i:ic skills associated with informal logic. ':'he test 'lie are employing is the Natson- Glaser Critical Thinking Appraisal. l It is being given in one version as a 'pre-test' at the beginning of the course and as a '~ost-test' at the end. The difference in student performance on these two versio~s will provide some measure of the effect~ve­ ness of the course in meeting its goals. (We are planning to establish a control group ~f students who will take the test, but who w~ll not be taking the course, as a way of making this a more accurate measure.) The data collected should be very helpful in per- suading our more empirically minded col- leagues of the effectiveness of this informal logic course. Additionally, it will provide valuable information to both the instructors and students. Informal logic will also have application in the Integrative Component of our new gen- eral education program. In terms of t~e un- derstanding of 'integration',here (obv~ously there are many complex issues in this approach to learning and education) our program inter- prets the concept as a process concept going well beyond the idea of mere 'relatedness' which sometimes characterize attempts at in- tegrative learning. In order to underscore this distinction, the program directs faculty who wish to teach courses in this component to specify the 'mechanism' of integratio~ to be employed. The philosophy faculty bel~eve that informal logic can serve admirably as just such a mechanism and that it can be employed for that purpose in a very wide variety of academic contexts. To give but one example: A program now being prepared for this component by Dr. Charles Krecz of our department, will be concerned with reli- gion. It will involve a course in each of: the ohilosophy of religion, the sociology of religion and an anthropology course in prim- itive religion, as well as an informal logic course which will concentrate on methodology, structure of exposition, analysis of types of reasoning, etc. of each particular disci- pline's approach to the study of religion as well as analYsis of reasoning in religion drawing from-the data provided-Sy the materi- al in the other courses. 'Jther areas in -.. ;hich infor:::al l::>gic can serve as the mec::'aniSr:! of integration ::light incl'lde "technology and ·1a1:.:es," "the a:rts ~:'ld er:."Ti=onment" and so .:)n. In ':act c?le pos- sibilities are about as great as the imagina- tion and interest of facultv and st:.:dents. Of course such an approach ~as the further advantage for those interested in informal logic of exposing them to a variety of dif- ferent areas where the special characteris- tics of reasoning in those areas can be analyzed. Such contact should help maintain vigor and 'freshness' in informal logic. Obviously many campuses will not be able to move in the precise directions we have. How- ever, I hope I have illustrated the fruitful- ness of looking for ways in which interest in informal logic can be pursued in the context of the debate on general education. 10 critical reviews CHALLENGE &RESPCNSE Carl Wellman Trudy Govier Trent University This book was ~ublished in 1971. It has not received very much attention from philosophers, possibly because Rawls' Theory of Justice, published almos~ at the same t~me, preoccupied many of these interested in moral philosophy, Challenge and Response deserves more attention ::nan it has rece~ 'led, I think, and it certain- ly merits careful study by those interested i~ in:::Qrmal loaic. ;.;ellman sets OUt to answer the meta-ethical question 'how can moral judg- ments be justified?', but befQ:re approaching that question, raises the prior one: 'what is justification?' The first hal::: of ~is book is devoted to answering this general question, and, as such, contains much which is relevant to theorists of argument. After some one hundred and thirty pages of close argument, Wellmann arrives at his view of what justification amounts to: In my view justification is to be understood essentially as a process of responding to challenges made. It may be observed and described as a psychological struggle in which one person tries to force another to back down, or one person struggles to come to terms with his own doubts and con- flicting convictions. But it is more than a psychological struggle because at its core are certain critical claims to truth, validity, to be upsetting, to be reassuring, an~ to be adequate. Therefore the actual outcome of any particular psychological struggle never settles once and for all the issues being fought over in the process of justification. It is this peculiar ambivalence of justification that enables what we actually do in discussion and thinking to serve as a test of critical ideals like truth, validity, and being justified. (pages 132-3) Much justification (though not all, in wellw'l man's view) proceeds by argument. Wellman has some novel and interesting