclusion that de- nies one and the same predicate affirmed in a premise. 84 George Boger 6. Fallacies not due to language Schreiber represents Aristotle as understanding fallacies not due to language to be violations of the requirements of a syllogism in its refutation role. He maintains that Aristotle considered begging the question to violate the requirement that the con- clusion not already be included among the premises, that each of non-cause as cause, accident, consequent, and many questions violates the requirement that a conclusion follow logically from the premises. However, he considers secundum qUid to violate the requirement that the predicate denied in the conclusion must be the same predicate affirmed in the premise-that the thing be qualified in the denial in the same respect that it was affirmed in the premise. This fallacy involves mistaken beliefs about the way names and expressions relate to the things they signify and thus it combines errors about language and errors about nature- indeed, deceptive ways of speaking may produce mistaken beliefs about nature. Schreiber argues that secundum qUid properly belongs among the fallacies of dou- ble meaning due to language. He also alters Aristotle's distinguishing accident and consequent in much the same manner as he adjusts Aristotle's treatment of com- position/division-accident/consequent is one fallacy because each instance em- ploys the same kind of resolution, namely, showing by counterexample that not all predicates belong equally to things and their accidents. In the case of non-cause as cause, Schreiber notes that Aristotle's definition of reasoning has a built-in rel- evance requirement, that the error lies in a participant's "ignorance of which things are relevant explanations of non-self-explanatory facts" (112). This is not a formal feature ofinvalidity, but a participant's epistemic failing about ontology. This fail- ure is also a signature for cases of accident/consequent where someone mistakes the terms in the premises to signify things "indistinguishable and one in substance." In the case of many questions, Schreiber makes only a cursory reference to its violation devolving to ignorance of what aprotasis is, something Aristotle consid- ers important in SR 6 along with ignorance of what a refutation is in SR 6 and earlier in SR 5. Schreiber emphasizes the error as related to mistaken beliefs about nature. The two forms of many questions, disjunction and conjunction, consist in errors in predicating, respectively, what belongs to a whole as also belonging to each of its parts (the real locus of the parts/whole fallacy misascribed to compo- sition/division) and disjunctively offering an irrelevant premise as explanatory of the conclusion. Since argumentation theorists have devoted considerable attention to begginf the question, perhaps Schreiber's treatment of this fallacy can illustrate Aristotle': notion of correct reasoning and something of his notion of a paralogism. Discus sion has often focused on the sense in which there exists 'fallacious reasoning' From the vantage point of modem logic there is, strictly speaking, no fallacy, tha is, no violation of entailment or validity per se. Schreiber notes the restriction Aristotle places on deductive argumentation that distinguish his notion from that c Schreiber's Aristotle on False Reasoning 85 I modem logician. The error in begging the question is not formal per se, but ~pistemic; and this error devolves to a mistaken belief about nature. Schreiber lotes that in Prior Ana/ytics (he makes references in this connection to Posterior 4nalytics only in endnotes) Aristotle considers a demonstration (~1t6o€\~ tC;), which .s a syllogism, to have epistemic requirements, namely, that its premises be better mown and prior to the conclusion. He leaves unstated that these premises must also be known to be true. The requirement that such propositions be better known and prior to the proposition in the role of conclusion means that the premise propo- sitions must be known through themselves. Such propositions are, then, self-ex- planatory and not, which Schreiber does not mention, mediated-they are all€(Jov, that is, they are not the results of syllogistic reasoning but its starting points or first principles. In fact, as Schreiber does remark in an endnote (214), the fallacy is properly named "asking the original point" or "assuming the original point", He then lists five ways that a case of begging the question might arise, all of which devolve to a epistemic requirement of demonstrative reasoning. In a brief section relating begging the question to immediate inferences, or certain logical equivalences, Schreiber remarks that someone's "not recogniz[ing} the natural epistemic equivalences of logical equivalences" (l05) makes that participant vulnerable to this fallacy. The putative defect in reasoning lies not in validity per se but in the Aristotelian requirement that a syllogistic conclusion be a proposition whose terms have been mediated through the premise propositions. Schreiber does not incor- porate this notion into his assessment of SR. 7. Concluding remarks Schreiber early makes clear, while nevertheless largely following conventional wisdom about assessing fallacious