Title of the Paper [16 point font]
Emotions in Argumentative Narration. The
Case of the Charlie Hebdo Attack
SARA CIGADA
Department of Linguistic Sciences and Foreign Literatures
Università Cattolica del Sacro Cuore
Largo Gemelli 1
20123 Milan
Italy
sara.cigada@unicatt.it
Abstract: This paper studies emo-
tional inferencing triggered by emo-
tion terms, using Pragma-Dialectics
and the Argumentum Model of
Topics. The corpus, in French, is an
excerpt of a video-recorded testimony
in which a middle school teacher
evokes her experience of being in
class the day after the Charlie Hebdo
attack, thus presenting a case of
argumentation in context. The analy-
sis focuses on the argumentative
structure and on the rhetorical strate-
gies that trigger emotional inferenc-
ing. The emotional inferencing
derives from a Locus of Ontological
Implication, which links a situation
and an emotion (and vice-versa),
while the culture-bound elements tend
to be part of the endoxon.
Résumé: L’article étudie l’inférence
déclenchée par l’usage de termes
d’émotion, en utilisant comme mo-
dèle de référence la Pragma-
dialectique et le Modèle AMT (Ar-
gumentum Model of Topics). Le
corpus est constitué par
l’enregistrement vidéo d’une ensei-
gnante de collège dans la banlieue
parisienne, qui évoque son expérience
en classe le jour d’après l’attentat à
Charlie Hebdo en janvier 2015. Nous
avons analysé ce corpus en tant
qu’exemple d’argumentation en
contexte, en en considérant la struc-
ture inférencielle et les stratégies
rhétoriques qui déclenchent
l’émotion. L’émotion dérive d’un
Topos de l’Implication Ontologique,
qui relie une situation à une émotion
(et vice-versa), tandis que les élé-
ments culturels ont tendance à appa-
raître dans la fonction d’Endoxon.
Keywords: Argumentum Model of Topics, emotional inferencing, emotion
lexicon, French discourse, ontological implication, rhetorical strategies, Rodol-
phus Agricola
mailto:sara.cigada@unicatt.it
402 Cigada
© Sara Cigada. Informal Logic, Vol. 39, No. 4 (2019), pp. 401–431
1. Introduction
This paper explores the role played by emotions in knowledge-
oriented argumentation. It aims to fill a knowledge gap concerning
the function of emotions as an argumentative hint and an inferen-
tial trigger.
My analysis stems from “emotion terms” (Plantin 2004, p. 269)
– in French, “termes d’émotion” (Plantin 1999 and 2011) – in an
argumentative narration (Olmos 2017; Thierry 2008). The Argu-
mentum Model of Topics (AMT) (Rigotti and Greco Morasso
2010) combined with Pragma-Dialectics (van Eemeren and
Grootendorst 2004) form the theoretical frame for this contribu-
tion. The choice is appropriate for the purposes of the analysis
because the AMT is particularly suited to the semantic analysis of
micro-excerpts in which linguistic structures displaying emotions
(more precisely lexicon in the case of emotion terms) convey
explicit and implicit information and work together with the other
linguistic structures to rationally support a standpoint (Palmieri
2014).
The corpus is an excerpt from a video-recorded testimony in
which a French middle school teacher, Martine, evokes her experi-
ence of being in class the day after the 2015 terror attack on the
offices of the Parisian magazine, Charlie Hebdo. Data are particu-
larly relevant for exploring emotions in knowledge-oriented argu-
mentation as they refer to unexpected tragic events arousing dis-
rupting, dysphoric emotions. It is worth highlighting that Mar-
tine’s discourse does not aim to move the audience, but rather to
share professional competence and experience about the manage-
ment of highly emotional situations in an educational context with
peers. In this paper, I am not referencing the opposition between
“emotive” and “emotional” (“die Emotive” and “die Aussagen”,
see Marty 1908, pp. 363-364 and passim, and Caffi 2007, p. 139,
177). In fact, as already pointed out by Plantin (2011, pp. 137-
142), we have too little linguistic evidence for this distinction.
Rather, I analyze linguistic and rhetorical structures related to
emotions insofar as they contribute to argumentative sense-effects.
Emotions in argumentative narration 403
© Sara Cigada. Informal Logic, Vol. 39, No. 4 (2019), pp. 401–431
Given this, I will use a nonspecific “emotional” as a version of
Plantin’s “émotionné.”
The AMT allows the analyst to show the different ways in
which emotion terms used in narration activate inferential struc-
tures (Ungerer 1997, “emotional inferencing”). In the current
paper, in the reconstruction of the so-called “Y structure,” emotion
terms appear, with different functions, both on the right side, i.e. in
the procedural-inferential component of the Y structure (maxim),
on the left side, i.e. in the material-contextual component (data),
and in the final conclusion. In any case, emotion terms convey
information that forms a coherent part of the discourse meaning.
Different communities described in narrative discourse may have
good reasons to react in emotionally different ways to the same,
unique event according to their personal and communal convic-
tions, depending on whether or not they share the endoxon. Alt-
hough based on current models (Plantin 2011; Micheli 2014) and
partly consistent with them, this description of emotions in argu-
mentation is much more precise and accords linguistic devices
more relevance. In fact, the reconstruction shows that co-occurring
linguistic structures (rhetorical strategies) take part in triggering
emotional inferencing.
Consistently with the models I refer to, I suggest that emotions
displayed in discourse should be described in a “reasonableness”
model in which rhetorical devices are accounted for by the same
method as the other components of discourse (Rigotti and Palmieri
2016; cf. Gobber 2019, p. 292).
2. Emotions in discourse and in argumentation: accounting for
linguistic data
2.1. The termes d’émotion
This paper considers a single layer of the complex phenomenon of
“emotion” in discourse, i.e. the presence of direct or indirect
“emotion terms,” as an important first step towards analyzing the
implicit emotional component in discourses that do not mention
emotions either directly or indirectly.
404 Cigada
© Sara Cigada. Informal Logic, Vol. 39, No. 4 (2019), pp. 401–431
I start by considering emotion terms. Firstly, emotion terms are
considered with the procedure identified by Plantin and further
applied and developed by Micheli. Plantin considers emotions to
be an intrinsic element of discourse, and Micheli (2010) agrees
that emotions should not be considered as external elements “help-
ing” to persuade, but that they should be analyzed as the actual
object of argumentative constructions. Plantin’s methodology is
lexicon-based and consists of identifying “emotion terms,” i.e.
words that mean emotions. In French, the language I focus on, as
in English, these words may be nouns, adjectives, verbs, adverbs
and interjections (e.g. joy, afraid, I hope, desperately, ouch!). The
emotion terms occur in an “emotion sentence,” which “asserts or
denies that a particular individual or experiencer is in the grip of a
particular emotion or psychological state” (Plantin 2004, p. 269;
“experiencer” for Fr. lieu psychologique) on the basis of a specific
“reason” (Fr. source) that emerges in discourse as the cause of that
emotion. This kind of analysis is useful to describe the layer of
emotions that are explicitly mentioned in the discourse. In addi-
tion, Plantin suggests analyzing “indirect” emotion terms (e.g. to
tremble, to wring one’s hands), i.e. words that indicate typical
physiological or attitudinal reactions associated with specific
emotions. The same should be done with idioms that indicate
emotions through metaphor (e.g. her heart was on fire; his eyes
betray darkening storm). As both indirect emotion terms and emo-
tion idioms are highly language- and culture-dependent, they are
often comprehensible within a specific community, but barely (or
not at all) outside of it. This is relevant for the intersubjective
understanding of emotion terms.
The addressee is able to correctly interpret and understand the
emotions attributed to individuals on the basis of the reasons told
in a discourse (obviously, the individual to whom an emotion is
attributed may be the speaker himself. See Plantin 2004, p. 269).