things to say about, arguments and arguing, and it is to these that I I'll devote most of my attention here. He I maintains that there are legitimate arguments 'I which are neither inductive nor deductive (he ! naml endl finl the disl and misl cam F: cone def: so \ ask the! tha1 dedI posj and defj trac His is n In t, whic. prob be e, judgl it i] or wi Ofte] GalbI form to it argun makes las not :ophers, :e, :Cupied :ophy. :ention !rtain- :ted i:l .wer . judg- thing rhat is look is .on, .evant ~s of view :t :k ~e 1- :e Ie lims :ess Lar lssion (, 1 Well- nan has ~ about se that He Ill\lents lTe (he names them 'conductive'); redefines "valid"; endorses the notion of nonformal validity; de- fines "induction" in an original way; relates the notion of burden of proof to old-fashioned discussions of rules for directing the mind; and takes on the hoary problem of missing pre- mises. Obviously this is a rich source; I cannot discuss all these topics here. First of all: deductive, inductive, and conductive. As Perry Weddle has argued l , definitions of "inductive" and "deductive" are so unsatisfactory that it seems premature to ask whether all arguments fall into one of these two categories. Anyone who tells us that there are arguments which are not either deductive or inductive had better clarify his position by explaining what he takes inductive and deductive arguments to be. Wellman's definition of deductive argument is fairly traditional: Deduction is that form of reasoning in which the claim is made that the conclusion follows necessarily from the premises. If it is possible for the premises to be true and the con- clusion false, then the argument is invalid; if the truth of the premises is a sufficient condition for the truth of the conclusion, then the argument is valid. (page 4) [my emphasis] His definition of inductive argument, however, is not. By "induction" I mean that sort of reasoning by which a hypothesis is confirmed or disconfirmed by estab- lishing the truth or falsity of its implications. To show that the con- sequences of some hypothesis are true is to provide evidence for its accep- tance; to show that one or more of its consequences are false is to refute it. It is this sort of reasoning, so important to science, to which I refer by the word "in- duction". (page 33)2 In the definition of deduction, the phrase "in which the claim is made" will give rise to problems. For typically, that 'claim' will not be explicitly expressed, and we will have to judge whether the premises are supposed to make it impossible for the conclusion to be false, or whether some looser connection is intended. Often this will be difficult. Consider: It is the singular feature of such ethnic explanation (of poverty) that it is all but exclusively con- fined to conversation. The repu- table scholar unhesitantly adverts to it in casual interchange but rarely if ever puts it in his books or even his lectures. What is wholly plausible in conversation is wholly impermissable in print There is obviously something odd' about an explanation of poverty and well-being that must be so discreetly handled. (from Galbraith, The Nature of Mass Poverty, pages 14-15) Galbraith is arguing from the absence of this form of explanation in print and in lectures to its being an odd explanation. Does his argument 'involve the claim' that the ~remise makes it impossible for the conclusion' to be 11 false? It's hard to know what to say in re- sponse to this question. The same situation arises with: • • • the combination of science and intellectual history is an unusual one. Initially it may therefore seem incongruous. But there can be no intrinsic incongruity. Scientific concepts are ideas and as such they are the subject of intellectual history. (from T. S. Kuhn, The Copernican Revolution, page vii.) Discriminating deductive arguments from others on the basis of what connective claim 'is made' isn't easy, and here Wellman shares difficul- ties with logical tradition. Standard textbook accounts define deduction as Wellman did, and then go on to define in- ductive arguments as those which 'involve' or 'make' the lesser claim that premises only make the conclusion more likely or probable. In these accounts, the full weight of the in- ductive/deductive distinction falls on the matter of the claim made (implicitly) in the argument. Also the inductive category looks like a bit of a grab-bag; inductive arguments are just all those arguments which aren't de- ductive. In view of these facts, Wellman's rather different account of induction is worth studying. Inductive arguments, for Wellman, will be those arguments for or against hypotheses, from the confirmation or discomfirmation of those hypotheses in specific instances. Thus, 'these 100 crows are black, so all crows are black' would qualify as an inductive argument. Also, as Wellman points out, scientific rea- soning is frequently inductive