reasoning, that guarding against false reasoning involves beliefs not just about the "mechanics of proper logical form ... [but also about] the right meta-logical and metaphysical beliefs" (xiii). Indeed, his assess- ment of fallacious reasoning decidedly shies from a formal logical analysis. So- phistical reasoning naturally involves various appearances. There are: premises that appear to be what they are not; arguments that appear to be valid but are invalid; valid arguments that appear to be relevant but are not (2). Resolving such appear- ances requires discovering certain false beliefs, in particular, those about: the parts of language itself; the relationship language has to the realities it signifies; and the non-linguistic world outside of language signified by language (6; cf. 150-151). Schreiber does not succumb to psychologistic explanations of these appearances but repeatedly locates their sources in mistaken beliefs about nature. We might recognize a leitmotif of his book that "logic, as a general study of reasoning, is not metaphysically neutral for Aristotle" (7). This notion of 'metaphysical partiality' chimes again at the very close of his discourse that logic "is not a metaphysically neutral activity" (171). 86 George Boger A particularly attractive feature of Schreiber's discourse in this connection, as his subtitle suggests, is treating fallacious reasoning not only against the standards of correct reasoning but also by understanding correct reasoning as itself grounded in nature. This understanding requires excursions into ontology for two projects: (1) to ascertain the truth or falsity of a given proposition and (2) to ascertain the validity or invalidity of a given argument. Schreiber, however, does not especially explicate this theme; his study is more practically disposed and not itself a work in the philosophy of logic and ontology. Still, he mentions or suggests at important junctures-for example, when elucidating the notion of fallacy resolution, in ap- pendix 3 on !co(nov predication, and when comparing Protagoras on solecism- the notion that language reflects in consciousness realities existing independently of consciousness and that grasping correct reason, analogous to grasping the truth and falsity of a proposition, has an ontic underpinning. Aristotle, he remarks, considered language a human convention for understanding nature. Although no- where ascribing a correspondence perspective to Aristotle, Schreiber surely at- tributes such a view to Aristotle for understanding his accomplishments in SR. This theme resonates in his explaining and resolving fallacious reasoning in both its objective and participant relative respects. In fact, he concludes that all the fallacies, with the exception of accent and composition/division, derive their per- suasive appearance wholly or partly from some sort of extralinguistic misconcep- tion.) "Because the ability to reason correctly is dependent on the ability to distin- guish true from false argumentation, it follows that, for Aristotle, proper reasoning requires a proper metaphysics" (170-171 }-that is, an epistemology grounded in a proper understanding of nature. Not having the proper ontology necessarily leads to confusing cogent and fallacious argumentations. [While] Aristotle has not given us the last word either on metaphysics or language ... contemporary logicians should recogni7.£, as Aristotle did, that even our logical intuitions-those beliefs about what constitutes a valid inference that formal systems of natural deduction are designed to capture- themselves are based upon definite ontological presuppositions. Aristotle's general position merits serious consideration. Logic, as the study of reason- ing, is not a metaphysically neutral activity. (l71) Argumentation theorists and formal logicians might give this notion more serious consideration. Schreiber, then, neither aligns himself with traditional formal logicians nor es- pecially with argumentation theorists. He has managed to steer a course between the two and perhaps as a consequence to have established some new ground, consideration of which might move both traditions toward some reconciliation. On the one hand, Schreiber suggests that logic is a part of epistemology, whose project is to establish objective knowledge ofthe truth or falsity of a given propo- sition. In this connection, logic treats argumentation forma1Jy in respect of deter- mining the validity or invalidity or a given argument as a deductive exercise. On the other hand, he suggests that such a project requires an awareness of its ontic Schreiber's Aristotle on False Reasoning 87 underpinning. Objective knowledge of both truth and falsity and validity and inva- lidity requires grasping them as reflections in cognition of matters objectively inde- pendent of cognition. Thus, aformallogician might better grasp the ontic founda- tion of validity and invalidity as with truth and falsity, and an informal logician might better recognize the traditional formalism underlying study of fallacious reasoning. Demonstrative knowledge requires objective knowledge both of logical consequence and truth and falsity as these unite in argumentation. Schreiber's discussion only suggests this application of his