On this basis, a reader is able to understand the reasonableness of
emotions that are, for example, attributed to characters in a novel
or to real persons in a narrative excerpt, e.g. in a news story. The
reasons given to support the experiencer’s emotions are usually
rhetorically elaborated so as to create euphoric or dysphoric ef-
fects. The linguistic devices are described by Caffi and Janney
Emotions in argumentative narration 405
© Sara Cigada. Informal Logic, Vol. 39, No. 4 (2019), pp. 401–431
1994, Ungerer 1997, Plantin 1999 (cf. Cigada 2006), Micheli
2008, Plantin 2011, Cigada 2016. However interesting, these
descriptions do not explain the inferential procedure by which
emotion arising from “situational” elements is transferred to the
experiencers.
Indeed, the intersubjective understanding of emotion terms not
only requires a mutual linguistic interpretation of emotion terms
themselves1, but also a community dimension in the understanding
and evaluation of the situation. As Micheli (2008, pp. 144-148)
points out, the arguability of emotions is founded in their cognitive
reasons (“a set of beliefs and judgments regarding this situation”,
Micheli 2010, p. 7 and passim). It is relevant that the addressee
shares the evaluation backing the emotional interpretation of a
situation; however, doing so presupposes sharing both “contextual
beliefs and judgments” and a specific ontology that justifies the
inference from that situation to that emotion.
2.2. “Emotional inferencing” revisited using the Argumentum
Model of Topics
The situation that underlies and justifies an emotion is often re-
ferred to in terms of “topics” (Ungerer 1997; Micheli 2008; Plan-
tin 1999, 2011 and 2018), understood as a set of linguistic-
cognitive devices that are able to trigger “emotional inferencing”
(Ungerer 1997, p. 310) such as: discursive orientation to the inter-
locutors, proximity in time and space, quantity and analogy, which
are represented via the deictic system, quantification, evaluative
lexicon and so on. According to Ungerer, emotional inferencing in
news stories is based both on “principles” (including proximity,
animacy, rank and number) and on “strategies” (emotional evalua-
tion, intensity, negative content, homocentrism); principles and
strategies are expressed by respective “linguistic triggers/cues of
emotional inferencing” such as, for instance, deictic items, kinship
terms, “disaster vocabulary,” and so on (1997, pp. 310-319). Start-
ing from Grice’s maxims, Ungerer notes that “although the infer-
1 Plantin makes some almost implicit references to the fact that emotion terms in
French may be different to those in other languages but gives no systematic
account of this (Plantin 1999, p. 206 and p. 218 note 4).
406 Cigada
© Sara Cigada. Informal Logic, Vol. 39, No. 4 (2019), pp. 401–431
encing is carried out by the reader, the maxims must also be ob-
served by the author/editor to become effective.” He suggests that
these might be found in the practical guidelines given to the jour-
nalists or in manuals about “newsworthiness.” In fact, “the sub-
stance of the maxims, which are at the heart of the inferencing
process, must come from elsewhere” and not from the news stories
themselves (Ungerer 1997, p. 310).
I think that it is a worthwhile exercise to investigate “emotional
inferencing” using Pragma-Dialectics combined with the Argu-
ment Model of Topics, which is specifically designed to study
inference and inference triggers in argumentative discourse.
In Plantin’s model, emotions are identified and accounted for as
the standpoint of argumentative processes, as there are “good
reasons” that justify them and make them inter-subjectively under-
standable. In Ungerer’s model, a reader’s emotions are the result
of the content and linguistic features displayed by discourse. AMT
is useful in providing a more precise insight into the phenomenon.
3. Situated argumentation: Martine’s testimony in its context
The corpus is situated in many respects. As a discursive situation,
Martine’s testimony is an autobiographical narration, that is, a
kind of discourse in which emotions are likely to play an important
role. Some emotions are discursively auto-attributed; others are
attributed to other individuals. Her testimony takes places within
the wider context of an international life-long learning program
based in Italy and targeted at Lebanese French-speaking teach-
ers—S’éduquer pour éduquer (Educating oneself to educate)—
which took place from 2014 to 2017. I took part in the program as
a trainer during the first year and subsequently as the project lead-
er. Over the years, there was some turnover among participants
and some of us took on different roles, thus creating a complex
discourse community. The main group of stakeholders in the
project was constituted of approximately forty Lebanese teachers
from six French-speaking schools, both male and female, Maro-
nites, Orthodox and Muslims, teaching different subjects across
the full age range from kindergarten to high school (see Moeller
2010 on French-speaking schools in the context of Lebanese edu-
Emotions in argumentative narration 407
© Sara Cigada. Informal Logic, Vol. 39, No. 4 (2019), pp. 401–431
cation system). Even if the teachers have no voice in the corpus
analyzed in this paper, they were its main intended audience.
The witness and author of the discourse is Martine, a French
teacher in her forties. Her institute, a middle school situated in the
suburbs of Paris, draws pupils from different cultural, religious
and social backgrounds. As she had told me about her school on a
previous occasion, I specifically asked her to video-record her
testimony for the project. In the video, among other things, she
recalls her experience of being at school the day after the terror
attack on Charlie Hebdo2. In terms of the corpus, she is the speak-
er. Within the context of the whole project, this session aimed to
exchange ideas about the role of the teacher in potentially conflic-
tive situations, discussing whether and how they are called to
mediate between opposing positions and whether it is acceptable
for them to take part in the dialogue supporting one of the parts.
More generally, the issue at stake in the video is whether the
teacher should be neutral or play an active role in the transmission
of the tradition of their community3.
The other stakeholders were the Italian NGO that was hosting
the project, Fondazione AVSI, and its local partners (Caritas
Lebanon and La Femme Libanaise). I myself was part of a group
of about fifteen Italian trainers who evaluated and selected the
2 On 7th January 2015, two French terrorists attacked the offices of the satirical
weekly Charlie Hebdo in Paris killing twelve people. Al-Qaeda took responsi-
bility for the attack. France24 wrote the following about the attack: “Charlie
Hebdo’s caricatures frequently caused outrage by poking fun at religion and
politics. They were not popular with everyone, but in killing the country's most
famous cartoonists the gunmen had targeted a core French value: freedom of
speech” (http://webdoc.france24.com).
3 In recent years, Lebanon has experienced massive legal and, according to the
laws of the country, illegal immigration from Syria and other Middle East
countries, resulting in social tensions. The teachers from the South and East
regions of Lebanon had been reporting terror attacks in their towns or villages,
which caused a general state of insecurity. Schools were accepting thousands of
foreign pupils scarred by war traumas. Schools, traditionally open to all, were
facing internal and external pressures and reflecting violent socio-political
conflicts. The vast majority of pupils at the French-speaking Christian school
Saints-Cœurs in Baalbek, for example, were Muslim. For a description of the
six schools, their statistics, geographical situation, social and religious context,
see Marta Piccinelli 2019.
http://www.france24.com/en/20150107-charlie-hebdo-satirical-weekly-islamists-prophet-cartoons-deadly-attack
http://www.france24.com/en/20150107-charlie-hebdo-satirical-weekly-islamists-prophet-cartoons-deadly-attack
http://webdoc.france24.com/
408 Cigada
© Sara Cigada. Informal Logic, Vol. 39, No. 4 (2019), pp. 401–431
video, supported by two experts in international cooperation. One
of the most important reasons for this choice was the excerpt I am
studying in this paper: the autobiographical reference to an ex-
tremely violent situation at school and the deadly emotions con-
nected with it.
This description of the communicative context aims to explain
why the video-recording analyzed in this paper should be consid-
ered as dialogical in nature, even if it consists of a monologue: in
reality, it singles out one moment of a highly dialogical process.
