FROM THE EDITORS To begin, we want to apologize for and explain the very late publication of 18.2&3. Due to the resignation of our fonner assist- ant, a delay in securing his replacement, and considerable disorder in the operation, we have only recently begun to get on top of the journal's business. We deeply regret that the process of disseminating the work sent to the journal has been slowed. We plan to publish 19.1 in the summer, and an- other double issue, 19.2&3, in the fall, dat- ing that volume 1999. (Subscriptions,by Volume, not year, will not be affected.) Thanks to Mr. Pierre Boulos for his serv- ices from June 1997 through July 1998, and welcome to Dr. Marcello Guarini, our new assistant. Marcello has been a great help in restoring orderly operations, ably assisted by three students: Janice Perera, Daniel Gunaratnam and Bill Snowden. Thanks also to our colleague Kate Parr for help in pre- paring this issue. The contents of this double issue range widely over the principal areas of interest to readers of this joumal-infonnallogic, ar- gumentation theory and critical thinking. In "Logic, Art and Argument," Leo Groarke argues that pictures, paintings and cartoons all may carry persuasive force and hence can be construed as argument, to be appraised with the procedures and criteria used on verbal arguments. In "Philosophical Dialogue Theories," David Moore and Dave Hobbes, from a background in computer studies, review various dialogical models for argumentation, argue that Mackenzie's DC model has great potential, discuss empirical tests for its suit- ability, and inquire into the tractability of the system for computer-based applications. Most theorists agree that critical think- ing requires dispositions as well as skills, but no account of the dispositional compo- nent is generally accepted. In "Critical Think- ing Dispositions," Robert Ennis presents a new approach, specifying a set of criteria for judging dispositional accounts. His cri- tique of Perkins, Jay and Tischman leads to his own proposal. He concludes with some reflections on the task of assessing dispo- sitions. In "Attributed Favourable Relevance and Argument Evaluation" Derek Allen ar- gues there are problems with George Bowles's account (see INroRMALLooIC, 18.1) of the role of attributions of favourable rel- evance in deciding what constitutes a good argument, but argues that such attributions are relevant for the evaluation of an argu- ment In "What is an Infmite Regress Argu- ment?" Claude Gratton examines a mode of argument much used but little studied, in- troducing a basic vocabulary for discuss- ing such arguments and developing an hy- pothesis to explain why the claimed regress sometimes fails. He illustrates a common mistake in deriving the infmite regress and examines how the infmite regress functions as a premise. In "Does Scientific Realism Beg the Question," after reviewing four different ways of understanding the fallacy of beg- ging the question, Geoffrey Gorham con- cludes that, contrary to Fine, in none of them can it be claimed that scientific realism is guilty of begging the question. "The Argument of the Beard" is part of Douglas Walton's ongoing research into the individual fallacies. He proposes that the so-called argument of the beard, depending on the allegation of vagueness, is related to both the heap argument, and also to slip- pery slope. He classifies these three types or argument and discusses issues they raise for infonnallogic research. Besides these articles, there is a note from John Follman et a/. on resources for research in critical thinking assessment, critical reviews of Johnson's The Rise of Informal Logic (by David Hitchcock) and Walton's Plausible Reasoning (by James Freeman), and five book reviews. Contributors please note the new specifications for manuscripts in Editorial Information.