in his sense; particular observations and experiments are brought to bear on more general hypotheses. Induction in some sense is still widely thought to be the method of science, and most inductive logics deal exclusively with sci- entific confirmation and disconfirmation. Where Wellman's definition starts to have non- traditional consequences is in its permission of a priori induction 3 . Reasoning for or against general ethical principles on the basis of conclusions about specific instances would count as induction. If we were to argue, contra Kant, that lying is not always wrong, because it would be permissible to lie in order to save a life, we would be using an in- ductive argument, in Wellman's sense of "in- duction" • Ethical theories, just like scientific ones, have specific consequences for particular cases. If these con- sequences are found to be true, this confirms the theories. If they are found to be false, the theories are disconfirmed. However differently the consequences may be found to be true or false, the truth or falsity that is found has the same logical relation to the hypothesis of which it is a consequence. Therefore, inductive reasoning has its place in ethics just as it has in science. The logic of science is also the logic of ethics; the confirmation and disconfirmation of hypotheses is common ground. (page 44) On the other hand, some arguments which tra- dition would call inductive do not seem to be inductive by Wellman's definition. Consider: I've been a Supreme Court justice for 25 years, and never have I known any Supreme Court justice to divulge to a journalist the vote on any court case, If this journalist says that a justice told him there was a 5~4 split on the Stephen Truscott case, he must be lying, 4 This argument is of the type 'never in my ex- perience, X; therefore not X in this case', It is much like 'never has the sun failed to rise, so it will surely rise tomorrow', and would surely count as inductive according to logical tradition. Yet the argument appears not to be inductive in Wellman's sense, for it applies a general hypothesis to a particular case, rather than moving from a case or cases to a hypothesis, I shall not pursue this matter' further, for, given the problems which have been found to arise in standard accounts of inductive and deductive arguments it does not count as much of a criticism of Wellman's distinction to point out that his rather novel definition of "induction" fails to include all the old examples as inductive. His definition pre- serves a link between induction and science, and between the relation between confirmed/ 1isconfir~ed p3rticular judgments ar.d a gen- eral hypothesis. However, it allows for non- empirical induction and may fail to classify some probabilistic arguments as inductive, Also, it does not distinguish inductive from deductive arguments in such a way as to make the distinction one which is b~ definition exhaustive. This last innovat~on str~kes me as an advantage, but others may not see the matter this way. On the standard notion of inductive argu- ments as all those based on anyth~ng less than logical entailment as a connection be- tween premises and conclusion, the argument 'you should meet me at 2:00 because you prom- ised to do so' would be inductive. 5 Yet such an argument seems to have nothing of impor- tance in common with 'these observed crows were all black; so all crows are black'. The moral argument is of the type Wellman has termed 'conductive'. The conductive argument, he says: derives its conclusion from a variety of premises each of which has some independent relevance. TypicaIIY; although by no means always, several reasons are given in such arguments; and in those cases where a single reason is advanced, there are others which might have been given as well. Since what is characteristic of this sort of reasoning is the leading to- gether of various considerations, it seems appropriate to label it "con- duction". (page 52) [my emphasis) This type of reasoning has also been noticed by !1ichael Scriven and Stephen Thomas who, like Wellman, emphasize that premises bear separatel1 on the conclusion in such a way that the alsity of one does not affect the pertinence of others. 