The whole of the project, in fact, may be considered as the pro-
gressive construction of a communicative exchange between the
stakeholders (Palmieri and Mazzali-Lurati 2016) in which this
specific communicative act has been designed with the purpose of
activating dialogue between the participants. Martine shows a
strong commitment to argumentation and gives her speech a clear
argumentative structure. She starts by presenting her thesis about
the issue at stake, which is the meaning the schooling, and presents
her supporting arguments (minute 00’00’’ to 01’26’’). Then she
explains in more detail what she has in mind by means of two
autobiographical anecdotes, the second of which is the corpus4.
4. From the video recording to the transcriptions: methodolog-
ical questions and the analyst’s position
In terms of analytic methodology, the use of public video-
recording lowers the observer’s paradox. The video was recorded
with the purpose of being watched and discussed during that pro-
ject session so all the audiences mentioned in the previous para-
graph were considered and accounted for by the speaker. Martine
set no limits on the use of the video but requested to remain anon-
ymous.
4 This narrative excerpt is explicitly put forward as an “exemplum,” in the sense
described by Plantin (2018): “The illustrative example facilitates the under-
standing of a concept or a law, by introducing a (typical) instantiation of the
concept or the law: ‘A migratory bird is a bird that ... So the swallow...’ Moreo-
ver, if the example chosen is (presented as) typical of the phenomenon, it
renders the time-consuming and precarious work of checking a large number of
cases unnecessary” (p. 264, s.v. Example).
Emotions in argumentative narration 409
© Sara Cigada. Informal Logic, Vol. 39, No. 4 (2019), pp. 401–431
The setting is very simple. The speaker is sitting alone in a
classroom and addresses the video-camera. The whole recording is
07’18’’long. The analysis considers the section from 02’58’’ to
03’50,’’ which corresponds to the opening of the part in which
Martine recalls how the shooting at the Charlie Hebdo magazine
affected her pupils (02’58’’ to 06’25’’) ten months previously.
The transcription is a simple textual transcription as is usual in
Pragma-Dialectics and AMT. This kind of transcription fits well
with the purpose of the analysis, which focuses on the lexical and
semantic layer of discourse. However, the whole video has been
transcribed according to the French transcription conventions
ICOR. This transcription will be useful for further inquiries and
for crosschecking emotions in the spoken discourse.
As Plantin (2011) explains, when analyzing emotions in a
discourse, the analyst risks self-identification and self-confusion
with the addressee (pp. 194-196). Checking other discourses pro-
duced in the same context and community, in order to avoid the
risk of emic interpretation, is a key part of the methodology. This
kind of checking allows one to measure and define the different
emotional reactions to an argument for different individuals. It is
important but not sufficient to say that one needs to know “the set
of beliefs and judgments which are most commonly associated
with this particular emotion” (Micheli 2010, p. 7) because this
association changes from one time and one community to another,
so that the “good reasons” for an emotion are not absolute, but
should be considered in relation to a specific context. Lebanese
teachers, for instance, displayed empathy towards Martine’s feel-
ings about the Charlie Hebdo attack and appreciated the way she
managed the class. One of them, however, commented on Mar-
tine’s evident distress saying: “Elle est française, elle a pas
l’habitude” (She is French, she is not used to this). After which,
they went on discussing the best time and approach for talking to
pupils after terror attacks.5
5 The corpus also consists of the c. 2h30’ video-recording of the training session
with the Lebanese teachers based on the discussion of Martine’s testimony and
transcripts of interviews given to participants. Lebanese teachers aligned them-
selves with the “reasonableness” side (dialogue as a radical alternative to
violence) and, subsequently, with the teacher’s standpoint of “non-neutrality.”
410 Cigada
© Sara Cigada. Informal Logic, Vol. 39, No. 4 (2019), pp. 401–431
Here is the original French excerpt:
J'ai aussi beaucoup appris de ce qui s'est passé dans notre éta-
blissement l'an dernier à la suite des attentats du mois de janvier.
Comme il y avait un certain nombre de tensions entre communau-
tés dans notre établissement, et qu'un certain nombre d'élèves
s'était félicité des attentats à Charlie Hebdo, nous avions reçu
comme consigne de ne pas aborder le sujet en classe, de l'éviter le
plus possible ou de nous contenter tout au plus d'un rappel géné-
rique à la tolérance. Il se trouve que j'avais, cette année-là, une
classe très particulière, avec beaucoup d'élèves dans des situa-
tions extrêmement complexes d'un point de vue personnel,
quelques délinquants, et dans laquelle nous avions déjà été ame-
nés à intervenir pour des tensions entre communautés confession-
nelles. Donc, inutile de vous dire que la tension était grande ce
matin-là, le matin du 8 janvier avant mon entrée dans cette classe.
In the English version, the first introductory utterance has been put
in parenthesis as it is not considered in the analysis. Some foot-
notes and comments have been inserted, and the corpus has been
divided into three main utterances. The two emotion terms that
will be analyzed in this paper are marked in bold. In the analysis,
references to the French text will be made where necessary in
order to take into account the specific contribution of rhetorical
strategies (Jacobs 2006, p. 428). In fact, one cannot pretend that
translation preserves discursive sense effects:
[I also learnt a lot from what happened in our school last year
6
, follow-
ing the attack in January.]
(Utterance 1) As there was a certain number of tensions between
the communities in our school, and a certain number of pupils had
expressed appreciation for the attack on Charlie Hebdo, we had been
In fact, Martine’s discourse provides an example of the teacher’s role in conflict
mediation, not as an external director, but as an active promoter of the choice in
favor of dialogue (“conflict should not have the last word”, Greco 2017, p. 29)
and as a guarantor of space to think (Perret-Clermont 2005). In a sense, this is
not only the short-term premise of the project S’éduquer pour éduquer, and nor
it is just that of the school as an institution, but it is instead an essential basis of
human reasonable get-togetherness.
6 Martine refers to the past school year 2014-2015, while recording her video at
the beginning of the new school year 2015-2016.
Emotions in argumentative narration 411
© Sara Cigada. Informal Logic, Vol. 39, No. 4 (2019), pp. 401–431
given the order not to address the subject in the classroom, to avoid it
whenever possible or at the very most to confine our remarks to generic
reminders about tolerance.
(Utterance 2) That year, as it happened, I had a very particular kind
of class, where there were a lot of pupils with extremely complex per-
sonal circumstances, as well as some young offenders, and we had
already been forced to intervene due to tension between the different
religious communities.
(Utterance 3) So needless to say, tension was high on that morning,
the morning of January 8
th
, before I entered the class.
5. Two examples: emotion as an argument and as a standpoint
In the following sections I explain how, in the first example, an
emotion term plays the role of datum in Utterance 1 (5.1). I then
analyze emotion in the role of the conclusion in the same Utter-
ance (5.2) and in Utterance 3 (5.4).
5.1. Emotion as an argument: “had expressed appreciation”
(s’était félicité)
According to Plantin’s classification of emotion terms, se féliciter
should be considered an indirect term, i.e. a term representing the
typical7 expression of an emotion (joy, satisfaction). Utterance 1 is
characterized by a polyphonic phenomenon because the argumen-
tation is reported; Martine reports the reasoning of the school. That
is why this passage should be considered as a piece of argumenta-
tion and not as an explanation. As for argumentative structure, the
speaker explicitly (cf. connective as) reports the reasons behind
the order not to address the subject of the attacks. The issue at
stake is therefore: “What should we do to prevent more tensions
arising in our school, which are highly likely and have already
started to manifest themselves in the light of yesterday’s Charlie
Hebdo attack?” The issue might in principle admit alternative
solutions. In terms of a pragma-dialectical analytical overview
(van Eemeren 2018, pp. 90-91; van Eemeren and Grootendorst
7 As mentioned, “typicality” should be referred to a specific community, both
for the connection between an event and the emotional response to it and for the
way the emotional response is expressed.
