INFORMAL LOGIC XV. 1 , Winter 1993 Rhetoric and Argumentation: An Introduction JOSEPH W. WENZEL University of Illinois When the editors suggested this special issue on rhetoric and argument, they play- fully appended a sub-title: "What every in- formal logician should know about rhetoric, but was too shy to ask." The com- mon ground on which informal logicians and rhetoricians meet is argumentation, and both parties share a common goal, i.e., understanding argumentation-in theory, practice, and criticism. A well developed theory of argumentation, 1 submjt, requires principles and standards drawn from three sources that, together, make up the contro- versial arts par excellence: rhetoric, logic, and dialectic. If that's a fair statement, then it behooves informal logicians to attend to insights derived from rhetorical studies of argumentation. Argumentation is both a natural phe- nomenon and a unique human accomplish- ment. People argue naturally as one means of managing disagreements, but they typi- cally do so imperfectly and without con- scious art. Argumentation appears as a remarkable human accomplishment, how- ever, when the method is skillfully em- ployed for the sake of resolving differ- ences. Indeed, when the potential of argu- mentation as a method of critical deci- sion-making is fully realized, it is revealed as the paradigm of rational procedures for creating knowledge and achieving wise decisions-at least in the Western tradi- tion. At its best, argumentation is a process whereby problems are brought to attention and analyzed, interested parties become more knowlegable and more critical about relevant facts and values, and solutions are hammered out on the anvil of contro- versy. It is a process both creative and disciplined, depending on the skillful de- ployment of the three controversial arts. First, argumentation arises in a rhetori- cal situation. By that 1 mean a situation in which a human agent perceives an exi- gence, believes that something can be done about it by mobilizing the efforts of other human agents, and adresses them as an au- dience in a way calculated to influence their beliefs, feelings and/or actions with respect to the exigence (Bitzer, 1968). But, every rhetorical situation carries with it the potential for being transformed into a dia- lectical situation, that is, one in which op- posing discourses are brought forth in a way that invites mutual criticism and facil- itates a choice between them. Dialectic comes into play most clearly within insti- tutions that have been created for the spe- cific purpose of resolving contested claims and proposals, e.g. courts, legislatures and the journals and meetings of learned socie- ties. Within such controversial situations, logic enters at each moment when a partic- ular claim and its support are singled out for evaluation. Central to this entire proc- ess is rhetoric, that is, the creative use of language by human agents striving to find the "fitting words," to craft the discourse that makes sense of the problematic situa- tion in a way that withstands the criticism of opposing discourses, and satisfies a crit- ical audience, e.g. "a community of model interlocutors" (Blair & Johnson, 1987). Rhetorical art drives the creative struggle to find ameliorating language; logic pro- vides the critical standards by which to in- sure cogency; and dialectic frames the entire enterprise with principles intended to promote cooperative, comprehensive, 2 Joseph W. Wenzel candid, and critical interaction (Wenzel, 1990). No one of the controversial arts, alone, is sufficient for the production of informed understanding or sound decisions. Rather, human judgment is an accomplishment that depends upon all three. Hence, a fully developed theory of argumentation re- quires a synthesis of principles, standards, insights and modes of understanding drawn from the perspectives of dialectic, logic and rhetoric. Now, the foregoing implicitly charac- terizes rhetoric as a practical art, as Aristo- tle described it, a trained capacity for producing forms and materials of proof ap- propriate to problematic questions. That conception of rhetoric is featured in the first essay in this issue. Thomas Conley lo- cates rhetoric as one of the arts of language central to education in the Western world for many centuries. He accounts for the trivialization of some aspects of that edu- cational tradition, but argues that rhetoric-even in apparently trivial exer- cises such as declamation-retained its vitality and utility because it never lost touch with the robust idea of controversia. The contemporary study of rhetoric has expanded beyond its original formula- tion as the art of the speaker, however. It now embraces sophisticated methods of analysis and criticism that have much to teach us about how arguments are fash- ioned in ordinary (and not-so-ordinary) language, and how cognitive changes are effected by discourse. Michael Weiler's es- say demonstrates this potential as he ex- plores the rhetorical character of ideology. From a rhetorical point of view, ideology can be understood as a distinct species of argumentation that functions to legitimize the exercise of political power. As such, it challenges the rhetorical critic to uncover the partiality hidden behind its claims to universality. John Lucaites and Charles Taylor take up another important dimension of political rhetoric, centering on the concept of prudential judgment. Their exemplary study of debate in the U.S. Senate over authorization for the use of military force in the Persian Gulf helps to explain, on the one hand, how the particular decision was reached. But, more importantly, it demonstrates that the very grounds of decision-making-in this case, a particular conception of prudence-are often rhetorically constructed in the course of deliberation. G. Thomas Goodnight is also interest- ed in the crafting of reason through delib- erative rhetoric. In his contribution to this issue he blends the interests of informal 10- gicians and rhetoricans in an intriguing way. Starting with an apparently technical problem in logic, the choice of backing to authorize a warrant, he expands the hori- zon to examine "legitimation controver- sies" which emerge when consensus about the grounding of judgment is challenged. His case study demonstrates the possible expansion of the domain of inquiry for informal reasoning. In the essay rounding out this issue, Dilip Gaonkar reflects on the implications of certain terms of recent currency: "the re- vival of rhetoric," "the new rhetoric," and "the rhetorical tum." He locates those terms in recent intellectual movements, ex- plains how each one invokes a particular conception of rhetoric, and concludes by showing how the "rhetorical tum," in his words, "signifies a radical shift in the self understanding of rhetoric." It may be fair to say that the full implications of that tum for rhetoric's relation to argumentation have yet to be realized by most of us. Certainly this issue cannot tell infor- mal logicians everything they might want to know about rhetoric, but one hopes it makes a helpful start. In addition to the authors, who deserve the chief credit for producing this issue, there are others to thank. I am grateful to the reviewers for their careful reading and commentary on manuscripts: J. Robert Cox (University of North Carolina), Robert Hariman (Drake University) and Charles A. Willard (University of Louisville). I thank Tony Blair and Ralph Johnson for inviting me to undertake this project. And, there having been "many a slip twixt cup and Rhetoric and Argumentation 3 lip" since they made that invitation so long ago, I must publicly thank them, and Managing Editor Mark Letteri, for extraordinary patience with recalcitrant rhetoricians. References Bitzer, Lloyd E, 1968, "The Rhetorical Situation," Philosophy & Rhetoric, I, 1-14. Blair, J. Anthony & Ralph Johnson, 1987, "Argu- ment as Dialectical," Argumentation, 1,41-56. Wenzel, Joseph w., 1990, ''Three Perspectives on Argument: Rhetoric, Dialectic, Logic," in Perspectives on Argumentation, edited by Robert Trapp & Janice Schuetz (Prospect Heights, IL: Waveland Press), 9-26. JOSEPH W WENZEL DEPARTMENT OF SPEECH COMMUNICATION UNIVERSITY OF ILLINOIS 702 S. WRIGHT ST. URBANA. ILLINOIS 61801 0