conflicting pronouncements it hardly follows that p A, P is in fact true. The same con- sequence follows by elementary laws of prob- ability from taking "X (a generally veracious but imperfect source) maintains p, therefore p is highly probable" as a correct inference. 3 Thus Rescher has shown that for an essen- tially subject-based (for two sources X and Y, or greater than two) appeal to authority, the type of inference can be neither deduc- tive nor inductive. In essence, these dis- proofs reflect the conception that for mul- tiple authorities that are imperfect and may be expected to have conflicting pronounce- ments, deductive and inductive models of inference are "too perfect". Hamblin's and Salmon's conceptions of the ad verecundiam are too idealized to adequatiry represent the practice of appeals to imperfect authorities whose pronouncements may clash. But con- fronted by contradiction we mus~ not give up --even though deductive or inductive logics give no further guidance--but press on to resolve the contradiction by means of plausi- bility theory. Now that we have eliminated the deductive and inductive models, and identified plau~i­ ble inference as a preferable model for the type of argument exemplified by the ad verecundiam, it would seem the way is open to an analysis of this fallacy. And so in- deed it may be, but this is not a project we shall attempt here. Suffice it to say for the moment that as Rescher conceives it plausible inference is not subject-matter- sensitive, so at very least plausibility theory will have to be conjOined to a theory of the subject-matter content of propositions 4 in order to be adequate to the full ad verecundiam. These refinements aside how- ever, we are at least in the position now of being able to identify one noteworthily in- sidious form of the ad verecundiam. The fallacy we allude to occurs where an appeal to authority is construed so strongly, or such a lack of specification of its type of argument has transpired, that the argument is taken to have (a) deductive, or (b) in- ductive correctness. Yet if the appeal is ment to be taken--as it should be generally-- to a less than perfectly veracious authority, then its construal as (a> or (b) is falla- cious. The specific fallacy here lies not in the appeal to authority as such, but in the spurious escalation of the appeal towards a claim to a source of truth that is more perfect or infallible than a plausible argu- ment has any logical right to be. In short, this fallacy is to misidentify the type of argument. This particular error is of course not the only way in which an ap~eal to authority can go wrong, and elsewhere we have suggested that ad verecundiam is an umbrella concept for several specific pitfalls of argument from authorities. But this particular spe- cies of the ad verecundiam is an important one, we think, in teaching students how to confront and deal with the fallacies, be- cause it underscores the need to take into consideration identification of the type of 6 argument as a necessary skill of informal logic. The first step in attempting to adjudicate any allegation that a fallacy has been committed is to ask the question "What (exactly) is the argument?" Answering this question involves more than simply specifying a set of propositions--as in the approach of formal logic--it includes, among other tasks, specification of the type of argument that has been advanced. Notes lsee our article "Fallaciousness Without Invalidity?" Philosophy and Rhetoric, 9, 1976, 52-54, ana "Formal~gic ana the Logic of Argument" to be presented at the 6th International Congress of Logic, Methodoloqy and Philosophy of Science in Hannover, Germany, August, 1979. 2see our article "Argumentum Ad Verecundiam," "Philosophy and Rhetoric 7, 1974, 135-153. - , 3The proof, parallel to the one above, is given by Rescher (1976, p. 3). 4For such a theory, the reader should look ., to Douglas N. Walton 'Philosophical Basis of Relatedness Logic,' Philosophical Studies, to f appear. References C. L. Hamblin, Fallacies, London, Methuen, 1970. Nicholas Rescher, Plausible Reasoning, As sen/Amsterdam, Van Gorcum, 1976. Wesley Salmon, Logig, Englewood Cliffs N.J., Prentice-Hal~, ~ 63. ' discussi on notes A NOTE 'IN THE "SURPRISE TEST" PUZZLE Harry A. Nielsen (University of Windsor> pre he Fri bet sam Tha stu the Fri and die thl!l ext be ThE be oui fo: th4 hal Cl, SUl th. ar, thi It i that is evening dity su' bright went by surpris --Sorry you can That is imagin! thus ru puzzle our for time be the end before the tea quence her sur The test ele to neat class ~ does nc minutes student er came could 11 school. doesn't too muc prise j lapse c show a A schoolteacher announces to her class that there will be a surprise test during the followinq week. She specifies that by a "surprise test" she means one which no one could reasonably predict while walking to school. Immediately, one of her ~righter students claims that she has contradicted herself. He offers this argument: The surprise test could take place on Friday, for if there had been no test up until Friday, then from that fact and the knowledge that there will be a test any student could ~ point, [ a posit until 1 Witt if whai