412 Cigada
© Sara Cigada. Informal Logic, Vol. 39, No. 4 (2019), pp. 401–431
2004, pp. 120-121), the standpoint is formulated in the following
three passages and is supported by a coordinative argumentation
(i.e. the two arguments work together to support the standpoint):
1. [it is reasonable] to avoid the subject whenever possible or at the very
most to confine our remarks to generic reminders about tolerance
1.1a as there was a certain number of tensions between the commu-
nities in our school
1.1b and a certain number of pupils had expressed appreciation for
the attack on Charlie Hebdo
In some cases, such as this one, “components of coordinative
argumentation are part of a complex datum within one inferential
configuration under the same locus” (Rigotti and Greco 2019, p.
233). In fact, these coordinative arguments should be described as
inferentially linked to each other in the sense that both are neces-
sary to support the standpoint (Palmieri 2014, p. 40); “1.1a and
1.1b would represent different premises within the same inferential
configuration; they would both be included within one AMT
reconstruction” (Rigotti and Greco 2019, p. 231). The argument
1.1a reveals one datum (the contextual situation of the school with
a permanent conflict between opposing communities), while 1.1b
describes another datum, that is, the recent reactions of some
students who belong to a specific community anticipating the
probable beginning of a new and stronger conflict event. That the
students belong to a specific and “opposed” community is inferred
from their emotional reaction to the attack. The school’s conclu-
sion is triggered by the conjunction of the two arguments because
the decision not to allow discussion about the attack was made
subsequent to the students’ reaction in the context of a permanent
conflict.
The datum presented in 1.1b becomes relevant to the school’s
conclusion not to allow discussion about the attack due to another
inference in which the emotion term had expressed appreciation
appears.
The analysis of an emotion playing the role of argument has
already been proposed by Rigotti and Palmieri (2016, p. 55), who
apply the AMT to Solomon’s judgment. In the context of Solo-
mon’s judgement, the emotional reaction of the true mother to the
king’s proposal that the child be divided in two is taken into ac-
Emotions in argumentative narration 413
© Sara Cigada. Informal Logic, Vol. 39, No. 4 (2019), pp. 401–431
count by Solomon as a datum included in the material starting
point. This permits Solomon to conclude that that woman must be
the mother. Emotion enters the argument supporting the stand-
point. In the excerpt, the following Y structure can be reconstruct-
ed (Figure 1):
Locus: Ontological Implications (between the ontology of a sit-
uation and what the situation implies: the habitudo links the sec-
ond pole to the first one, see Discussion in paragraph 6)
Maxim: Euphoric emotions are the sign that one is experiencing
a positive situation
Major Premise (Endoxon): Terror attacks like the attack on
Charlie Hebdo are horrific situations
Minor Premise (Datum): These students have expressed appre-
ciation for the attack on Charlie Hebdo
First Conclusion: These students have expressed appreciation
for a horrific situation
Final Conclusion/ Standpoint: These students experience the
Charlie Hebdo attack as a positive situation
Discussion. As we can see from this Y reconstruction, emotion is a
part of the material starting point and can be found both in the
datum (the manifestation of euphoric attitude) and in the endoxon
(as a relevant component in the evaluation of attacks in general).
Nonetheless, the inference is only possible on the basis of the
maxim that links euphoric emotions to a specific kind of situation.
I am not discussing here the problem of a symptomatic inference
(cf. Rigotti and Greco 2019, p. 249 and 259; Plantin recurrently
refers to emotions as “syndromes” and see Plantin 1999, pp. 209-
211 on the “topics” of emotions). I will come back to this point in
section 6.
So, the final conclusion that “These students experience the
attack on Charlie Hebdo as a positive situation” is one of the effec-
tive meanings of 1.1b.
414 Cigada
© Sara Cigada. Informal Logic, Vol. 39, No. 4 (2019), pp. 401–431
Figure 1: Emotion as an argument
Endoxon: Terror attacks like the
attack on Charlie Hebdo are
horrific situations
Datum: These students have
expressed appreciation for the
attack on Charlie Hebdo
Locus
Ontological Implication
Maxim: Euphoric emotions are
the sign that one is experiencing
a positive situation
First Conclusion/ Minor Premise: These
students have expressed appreciation
for a horrific situation
Final Conclusion: These students
experience the attack on Charlie Hebdo
as a positive situation
5.2. Emotion as an implicit standpoint
However, one should evoke another relevant Y structure (Figure
2) in which emotion occurs in the final conclusion (as set out in
5.4):
Locus: Ontological Implications (between the ontology of a
situation and what the situation implies: the habitudo links the first
pole to the second one, see Discussion in paragraph 6)
Maxim: Those who experience horrific situations feel trauma-
tized immediately afterwards
Major Premise (Endoxon): Terror attacks like the attack on
Charlie Hebdo are horrific situations
Minor Premise (Datum): We experienced the attack on Charlie
Hebdo just yesterday
First Conclusion: We have just experienced a horrific situation
Final Conclusion/ Standpoint: We feel traumatized
Emotions in argumentative narration 415
© Sara Cigada. Informal Logic, Vol. 39, No. 4 (2019), pp. 401–431
Figure 2: Emotion as an implicit standpoint
Endoxon: Terror attacks like the
attack on Charlie Hebdo are
horrific situations
Datum: We experienced the
attack on Charlie Hebdo just
yesterday
Locus
Ontological Implication
Maxim: Those who experience horrific
situations feel traumatized immediately
afterwards
First Conclusion/ Minor Premise: We have
just experienced a horrific situation
Final Conclusion: We feel traumatized
Discussion. Under the same locus and with the same endoxon as in
Figure 1, another relevant Y structure is reconstructed. The datum
is almost completely ostensive (it is contextual evidence); none-
theless, it is explicitly evoked by the mention of the attack. This
second inference completes the meaning of 1.1b. The contempora-
neous activation of these two Ys creates two pairs of conflicting
meanings—the first combining the standpoint “These students
experience the attack on Charlie Hebdo as a positive situation” and
the endoxon “Terror attacks like the attack on Charlie Hebdo are
horrific situations,” and the latter combining the standpoint “We
feel traumatized” and the datum “These students have expressed
appreciation for the attack on Charlie Hebdo.”
The association of 1.1a (past conflict) and 1.1b (present disrup-
tive conflict) suggests terminating confrontation in order to pre-
vent dangerous consequences. The school’s reasoning is based on
the Locus of the Opposite (between the community rejecting the
attack and the community supporting it) and the Locus of Termi-
nation and Setting up. As Rigotti and Greco (2019) put it:
when one uses the locus from termination and setting up, he or she
is comparing the current situation with a future possible world.
Following this comparison is an evaluation about the opportunity
416 Cigada
© Sara Cigada. Informal Logic, Vol. 39, No. 4 (2019), pp. 401–431
to set up (start or begin) an activity or to cease (‘terminate’) an ex-
isting state of affair (p. 263).
8
5.3. First results from the example “had expressed appreciation”
(s’était félicité)
Regarding emotion and procedural-inferential structure: The role
of the emotion term had expressed appreciation that occurs in the
datum is crucial in triggering the inferences that invite the audi-
ence to accept the conclusion (the standpoint of the school). In
fact, although occurring in the left material-contextual side of the
Y structures, this verb plays an important role in activating the
relevant loci and maxims and functions as an “invitation to infer”
(Rocci 2017, p. 103). It is thanks to this element that the audience
is able to evaluate the kind of tensions at play and their intensity
and to compare them with those previously mentioned (in 1.1a).
Thus, the reasonability of such a strong preventive measure as
forbidding teachers to talk about Charlie Hebdo is validated (cf.
Rocci commenting on Jacobs 2006, in Rocci 2017, p. 103-104).