6 12 In conductive arguments, typically several factors relevant to the conclusion are cited in the premises, and the conclusion is then drawn, Examples: 1. "You ought to take your son to the movie because you promised to do so, it is a good movie, and you have nothing better to do this afternoon." (Wellman, page 56) 2. "This is not a good book because it fails to hold one's interest, is full of vague descriptions, and has a very implausible plot." (Wellman, page 56) 3. "Hume is not a sceptic, for although he argues that our basic beliefs are not rationally justified, he rails against classical sceptics, and maintains that we are as much determined to believe as we are to think and feel." (My example) 4. "We can be proud that America has turned the corner on the depression of the last few years. At last the many indexes of recovery are showing optimistic readings. The rate of inflation has slowed, unemployment has more or less stabilized, inventories are beginning to drop, advance orders are starting to pick up, and--the best news of all-the average income figures are showing a gain. The doomsayers have been discomfited, and the free enterprise system once more vindi- cated," (Scriven, Reasoning, page 78) Wellman has a tendency to concentrate on ex- amples which he has contrived and which are solely from the domain of moral arguments. In doing this, I think he does his own case an injustice, and it is for this reason that I've included other examples above. Wellman wishes to make the case that conductive argu- ments are legitimate arguments which can serve to justify claims, and that where these arguments are used in support of moral judg- ments, they deserve to be taken seriously as rational instruments. Since his ultimate interest is in meta-ethics, it is natural for him to concentrate on moral arguments; how- ever, he would make a more solid case by showing that conductive reasoning and con- ductive arguments are widely used, and in- sisting that they are as legitimate in moral reasoning as elsewhere.' The conductive argument is one in which the premise, or premises, are each separately rel- evant to the conclusion, though none is suf- ficient to show its truth. In example (2) above, three quite separate reasons are given for thinking a book to be a poor one, Each aspect cited would be such as to make the book poor (i.e. relevant to thinking it poor), even in the absence of the other two, The three cumulate, so that good reason is given to think the book a poor one. In ex- ample (3), one factor is cited which would count towards Hume being a sceptic, and two others which would count against that. The latter two are supposed to outweigh the first one so that the argument overall presents good reason to believe that Hume is not a sceptic, The key notion for the conductive argument seems to be that of relevance, that kind of relevance which is less than full entailment. In support of a conclusion many relevant factors can be brought forward, some counti Much r gether clusio: conduc such r, involvi factor of the. Therl real 1. help tl which, and fUI appliel tive a: believi has, tl imposs. mentw: argumel such s' more rl of thil argumeJ inclin, out th, procee, each pi suppos, critic, would! ductivE l'1ell: conten1 anythil ture wI ments. (by 'tl not fOI of the --that demons1 rules c varioul formal by, no! validi1 SUI dOE an~ fOI Hi: bel sy! val rul hi~ so~ ree of ver loe titi But qUE lo~ son the val of unj This pc theoris eral ited nen it '1 an, t 1 of '1h he t st at we we of 'I mistic s g to pick erage The d the di- l ex- tre s. !se ~hat Lman lrgu- ~hese Idg- r as L for )w- 1- 1- )ral 1 the r rel- luf- n leo ,e it :wo. Ls Ld :wo 1he :irst I Lve :hat L ~any some counting for it, others counting against it. Much reasoning involves bringing these to- gether and 'weighing' them to see which con- clusion it is most reasonable to accept. A conductive argument may be the product of such reasoning; this kind of argument will involve the specification of several such factors and adduce a conclusion on the basis of their cumulative force. S There are many conductive arguments among real life arguments. Their prevalence may help to explain several student assumptions which appeared to me at first to be peculiar and funny, and which are inappropriate as applied to classically deductive and induc- tive arguments. Students, I've found, often believe that the more premises an argument has, the better it is. They find it almost impossible to believe, often, that an argu- ment with only one premise could be a good argument. (If an argument has more premises, such students will insist, then it offers more reasons for its conclusion.) This line of thinking is appropriate for conductive arguments. Also, some students show a strong inclination to analyze arguments by setting out the premises and the conclusion and then proceeding to criticize connections as though each premise, separately considered, was supposed to lead to the conclusion. This critical strategy is often wholly wrong, but would be more or less appropriate for con- ductive arguments. l-1ellman admits that since relevance is a content-dependent notion, there is little, if anything, of a formal or even a general na- ture which can be said about conductive argu- ments. Thev exist and they may be assessed (by 'thinking them through again'), though not formally. Wellman has a close discussion of the view--fairly common among philosophers --that validity must be formal and must be demonstrable by the application of formal rules of inference. He rejects this view for various