tent!al take he has lat lis rying 1 of asks, It jut )qic .oqy is look i of ~, to ,uen, predict while walking to school that he was going to be given the test on Friday. So the test must take place between Monday and Thursday. But the same argument works for Thursday. That is, on Thursday morning, any student could deduce from the facts that there can be no surprise test on Friday, and that there will be a test, and as it is Thursday the correct pre- diction is that the test will be given that day. Clearly the argument can be extended to show that the test cannot be given on Wednesday, Tuesday or Monday. The conclusion is that the test cannot be given at all. The teacher heard this objection out, and then gave the test on the following Tuesday, surprising, in the required sense, everyone. The puzzle here is to see what has gone wrong witH the argument. Clearly the teacher can give the surprise test. How rs-it the case, then, that an apparently impeccable argument can produce the conclusion that no surprise test is possible? ******************** It is odd to confront a piece of reasoning that is valid only on some particular Thursday evening or Friday morning, but this very od- dity suggests a key to the puzzle: time. The bright student in the story says, "If Thursday ~nt by, and still no test, it couldn't be a surprise on Friday, so we can scratch Friday." --Sorry, but Friday has this about it, that ~u can't scratch it for real until Thursday. That is, you can't scratch it for real by imaginin~ that Thursday's class has ended and ilius rullong Friday out. The reasoning in the puzzle derives its appearance of force from our forgetting that, for us humans, the whole time between the start of Monday's class and the end of Thursday's has to be lived through before' a student is in a position to downgrade the teacher's logic. It is within that se- quence of days that the teacher can bring off her surprise test. The time-range in which she can spring the test extends from the start of Monday's class to near the end of Thursday·s. As Thursday's class passes its halfway mark, the student does not know if she will give the test in the minutes remaining. Suppose she does; then the student will have no grievance, for the teach- L er came through with the test at a time he could not predict for certain on his way to school. But what can the student say if she doesn't give the test on Thursday? "You let too much time go by-- now the element of sur- prise is gone." This is hardly a lo~ical lapse on the teacher's part, though lot may show a bit of absent~indedness. The main point, however, is that her student is not in a position to make even that guarded judgment ootil the sands of Thursday's class run out. With these considerations in mind, I wonder if what we have here could be called an exis- tential paradox, in as much as the puzzle can take hold of the student only if he forgets a 7 certain temporal feature of his,.human exis .... tence, namely that he cannot' reason himself forward to the end of the week, and then work backwards through time, &ut has to exist through the intervening days one by one and wait to see what each day brings. conference repo rt 5 A PANEL ON INFORMAL LOGIC This Report was submitted &y Professor Samuel Fohr of the University of Pittsburgh at Bradford. A Panel on Informal Logic was presented a~ th7 Be~end Campus of Penn State Univer- s1ty 1~ Er1e, Pa: at the Spring meeting of the Tr1-State Ph110sophical Association on April 21, 1979. The Panel was organized and ch~ired.by William Rapaport of the State Un1vers1ty of New York, College of Fredonia The other participants were Samuel Fohr o~ • the Uni~ersity of Pittsburgh at Bradford,4 James L10tta of Lake Erie College, and Nelson Pole of Cleveland State University. ~amuel Fohr pointed out that informal log1c courses could help people to arrive at more true beliefs and fewer false beliefs But the value of such courses could be se;i- ously dimini~hed by how they were taught and the books wh17h were used. Philosophers have not been as r1gorous in their treatment of non-symbolic logic as they have been in their tre~tment of symbolic logic. Many writers of 10g1c ~ks have been either sloppy or in- correct 1n their definitions of basic terms such as "valid," "sound," "deductive argu- In7nt," aJ?-d ~inductive argument." Any way of d~stinguloshl.ng between deductive and illduc- tl.ve.arguments which is not based on the in- tentloons of the person putting forward the argument is faulty. The word "fallacy" is use~ very 100s71y by many philosophers. ~trl.ctly spea~1ng, a fallacy is an error in lonference.or l.n drawing a conclusion from so~ preml.ses. Yet philosophers have tended to lodentify assertions they take to be false as fa~lacies. ?n7 ref7rs to the fallacy of equat1ng determl.n1sm wloth fatalism, another to the fallacy of taking the rightness or wro~qness of actions to be related to the mot~ves for which they are done. Writers of ~og1c.bO?ks ha~e gone far beyond this in 1d7ntlofY1ng th1ngs as fallacies. Among other th1~gs the following have been identified in 10g1c ~ooks as fallacies: questionable clai~ (pract1cally every claim is), emotionally charged language, suppressed evidenc~, dog-