Regarding the discursive strategies and sense effects: As Scott
Jacobs points out, “strategy improves the quality of reasoning”
(2006, p. 428). That is why the linguistic devices contributing to
Martine’s argumentation are systematically taken into account
here. It must be said that reporting the school’s reasoning does not
coincide with sharing it as Martine clearly shows by her wording.
In fact, Martine’s discourse in general is characterized by an un-
derstated attitude, a high level of self-control (evidenced by the
transcription of the recording, which is not analyzed here), and a
non-emotional lexicon. For instance, she uses the word tensions to
describe the conflicts and the quantification a certain number (un
certain nombre, two occurrences) to quantify both the conflicts
and the pupils welcoming the attack. Mitigation strategies contrib-
ute to the atmosphere of tension in her narration because they are
interpreted as a typical cautionary reaction to a risk situation.
Nonetheless, with the exception of just this one passage, her point
of view and first-person perspective is clear throughout her testi-
mony. In this passage, by contrast, she adopts a specific perspec-
8 On this locus, see also Pollaroli and Rocci 2015, p. 187.
Emotions in argumentative narration 417
© Sara Cigada. Informal Logic, Vol. 39, No. 4 (2019), pp. 401–431
tive, which is manifested linguistically when she reports the deci-
sion to not allow debate about the attacks (nous avions reçu):
recevoir la consigne {x₁, x₂}, in fact, is the semantic conversive of
donner la consigne {x₂, x₁}, highlighting the receiver’s passive
role (Mel’chuk 1988, p. 33; Gatti 1992; Rigotti and Cigada 2013,
pp. 100-1019). Moreover, this role is represented by the plural
nous (we, the teachers): so Martine as an individual “disappears”
in the category targeted by the order10. The argumentative struc-
ture of her narration appears in explicit connectives (as…., and…,
we had been given the order…). The utterance is completely de-
void of singular first-person pronouns or possessives, which,
conversely, appear both before and after this passage thus creating
an effect of distance from the school’s reported standpoint.
The argumentative relevance of these linguistic hints is the
activation of polyphony and the discursive emergence of Martine’s
personal thesis about the issue. It could be represented under
another endoxon, such as something along these lines: “Whatever
happens, teachers are committed to managing their class, fulfilling
the institutional raison d’être of educating pupils to become good
citizens (who share the principles and laws of the Republic) ac-
cording to the orders given by the Ministry and the school’s prin-
cipal unless they contradict the institutional raison d’être.” Mar-
tine’s personal conclusion is based on a maxim derived from the
Locus of the Final Cause: “If the end must be reached, no possible
obstacle may be considered as a good reason to stop the action,” so
that all the problems and risks mentioned as data cannot be con-
sidered as a good reason not to act11.
9 French recevoir la consigne is a Lexical Function Oper2, i.e. the conversive
(Conv21) of Oper1 donner la consigne. The English version we had been given
the order exploits a different syntactic structure which is possible in English but
not in French, that of passive diathesis with the receiver in the subject’s role.
10 This would be an actantial shield in Caffi’s terminology (Caffi 2007, p. 107).
I am grateful to an anonymous reviewer for highlighting this point. In the
excerpt, mitigation strategies are consistent with the argumentation of emotions.
11 This interpretation is consistent with the preceding part of the testimony
where she had already evoked a strong personal commitment to her institutional
task (cf. video-recording 00’00’’ to 01’26’’), but I am not completing this Y
structure as it is not fully relevant to my point.
418 Cigada
© Sara Cigada. Informal Logic, Vol. 39, No. 4 (2019), pp. 401–431
5.4. Emotion as a standpoint: tension
Let us consider the occurrence of the emotion term tension in
Utterance 3 of the excerpt in the standpoint function. Martine’s
discourse, in fact, narratively justifies a “personal high-tension
situation.”
The AMT Model will allow the complex reasoning supporting
this final conclusion to be reconstructed. The totality of the excerpt
is considered as argumentatively answering the issue at stake
(“Shall I talk about yesterday’s attack in my class?” i.e. “Do I
agree that the combination of risks is a good reason to act against a
relevant institutional commitment?” but also, more generically,
“How shall I manage this situation?”). Utterance 1, introduced by
“as,” concluded with the (reasonable but still not-completely-
shared-by-the-speaker) order not to talk about the attacks with
pupils, thus indicating Martine’s misalignment with the received
order. This part constitutes a first datum resulting from two op-
posed institutional commitments: should she discuss it with the
pupils, she would be disobeying an explicit institutional order12;
and should she not discuss it with the pupils, she would be failing
in any teacher’s general educational commitment. Even if she does
not agree with the school’s conclusion based on the Locus of
Termination and Setting Up, Martine still shares the school’s
interpretation of the attitudes of certain students (had expressed
appreciation) as being the opposite of the expected one thus iden-
tifying with one of the opposing communities.
The second part of her narration (Utterance 2, il se trouve que)
adds further elements to the material-contextual situation, specify-
ing the circumstances of Martine’s class and, subsequently, her
personal involvement in the situation, that is, she is responsible for
what can be told in class (going against the ideological neutrality
of laïcité), but also for what can be done (by problematic pupils
and young offenders who have already been proven to resort to
violence instead of dialogue). Martine’s personal emotional reac-
tions to the attack and to the pupils’ reactions are also relevant
elements (they are explicitly evoked later in the discourse). In fact,
12 This remains implicit in the video but is relevant to the understanding. In fact,
Martine asked me never to mention either her real name or that of her school.
Emotions in argumentative narration 419
© Sara Cigada. Informal Logic, Vol. 39, No. 4 (2019), pp. 401–431
when she enters the classroom, she has not yet made a decision
about the issue at stake and she is still weighing up the conflict
(tension) situation.
How does the narration justify Martine’s tension before she
entered the classroom that morning? Let us turn to the Pragma-
dialectical analytical reconstruction, moving on from Utterance 1,
which has already been analyzed, to focus on Utterances 2 and 3.
1. So needless to say, tension was high on that morning, the morn-
ing of January 8th, before I entered the class (Utterance 3)
1.1a as there was a certain number of tensions between the
communities in our school, and a certain number of pupils had
expressed appreciation for the attack on Charlie Hebdo, we had
been given the order […] (Utterance 1)
1.1b that year, as it happened, I had a very particular kind of
class
1.1b.1a where there were a lot of pupils with extremely
complex personal circumstances
1.1b.1b as well as some young offenders
1.1b.1c and we had already been forced to intervene due to
tension between the different religious communities
In Pragma-dialectical terms, 1.1b represents a second argument
and a subordinative argumentation: “subordinative argumentation
is typically adopted when the argument justifying the standpoint
does not constitute a shared premise” (Palmieri 2014, p. 39), so
one needs to provide further arguments to support that premise (cf.
Rigotti and Greco 2019, p. 233). In fact, as it is not a shared prem-
ise that Martine’s class was of a very particular kind, so the speak-
er needs to provide some arguments supporting this standpoint.
The AMT highlights the fact that the procedural-inferential
process that allows for the standpoint to be determined is based on
a Locus of Ontological Implications: “This locus builds on the
relation between the nature of an entity […] [in our case, the on-
tology of a situation] and what this nature implies.” (Greco et al.
2018, p. 452). As Rigotti and Greco (2019, p. 254) put it, “[onto-
logical implication] is active in reasoning processes such as the
following: “We must thank him, because he has done a good job.”
420 Cigada
© Sara Cigada. Informal Logic, Vol. 39, No. 4 (2019), pp. 401–431
The implication of being grateful, in this case, depends on the
“ontological” relation between doing [or better receiving] some-
thing good and being grateful.” In the current case, the implication
of being tense depends on the “ontological” relation between
having to face a complex and dangerous situation and being tense:
the habitudo links the second pole to the first one (see Discussion
in 6).