study. Finally, we indicate some matters that need attention for our improved under- standing of SR. First, the scholarly community still awaits a fuller understanding of Aristotle's notion of aparalogismos, typically translated by 'fallacy' as Schreiber. Second, Schreiber's notion of a sullogismos is unsatisfactory in light of recent developments. And, third, while he displays familiarity with Greek and generally with logic, his translations of Aristotle's logical terminology need considerable refinement. Just what counts as a fallacy or a mistake in reasoning is continually discussed among argumentation theorists, less avidly or assiduously among formal logicians. Getting a grip on this matter, of course, is compounded by similar discussions about what counts as an argument or an argumentation, whether cogency is par- ticipant relative or context independent, etc.-in short, by discussions about 'good arguments' and 'bad arguments'. When a modem logician turns to assess Aristo- tie's treatment of fallacious reasoning, and even to his treatment of 'formal logic' , he or she is often encumbered by various modem prejudices as well as by mis- taken notions of logic. In just this respect, then, we need a clear exposition of how Aristotle understands deductive reasoning, or natural deduction as the case may be, and how he understands an argument not to satisfy deductive rigor. Schreiber has followed the conventional wisdom to consider SR the final section of Topics, thought to be part of an 'earlier logic.' It is customary to consider Aristotle's treatment of the fallacies to be 'informal', since he hardly invokes the formalism evident in his treatment of syllogistic reasoning in Prior Analyties. However, understanding a 1t~P~AoywIJ6C; (paralogismos), or a 'parasullogismos' as the case may be, might require understanding something of the formalism of a sullogismos. There are suggestions of this requirement in SR, as indeed the second part of Prior Analyties involves matters relating to SR. Schreiber in Aristotle on False Reasoning makes headway on this project as, for example, in (I) his laying out the requirements of a refutation, (2) his brief and insightful appendix 1 on paralogism, and (3) Chapter 5 on resolution. However, grasping fallacious reason- ing against the rigorous requirements of ~1tOOHKnKT) E1tUl1:"lJl1, or demonstrative knowledge, would considerably enrich his portrait of a paralogism os. An analogue of this approach concerns the order of writing the two Analyties. Whether the writing of Posterior Analyties antedates that of Prior Analylies, we can still recog- nize that Posterior Analyties is informed by his conception of a sullogismos as 88 George Boger treated in Prior Analytics. Perhaps, then, our understanding of a paralogism os as Aristotle treats it in SR could be infonned by grasping how he understands a sullogismos in Prior Analytics. In any case, this matter needs to be worked through more fully as a topic in its own right. Granting a mutual relationship among the Organon treatises for understanding each of them, we might expect Schreiber's treatment of a sullogismos and its role in resolving sophistical refutations to need some adjustment. His treatment of as- sessing argumentation seems throughout to waffle on this matter. On the one hand, he down plays syllogistic fonnalism by turning to semantic and ontological matters, and, on the other hand, he invokes the validity requirement of a refutation (an elenchos), which just is asullogismos. But he leaves undetennined the connec- tion between the two; thus he leaves undetennined how Aristotle conceived their relationship. Does Aristotle presume an underlying fonnalism in his assessment of fallacious reasoning? Does Aristotle link semantic considerations to detennining the fonn/pattern of an argument? These are important and eminently interesting matters, clarity on which, albeit principally historical, would benefit fonnal and infonnallogicians alike. We can leave open the question about reducing the falla- cies to linguistic problems. Nevertheless, it is possible to reduce most of the falla- cies-as Aristotle himself suggested when he referred to them as ignorance of what a refutation is and what a proposition is-to violating the rule for mediating tenns in 'categorical' logic, the very logic grounded in a substance/attribute ontol- ogy as Schreiber so aptly notes. Of course, then, we must better grasp that the fonn, or pattern, of a proposition and that ;)f the argument consisting in such propositions, has a semantic dimension. While the pattern of a sullogismos, such as, that named "Barbara," is patently obvious, recognizing that a homonymous name in a categorical sentence really constitutes two tenns and thus that the one sentence expresses two propositions is not so obvious. The fallacy of homonymy, then, is analyzable as a fonnal violation-namely, the introduction of a fourth tenn. Perhaps, then, all the fallacies, save begging the question, introduce a fourth tenn and thus violate the fonnal requirement of a sullogismos, which leads to a conclusion that is not a logical consequence of the given premises. While this notion might seem to stretch interpretive license, it will nevertheless strengthen the integrity of