reasons, most importantly because formal rules must derive from and be testable ~y, nonformal, extra-systematic judgments of validity. surely the existence of valid reasoning does not presuppose the existence of any such calculus of derivation rules, for the inferences formalized by Hilbert and Ackerman, say, were valid before they invented their logical system just as the syllogism was valid long before Aristotle. As a rule, the logician tries to construct his calculus so that it will reflect some sort of reasoning that is recognized to be valid independently of his system. To be sure, the in- ventive logician can think up queer logics which suggest new, and some- times strange, ways of reasoning. But if these queer logics become too queer, they are no longer considered logics, but only symbolic games of some similar sort. This indicates that even here, our standards of validity are outside of and independent of the derivation rules in any uninterpreted calculus. (page 75)9 This point, strongly emphasized by such theorists of logic as Arthur Pap and Susan 13 Haack, seems to me to be entirely correct. Connections which exist between premises and conclusions are not the products of logical systems, but rather are presupposed by those systems. Validity is not by definition for- mal validity; connections need not be formal- ly articulable in order to exist. There is room, then, for the idea of a legitimate connection between the premises and con- clusion of conductive arguments, even though this connection is most unlikely to be for- mally capturable. Though it may be true, as Wellman anticipates it will be, that there is little of a systematic nature which can be said about conductive arguments, that is no reason to deny their existence, or to deny them any sort of validity. I"ellman's innovation on 'inductive I and his defense of the notion of conductive argument strike me as the most significant aspects of his book for those interested in informal logic and, accordingly, I have described these at some length. There is much else that is pertinent and for other topics I shall be considerably more brief. There is the matter of validity. \'l'ellman eventually develops an umbrella notion of validity which applies to arguments of all types: If it is granted that inductive and conductive arguments cannot be re- duced to deductive form and that they are subject to logical criticism, then it must be admitted that there is a genuine sense in which thes7 arguments are valid or invalid. By log~cal criticism I mean the judgment of correct- ness or incorrectness as inferences, as drawing a conclusion from one or more premises, quite apart from a~y question of the truth of the prem~ses. Once deductivism is abandoned, the need for this broader conception of validity becomes apparent. (page 240) His proposal for 'valid' is: to ~ay.that an argument is valid is to say that ~t ~s per- suasive after indefinite criticism for all those who think in the normal way. 'Indefi- nite' criticism is required so that the notion of validity is not purely descriptive; 'the normal way' so that the failure of an argu- ment to convince lunatics does not brand it invalid. Thinking in the normal way means "having a tendency to be persuaded by some sort of arguments and not by other sorts • • • most men are similarly persuaded or unpersuaded". There seem to be dangers of circularity here. Wellman also seems to be in some trouble with the question of whether an argument with false or unwarranted premises can be valid in his sense--can it be persuasive? What are the conditions of persuading? That the person to be persuaded accepts or has the premises of the argument, that he rejects or doubts it conclusion, and that he pays attention to or thinking through the argument. • . • . . to say that an argument is persuasive is to say that is usually persuades one who accepts or has its premises, who rejected or doubted its conclusion just before being subjected to the argument, and who thinks through the argument. (page 91) What about one who rejects the premises of an argument? Can the argument be persuasive to him? It must be found 'persuasive after in- definite criticism' to qualify as valid in the new sense. Yet since the account of per- suasiveness is in terms of one who accepts the premises, it is hard to see how Wellman can achieve what he wants, namely an umbrella way of speaking of the connection between premises and conclusions which is independent of considerations of the truth or falsity of premises. He tries to fix the account, saying: a pe:son who does not accept the prem~ses of a given argument can still imagine what it would be like to accept them and make a good guess as to whether they would then persuade one of the conclusion. (page 109) I am not sure this is good enough. A more fundamental question is whether such an umbrella notion of validity, involving as it does