Ontological implication is combined with another locus, specif-
ically, Proportion (“All the More,” cf. Rigotti and Greco 2019, pp.
262-263). In fact, given the comparison between the past and
present experiences of the difficulty in fulfilling the teacher’s
institutional commitment in an everyday context and in the present
context (of the previous day’s attack and some pupils’ euphoric
emotions), it becomes reasonable to predict that, in her specific
class, which is particularly problematic, it will be not only difficult
but almost impossible to manage the situation.
Therefore, the maxim derived from the combination of these
two loci might be sketched as follows: If someone is committed to
managing a situation but present circumstances (which are worse
than normal) probably make it impossible, there is an implication
that the person will be tense about the situation.
In order to make this maxim work in the actual context, some
material requirements, i.e. the endoxon and the datum, need to be
filled in.
Major Premise (Endoxon): Teachers are committed to manag-
ing their classes, fulfilling their institutional duty of educating
pupils to become good citizens (who share the principles and laws
of the Republic), according to the orders given by the Ministry and
the school’s Principal.
Minor Premise (Datum): 1.1a as there was a certain number of
tensions…, and a certain number of pupils had expressed apprecia-
tion for the attack…, we had been given the order… + polyphony
effect (the reported conclusion contradicts the general institutional
duty of a teacher) + Martine felt traumatized by the attack + 1.1b
that year… I had a very particular kind of class (such that it was
difficult to manage on a daily basis).
The Premises in the material starting point support the First
Conclusion: Martine is committed to managing a probably unman-
Emotions in argumentative narration 421
© Sara Cigada. Informal Logic, Vol. 39, No. 4 (2019), pp. 401–431
ageable situation. Thus, combining the Maxim with this First
Conclusion, the reasoning arrives at the conclusion of the Stand-
point.
Final Conclusion/ Standpoint: It was reasonable to feel very
tense that morning before I entered the class (Donc, inutile de vous
dire que la tension était grande ce matin-là, le matin du 8 janvier
avant mon entrée dans cette classe), as in Figure 3.
Figure 3: Emotion as a standpoint
Endoxon: Teachers are committed to
managing their classes, fulfilling their
institutional duty of educating pupils to
become good citizens (who share the
Republic’s principles and laws), according
to the instructions given by the Ministry
and the school’s Principal
Datum: there was a certain number of
tensions; a certain number of pupils had
expressed appreciation for the attack; we
had been given the order…; the order
contradicted the general institutional duty
of a teacher; M. felt traumatized by the
attack; M. had a very particular kind of
class (difficult to manage on a daily basis)
Loci
Ontological Implication and All the More
Maxim: If P is committed to managing
S, but present circumstances (which are
worse than others) probably make S
unmanageable, there is an implication
that P will be tense about S
First Conclusion/ Minor Premise:
M. was committed to
managing a probably
unmanageable situation
Final Conclusion: It was reasonable to be very
tense that morning before entering the class
5.5. First results from the example tension
Regarding emotion and the procedural-inferential structure: Even
though emotional contextual elements come from the material-
contextual (left) side of the Y structure, the connection between
that kind of situation and the speaker’s emotions, which activates
422 Cigada
© Sara Cigada. Informal Logic, Vol. 39, No. 4 (2019), pp. 401–431
the inference, is on the right side of the Y structure. It is relevant
to analyze the meaning of this “ontological implication” and the
maxim that can be derived from it in more depth. In fact,
Walton et al. (2008, p. 307) declare that, “some [loci] are based on
logical-semantic properties and are necessarily true; others are on-
ly plausible.” This indirectly suggests that, in order to verify the
hold of the argument schemes, one has to analyze in depth the se-
mantic structure of the inferential connections (maxims) on which
they are based. In fact, a careful semantic analysis helps to identi-
fy the conditions of validity of these connections (Rigotti and
Greco Morasso 2010, pp. 492-493).
Regarding discursive strategies and sense effects: In Utterance 3,
the tension is presupposed as the definite article la shows, and the
focus is on its intensity. The emotion term la tension is interesting
because its occurrence in the conclusion represents the third occur-
rence of the lexeme in the excerpt. However, the meaning of this
last occurrence is manifestly different from the previous ones
which denoted conflict between pupils. The two meanings are
linked by polysemy so that the same word is used to denote both
the situation and the implied emotion. This adds consistency and
effectiveness to Martine’s narration.
From a discursive point of view, the connective so (donc)
shows the status of Utterance 3 as a conclusion, while needless to
say (inutile de vous dire) underlines, through the rhetorical device
of praeteritio, that this conclusion is considered self-evident by the
speaker. The move is strengthened by the direct appeal to the
audience (inutile de vous dire instead of inutile de dire) and by the
speaker’s self-deixis (mon entrée dans cette classe) but also by the
insistence on evidence about the precise timing (ce matin-là, le
matin du 8 janvier, avant mon entrée). The syntactically trans-
formed phrase with an abstract noun naming the action (mon
entrée dans cette classe instead of avant que je ne rentre dans
cette classe),13 not a preferential structure (Gardes Tamine 2015;
Rigotti and Rocci 2006, p. 234) in the French language, also con-
tributes to the pathetic effect suggesting the reification of the
13 Not preserved in English translation. See Rigotti (1979, p. 229) about
Shaumyan’s syntactic transformations.
Emotions in argumentative narration 423
© Sara Cigada. Informal Logic, Vol. 39, No. 4 (2019), pp. 401–431
action. The fact that the emotion term tension is not explicitly
attributed to the speaker is consistent with the general understate-
ment characterizing Martine’s discourse, thus adding to the discur-
sive construction of pathos, via understatement as a mitigation
strategy and de-focalisation of the speaker.14
Details in description play the role of adding more data to the
material starting point, thus strengthening the speaker’s emotional
conclusion. Greco states that “the reconstruction of material-
contextual premises, especially if they are left implicit and consid-
ered as taken for granted, gives a perspective on what is or is not
inter-subjectively shared by the interlocutors” (Greco et. al. 2018).
In the excerpt, narration plays the specific role of inserting into the
discursive context all those elements that, according to the speak-
er’s point of view, are not shared by the audience like details about
the class. At the time, addressing an audience of colleagues
(teachers), Martine does not stress the endoxon (their shared pro-
fessional commitment), which remains implicit. The right side of
the Y also remains implicit.
6. Discussion
The AMT emerges as particularly relevant to the understanding of
what has been sketched as “emotional inferencing.” I outline four
specific points regarding this in the examples and offer some
hypotheses well aware that they require further investigation and
discussion.
Result 1: Y’s Procedural-inferential component in Figure 1, 2
and 3: It is, unfortunately, possible to imagine a reader not sharing
the endoxon in Figure 1, “Terror attacks like Charlie Hebdo are
horrific situations” but accepting, for example, another endoxon
such as “Terror attacks like Charlie Hebdo are desirable situa-
tions.” Nothing in the procedural-inferential structure would
change, but the first conclusion would be that “These students
have expressed appreciation for a desirable situation.” The differ-
ence would depend on the material-contextual starting point and
would coincide with the different communal opinion about a
14 I am grateful to an anonymous reviewer for pointing to mitigation and de-
focalization.
424 Cigada
© Sara Cigada. Informal Logic, Vol. 39, No. 4 (2019), pp. 401–431
specific situation. The procedural-inferential organization of the
reasoning does not depend on the content of the endoxon but,
rather, on the maxim (consistent with Danesi and Rocci 2009, pp.
203-212 on culture-bound argumentation). Additionally, both
endoxa would require further justification as one might wonder on
what basis they are shared among a community. In Martine’s
discourse, there are no explicit arguments supporting one endoxon
or the other.