Aristotle's accomplishment. This is another worthy avenue for further investigation. Perhaps the most infelicitous aspect of Schreiber's discussion concerns his translations of Aristotle's 'technical' tenninology. Throughout his discourse he uses the following expressions: 'false argumentation', 'false reasoning', 'false refutation', 'false appearance', 'false belief, 'false argument', and each ofthese has its counterpart of 'real', as in 'real reasoning'. Schreiber translates 'WEU0tl<;;' (pseudes) and '~AT'lO*' (atethes), whether attached to '06~4' or to 'AOY0<;;', 'auAAoYWfJ0<;;' and 'EAEYXT'lO<;;', by 'false' and 'true'. We have already mentioned his translating 'sullogismos' by 'syllogism' and 'reasoning'. ; ~owever, he not only Schreiber's Aristotle on False Reasoning 89 refers to a valid or invalid argument, he also refers to a valid or invalid syllogism and a valid deduction, and this is decidedly not Aristotle's understanding-every sullogismos is valid. Now, while his generally equating an eristic argument with a sophistic argument as paraIogisms, and each of these with an apparent sullogismos, is correct, his purpose would be better served to translate 'pseudes' and 'aletMs' by, respectively, 'faulty' or 'spurious' and 'genuine'. Surely when someone thinks or reasons, whether faultily or non-faultily, that person is doing real or genuine thinking. A proposition or belief is true or false, an argument valid or invalid, and an argumentation, which might involve establishing knowledge of validity or inva- lidity, is either cogent (on the principle of transitivity of consequence) or falla- cious. In each case, a participant might have mistaken beliefs as Schreiber so well establishes. He reverts here to earlier translations. Consequently, his manner of expression reflects not consulting recent work on Aristotle's deduction system; nor, it seems, despite his cordial acknowledgment of Dorion's French translation of SR, has he absorbed that contribution. Dorion translates 'sullogismos' by 'deduction'. This practice does not nullify his contribution to our understanding of SR. However, while his facility with ancient Greek is adequate to explicate parts of SR, his handling of the logical terminology raises questions about his logical acu- men and thus about his faithfully reproducing Aristotle's meaning. Schreiber needs to work through this matter more carefully. Schreiber treats other topics that might interest argumentation theorists. There are, for example, his discussion of the monolectical and dialectical aspect of rea- soning (although not using these expressions), his discussion of the relationships of syntax and semantics (in respect of Aristotle's understanding and a modem making sense of the fallacies), and his assessing various typologies. His treatment of these topics is informative about Aristotle's thinking and about argumentation. His perspective on typing fallacies according to their resolution is generally con- vincing. Overall he successfully presents Aristotle as a competent and principled student of fallacious argumentation and shows that studying Aristotle can provide a worthwhile vantage point for assessing modem argumentation. Schreiber's con- tribution is a nice complement to recent work on SR. Indeed, his book can serve as a useful companion to contemporary efforts at translating SR and to continuing studies of that ancient treatise on argumentation. Notes I 'Argumentation theorist' is used here generally to eompass persons working in various trends in modem studies of fallacious reasoning, as well as of good reasoning, and thus to include informal logicians, pragma-dialecticians, critical thinking theorists, and new rhetoricians. 1 After concluding his discourse, Sehreiber qualifies each kind offallacy in the following ways (171; cf. 169): those due to language without double meaning as involving errors about language both necessary and sufficient for false appearanees; those due to language with double meaning 90 George Boger as involving errors about language necessary but not sufficient for false appearances; and those outside of language as involving errors about ontology sufficient for false appearances. J See, for example, his comments in this respect for each of the fallacies: homonymy and amphiboly (93), form of expression (51, 93), begging the question (106), non-cause as cause (109, 112), accident/consequent (139), secundum qUid (l51), many questions (166), and multiple reference (170). However, his treatments of accent and composition/division also seem to involve this principle of explanation (76). References Dorion, L.-A. 1995. Aristote: Les refutations sophistiques. Paris: Vrin. Forster, E.S. 1955. On Sophistical Refutations. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Pickard-Cambridge, W.A. 1928. Topica and De Sophistic is Elenchis. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Pickard-Cambridge, W.A. 1984. Sophistical Refutations. In J. Barnes, The Complete Works of Aristotle. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Poste, E. 1987/1866. Aristotle on Fallacies or the Sophistic; Elenchi. New York: Garland Publishing. George Boger Department of Philosophy Canisius College 2001 Main Street Buffalo, NY 14208-1098 boger@canisius.edu