a fundamental departure from tradi- tion in logic, is desirable. S. N. Thomas, in his text, takes the position that 'valid- ity' applies to arguments of all types and is a matter of degree. So Wellman isn't the only one suggesting radical changes. Person- ally I'm not sure I favor innovations here, as deductive validity is an established and relatively clear concept. Perhaps some new term could be adopted to handle the 'umbrella' aspect, and then deductive validity would be a species of this connectedness of premises and conclusion. Wellman points out that the ordinary language use of 'valid' is broader than the logicians', and this seems to be true--however the ordinary language use is so broad as to move towards considerations of truth as well. (E.g. "that's a valid point you made .•. ") Another key topic discussed by Wellman is the matter of missing premises. This problem is not discussed in any general way; however Wellman becomes involved in it when introduc- ing his notion of a conductive argument. He is aware that, given a move from a particular premise to a particular conclusion, many will insist that the argument must be enthymematic, so that there is a general premise missing. Descartes ran into this problem when some critics insisted that 'I think therefore I am' was really a syllogism requiring as a missing premise 'everything that thinks exists.'lO Descartes denied it; Wellman does too. Consider the simple conductive argument: 'you should return the book, because you promised you would do so'. Someone might in- sist that this argument is enthymematic, requiring a missing premise--e.g. 'People should do everything they promise to do'. Such insistence turns conductive arguments into deductive ones and makes reasoning about particular instances dependent upon the ac- ceptance of general principles. Wellman strongly resists the move, saying that the universal premise inserted is almost always false, or at any rate less plausible than the particular inference which the arguer wants 14 to draw, and that it is not fair interpreta- tion to saddle people with general claims when all they have set out to do is to draw particular inferences. We often want to do this, but perhaps this is only .because we are so strongly inclined, by training, to look at arguments through deductivist goggles. Turning conductive arguments into deductive ones grossly distorts their meaning and structure, for deductive arguments are sup- posed to be conclusive. A conductive argu- ment, citing three factors relevant to the establishment of a conclusion, would turn in- to three deductive arguments, each of which, as conclusive, would render the other two entirely redundant. This point seems to me to be an important one, and one which would apply to much philosophical argumentation. (If proponents of (e.g.) the mind/brain identity theory really think that their argu- ments for the theory are deductive, why would they need more than one?ll) A fault which runs throughout Wellman's ac- count is the failure to distinguish between reasoning and arguments. Despite his general carefulness, Nellman seems to make this re- lationship too close, identifying reasoning with putting forward or following through one or more arguments. But there is the process of argument construction, where one sifts through evidence, tries to determine what is relevant and what isn't •.. and all of this, which precedes the expression of an argument, is on most accounts recognized as reasoning. I don't think there is any cru- cial problem here, and I've simply tried to use 'araument' in contexts where Wellman speaks of reasoning, but is pretty clearly dealing with the arguments that are the product of reasoning. The point is of some importance, however, for critics might be tempted to allow that such reasoning is con- ductive, but deny that there is such a thing as conductive argument. I don't think this criticism is very plausible, in the light of the many examples of conductive arguments which can easily be found in natural language. The book covers much which I've not dis- cussed. I shall finish where I began, by urging others interested in informal logic to study this rich source, 1. 2. 3. Footnotes In the last issue of Informal Logic ~­ letter, (November, 1979). This passage exemplified Wellman's ten- dency to very closely relate reasoning and argument. As he is clearly talking about kinds of argument in this context, I.ve dealt with these and not with the question (much broader) of what different kinds of reasoning there might be. There is a connection here with the con- cept of reflective equilibrium, made fashionable by Rawls. Many moral philos- ophers now accept what Wellman refers to as induction in morals, though they would add that views on particular cases may .also be revised by theoretical principles which are in some sense or other well- established. The analogy which Wellman wishes to draw between ethical and sci- entific reasoning also seems to be quite a widely accepted one in current moral 4. 