In Figure 1, the Locus of Ontological Implication links the
situation and the emotion; the emotion’s extreme (the display of
euphoric emotion) is taken as the inference-trigger and the situa-
tion’s extreme (the experience of a positive situation) as the in-
ferred conclusion, so the inferencing operates from the implied
term to the implying one. Locus, in fact, coincides with a habi-
tudo: “habitudo highlights the relationship itself, thus involving
both relata. The habitudo, by the way, turns out to precisely coin-
cide with the locus” (Rigotti and Greco Morasso 2010, p. 494 note
4). As such, the link may be reversed and “read” in the opposite
direction. In fact, “each locus can be read in two directions, de-
pending on which pole of the habitudo is taken as a starting point
and which one is taken as a target point (e.g., cause to effect or
effect to cause)” (Rigotti and Greco 2019, pp. xiii and 210).
In Figures 2 and 3, in fact, the link between the two extremes of
the habitudo goes from the implying term (in 2, experiencing a
horrific situation; in 3, facing a probably unmanageable situation)
to the implied one (in 2, dismay; in 3, tension). Thus, the implying
extreme plays the role of inference-trigger while the emotion is
inferred as the ontologically implied extreme.
In examples 2 and 3, the logical form of the inference is a
modus ponens: “when one experiences a horrific situation, one
feels traumatized, and P is experiencing this horrific situation.” In
Figure 1, a form of symptomatic reasoning occurs. This maxim
“activates the logical form of false modus ponens, which is usual
in symptomatic argumentation” (Rigotti and Greco Morasso 2010,
p. 495; Rigotti and Greco 2019, pp. 211-212).
Result 2. Trying to sketch the locus. Homocentrism (interest) in
ontological implication: The link (habitudo) between “one being
involved in a specific situation” and “one’s emotional response”
Emotions in argumentative narration 425
© Sara Cigada. Informal Logic, Vol. 39, No. 4 (2019), pp. 401–431
has been accounted for as an ontological implication, that is, as an
intrinsic locus, that is a locus in which the two extremes of the
habitudo belong to the same possible word (Rigotti and Greco
2019, p. 96). Therefore, when describing emotions as one extreme
of an ontological implication, I maintain that the situation at hand
is affecting someone who is involved in it. This fits well with one
of the most relevant features mentioned in Ungerer’s model, that
of the “tendency of homocentrism which seems to permeate our
thinking and feeling” (Ungerer 1997, p. 313). In fact, emotion as
an ontological implication depends on the human perspective on
the situation. This relates to a pertinent question concerning the
asymmetry of emotion in orientation and in time. Emotions in fact
tend to be oriented towards the positive (Rodolphus Agricola
1542, ch. 3,3,1; van der Poel 1997, p. 225) and the future. This
needs to be investigated further in relation to the definition of the
inference-triggering of an “euphoric” vs “dysphoric” emotion. In
fact, the so-called “polarity” of emotions seems to be a fallacious
simplification.
Human (personal) involvement could appropriately be de-
scribed in terms of “interest,” a specific dimension of one’s “rea-
sonableness-in-context” (“it is reasonable that x evaluates any
situation in which he is involved, from the point of view of any
personal gain he has in that situation”). A pragma-dialectical
account of reasonableness may provide adequate backing, as
suggested by Rigotti (2011, p. 269):
Contrasting it [reasonableness] to the apparently close notion of
rationality can bring to light important differences, [in fact] “In
ordinary language use of the word reasonable is not limited to
verbal behavior but covers also non verbal behavior… The scope
of reasonableness seems to be wider than that of rationality. One
can, for example, speak quite well of reasonable desires, but not
so easily of rational desires.” (van Eemeren 2011, p. 29, note 9).
The example that is proposed exceeds the domain of behaviors,
both verbal and non verbal. Indeed desires belong to a class that
embraces emotions (fear, rage…), feelings, interests and other
psychological states such as suspicion, doubt, confidence beside
many other non-rational facts of human experience. And, if the
category of reasonableness can be predicated on such facts, they
acquire citizenship in argumentation theory, and strategic maneu-
426 Cigada
© Sara Cigada. Informal Logic, Vol. 39, No. 4 (2019), pp. 401–431
vering amounts to taking into account a considerably wider area of
human experience.
The very etymology of “interest” (Lat. mea inter-est) refers to
“one’s being involved” in a situation (Ernout and Meillet 1985, p.
320 and 567; Forcellini 1965, s.v. intersum).
Thus, the work that needs to be done in order to understand
emotional inferences within the AMT is an outlining of what the
relevant semantic components, both of the situations evoked and
of the human responses to them, are and under which conditions
they may be taken for granted. This should be done via a corpus-
based analysis of cases. It is likely that some habitudo will turn out
to be highly culture-dependent and very strongly held within the
community.15
Result 3. The cognitive dimension of emotional inference: In
the examples considered, maxims activating emotional inference
take the form of “Under xyz conditions affecting P’s interest, it is
reasonable that P feels like E” (or the converse symptomatic:
“When P displays E, it is reasonable to suppose that his interest is
being affected by xyz conditions”). This reformulation can possi-
bly account for the cognitive component of emotions, which has
been extensively explored by Plantin and many others. For in-
stance, to return to Figure 3, “If P is ‘committed to managing a
situation’ [this is Martine’s specific interest towards the situation]
and circumstances make her judge [cognitive component] that this
will probably be impossible, it is reasonable that P feels tense
about the situation.” This obviously reminds us of the third book
of Rodolphus Agricola’s De Inventione Dialectica (1542), where
Agricola explains that rhetorical discourse does not need to sug-
gest or recommend emotions to the audience because emotions are
the natural consequence of situations.16 Therefore, being moved is
an ontological implication when one comes to know about a given
15 Maybe the so-called “connotational frames” (Jurafsky and Martin 2018, p.
376) could be compared with the AMT to use data, mined and tagged on this
basis, for sentiment analysis.
16 According to Agricola, situations are made up of good or bad events (res)
regarding guilty or innocent persons (personae) (van der Poel 1997).
Emotions in argumentative narration 427
© Sara Cigada. Informal Logic, Vol. 39, No. 4 (2019), pp. 401–431
situation (see also Macagno and Walton 2014, pp. 66-67), accord-
ing to one’s opinion about people and events.
Result 4. Synchronization effect on the audience: As shown in
Figure 2, an emotion (dismay) experienced by the speaker might
be the conclusion of an inference triggered by a situation (the
attack on Charlie Hebdo). This emotional meaning, though implic-
it, is relevant to the meaning as it is understood by a specific audi-
ence (conflicting contents, as pointed out in 5.2). This means that
the audience is able to understand Martine’s emotion and its con-
tribution to the meaning of the whole passage. I borrow from
Martina Drescher (2003, pp. 129-130) the notion of emotional
synchronization, not only as an empathic reaction, but more wide-
ly as any emotional reaction of an audience to the situations and
emotions presented in a discourse (see Amossy 2008 about “sym-
pathy” and ethos). Different audiences “tested” with our corpus
synchronized in different ways, but all of them understood Mar-
tine’s emotion as a consistent element of her discourse; a previous-
ly mentioned example of this is the reaction of the Lebanese
teacher who commented on Martine’s distress “She is French, she
is not used to this.” This discursive reaction to Martine’s testimony
shows the teacher’s specific “interest” towards her and her situa-
tion, understanding Martine’s emotion but not aligning with it.
Moreover, according to Agricola’s description of affectus (van der
Poel 1997), audience’s emotions consist not only of empathy
and/or synchronization, but of emotional evaluation of any situa-
tion that is in play in the discourse. Roughly speaking, applying
the AMT allows us to give an account of the (subjective!) “emo-
tional layer” we perceive in any discourse we are interested in.