5. 6. 7. 8. 9. 10. 11. ph la po Ad Gl Ja Th mi ttl th Se Th La He ti in is se pl en ho cr (I ha wo gu Co Vi Es We of on se bo an we Co Ch Se an th qu po of Ha re to Ro Co an preta- ims draw to do we are look at ductive d sup- argu- the urn in- "hich, two to me "ould ion. 11 r argu- '{ would ~'s ac- ~ween ~eneral s re- )ning :2! one rocess Ets lat is )f an !d as cru- !d to in lrly some be I con- thing this ,ht of Its mguage. lis- by )gic : News- ten- ~ing Lking ltext, the fferent e con- ie ~hilos­ ers to '{ would may I1ciples e11- llman sci- quite oral philosophy. (Note: this is not a fal- lacious appeal to authority, but merely a point of information!) 4. Adapted from an argument in the Toronto Globe and Mail, appearing sometime in JaiiiJarY";-l9'8'Q, 5. That is, unless we insist on adding as a missing premise, 'You should do every.,. thing you promise to do', in which case the arqument is deductive. 6. See Scriven, Reasoning, pages 78-81, and Thomas, Practical Reasoning in Natural Language, pages 37-40. 7. He does note that the concept of conduc- tive argument has wider application, say- ing, "~'Jherever some descriptive predicate is ascribed on the basis of a family re- semblance, conductive reasoning takes place." (page 54). But he does not make enough of this point, nor does he tell us how many descriptive predicates ~ as- cribed on the basis of family resemblance. (If most are, as Wittgenstein seems to have thought, then conductive reasoning would be very common, and conductive ar- guments an extremely important type. Compare D. C. Yalden-Thomson, "The Virginia Lectures", in Wisdom: Twelve Essays, edited by Renford Bambrough.) 8. Wellman specifies three different patterns of conductive argument; one where only one relevant factor is adduced; one where several are adduced; and a third where both 'pro' and 'con' factors are adduced, and the claim is made that the former out- weigh the latter. 9. Compare Susan Haack, Philosophy of Logics, Chapter II. 10. See Objections to the Meditations (II), and Descartes' reply, in which he insists that a general proposition is not re- quired and that, indeed, "general pro- positions are formed out of the knowledge of particulars" (page 38, Volume II, in Haldane and Ross edition.) A similar response is made by Descartes in a letter to Clerselier (page 127 in Haldane and Ross, II.) 11. Compare Francis Dauer, "The Diagnosis of an Argument", r1etaphilosophy, 1974. 15 UI\EJERS I ~CING SCIENTIFIC REASONING Ronald N. Giere William Berriman University of Regina Suppose one could gather together about a hundred university professors of philosophy and suppose furthermore that they represented a fair sample of today's philosophers with respect to contemporary thinking about the teaching of logic and philosophy. To these people one now reads the first four para- graphs of Giere's Preface. By the end of the reading the philosophers would have become decisively divided on their attitudes to the book. Giere speaks of "new courses in 'applied philosophy''', of the "students' demand for 'relevance'" and of his reluctant rejection of his idea of subtitling the book "A Consumer's Guide to Scientific Method". He claims that students can become intelligent consumers of scientific informa- tion not by learn~ng science (or in his words "how to be scientists") but by learning merely how to read and interpret reports of scientific findings, espec~ally reports that appear in the popular magazines, newspapers, and even supermarket tabloids. Some of our philosophers would denounce the book as "light weight", "not academically respectable" and condemn the book outright. The others would find that the book arouses their interest. This aroused interest may have three (possibly overlapping) sources: a) an awareness of the possibility that the book may form the basis of an attractive (pop?) class. b) On the basis of one's know- ledge of today's students plus the nature of many media reports one may have concluded i) that most people know very little about science but that ii) they are prepared to believe the most outrageous stories provided these are in the realm of "science". Finally c) Giere's book appears to offer the oppor- tunity to extend one's work in informal logic into the area of the logic of science, and reports about science in the media. A cursory glance through the book reveals material that should arouse student interest. Giere's chapters deal with Haley's long- range forecast of the appearance of his comet, the World II model which uses a computer to predict disaster for mankind by the year 2100 unless great changes are made in the world socio-economic system by 1985. Additional (to informal logic) fallacies such as Vague Predictions (or the Delphi Fallacy), The Jean Dixon Fallacy (multiple predictions),