7. Conclusion
My analysis stems from Plantin’s account for emotion terms and
considers a situated argumentation (the day after the 2015 attack
on Charlie Hebdo; a middle school in the suburbs of Paris; the
ongoing dialogue between Martine and her problematic class;
Martine’s testimony addressing Lebanese colleagues in the inter-
national project S’éduquer pour éduquer). I analyzed the emotion-
al component of this corpus from the argumentative vantage point
428 Cigada
© Sara Cigada. Informal Logic, Vol. 39, No. 4 (2019), pp. 401–431
using Pragma-Dialectics and the Argumentum Model of Topics to
study the phenomenon of “emotional inferencing” (Ungerer 1997).
I considered a narrative corpus both because in narratives it is
taken for granted that emotions must be reasonable (in the sense
that we expect the text to give reasons supporting emotions) and
because narration (including the emotions it contains) may be used
as an argument as is the case in my corpus.
I analyzed two emotion terms: an indirect (to express apprecia-
tion) and a direct one (tension) as well as an implied (but not
expressed) emotion. For each case, I used the Locus of Ontologi-
cal Implication, considering the habitudo in the two possible direc-
tions: from the situation to the emotion or from the emotion to the
situation.
I noticed that emotional inferencing appears on the right side,
that is, in the procedural-inferential component of the Y structure.
On the left side, that is, in the material-contextual component, we
find the situational information instantiating the locus. Emotion
terms may occur on both sides and help to trigger the emotional
inferencing. The other linguistic and rhetorical structures represent
mitigation strategies that turn out to be consistent with the emo-
tional inferencing thus contributing to the sense-effects.
References
Amossy, Ruth. 2008. Dimension rationnelle et dimension affective de
l'ethos. In Emotions et discours. L’usage des passions dans la langue,
ed. Michael Rinn, 113-126. Rennes: PUR.
Caffi, Claudia. 2007. Mitigation. Amsterdam: Elsevier.
Caffi, Claudia, Richard W. Janney. 1994. Toward a pragmatics of emo-
tive communication. Journal of Pragmatics 22: 325-373.
Cigada, Sara. 2006. Connectif et relation entre locuteurs. In Sýndesmoi.
Connettivi nella realtà dei testi, eds. Giovanni Gobber, Maria
Cristina Gatti and Sara Cigada, 97-173. Milano: Vita e Pensiero.
Cigada, Sara. 2016. Analyzing emotions in French discourse: (Manipula-
tive?) shortcuts. In Case studies in discourse analysis, eds. Marcel
Danesi and Sara Greco, 390-409. Munich: Lincom Europe.
Danesi, Marcel, Andrea Rocci. 2009. Global linguistics: An introduc-
tion. Berlin/New York: Mouton de Gruyter.
Emotions in argumentative narration 429
© Sara Cigada. Informal Logic, Vol. 39, No. 4 (2019), pp. 401–431
Drescher, Martina. 2003. Sprachliche Affektivität: Darstellung
emotionaler Beteiligung am Beispiel von Gesprächen aus dem
Französischen. Berlin: de Gruyter.
van Eemeren, Frans H., Rob Grootendorst. 2004. A systematic theory of
argumentation: The Pragma-Dialectic account. Cambridge: Cam-
bridge University Press.
van Eemeren, Frans H. 2018. Argumentation theory: A Pragma-
Dialectical perspective. Cham: Springer.
Ernout, Alfred and Antoine Meillet. 1985. Dictionnaire étymologique de
la langue latine (4
e
éd.). Paris: Klincksieck.
Forcellini, Egidio. 1965 (1671). Lexicon Totius Latinitatis, eds. F.
Corradini and J. Perin. Padova : Gregoriana.
Gardes Tamine, Joëlle. 2015. Le style, entre langue et rhétorique.
Nouvelle Fribourg 1. URL accessed March 2019
.
Gatti, Maria Cristina. 1992. Dalla semantica alla lessicologia.
Introduzione al modello senso-testo di Igor Mel’chuk. Brescia: La
Scuola.
Gobber, Giovanni. 2019. The scarlet letter of “post-truth”: the sunset
boulevard of communication. Church, communication and culture
4(3): 287-304.
Greco, Sara. 2017. La dimensione inferenziale nell’argomentazione. In
Argomentare per un rapporto ragionevole con la realtà, eds. Paolo
Nanni, Eddo Rigotti and Carlo Wolfsgruber, 25-53. Milano:
Fondazione per la Sussidiarietà.
Greco, Sara et al. 2018. The analysis of implicit premises within chil-
dren’s argumentative inferences. Informal Logic 38(1): 438-470.
ICOR, Clapi website. URL accessed March 2019: .
Jacobs, Scott. 2006. Nonfallacious rhetorical strategies: Lyndon John-
son’s Daisy ad. Argumentation 20 (4): 421-442.
Jurafsky, Dan, James H. Martin. 2018. Speech and language processing
(3
rd
edition online draft). URL accessed March 2019:
.
Macagno, Fabrizio and Douglas Walton. 2014. Emotive language in
argumentation. Cambridge: Cambridge UP.
Marty, Anton. 1908. Untersuchungen zur Grundlegung der allgemeinen
Grammatik und Sprachphilosophie. Vol. 1. Halle a. S.: Niemeyer.
http://www.nouvellefribourg.com/universite/le-style-entre-langue-et-rhetorique/
http://www.nouvellefribourg.com/universite/le-style-entre-langue-et-rhetorique/
http://clapi.ish-lyon.cnrs.fr/
http://clapi.ish-lyon.cnrs.fr/
https://link.springer.com/journal/10503/20/4/page/1
https://web.stanford.edu/~jurafsky/slp3/ed3book.pdf
430 Cigada
© Sara Cigada. Informal Logic, Vol. 39, No. 4 (2019), pp. 401–431
Mel’chuk, Igor A. 1988. Paraphrase et lexique dans la théorie linguis-
tique Sens-Texte. In Lexique et paraphrase, eds. Gabriel G. Bès, Ca-
therine Fuchs, 13-54. Lille: Presses Universitaires de Lille.
Micheli, Raphaël. 2008. Emotions as objects of argumentative construc-
tions. Argumentation 24: 1-17.
Micheli, Raphaël. 2010. L'émotion argumentée. L'abolition de la peine
de mort dans le débat parlementaire français. Paris: Editions du Cerf.
Micheli, Raphaël. 2014. L'émotion dans le discours, Louvain-la-Neuve:
deBoeck.
Moeller, Esther. 2010. Une union éternelle ? Les catholiques libanais et
les écoles françaises au Liban 1900-1950. Documents 45: 43-68.
Olmos, Paula (ed.). 2017. Narration as argument, Cham: Springer.
Palmieri, Rudi. 2014. Corporate argumentation in takeover bids. Am-
sterdam: Benjamins.
Palmieri, Rudi and Sabrina Mazzali-Lurati. 2016. Multiple audiences as
text stakeholders: A conceptual framework for analyzing complex
rhetorical situations. Argumentation 30: 467-499.
Perret-Clermont, Anne-Nelly. 2005. Lo spazio per il pensare. In
Discorso: Una proposta per l’autoformazione e apprendimento degli
insegnanti, ed. Carlo Pontecorvo, 21-34. Roma: Carocci.
Piccinelli, Marta. 2019. Il francese del Libano: per una verifica
sociolinguistica dell’uso in contesto scolastico. Master thesis at the
Università Cattolica del Sacro Cuore, Brescia.
Plantin, Christian. 1999. La construction rhétorique des émotions. In
Rhetoric and argumentation, ed. Eddo Rigotti, 203-219. Tübingen:
Niemeyer.
Plantin, Christian. 2004. On the inseparability of emotion and reason in
argumentation. In Emotion in dialogic interaction, ed. Edda
Weigand, 265-276. Amsterdam: Benjamins.
Plantin, Christian. 2011. Les bonnes raisons des emotions. Bern: Peter
Lang.
Plantin, Christian. 2018. Dictionary of argumentation, College
Publications.
van der Poel, Marc. 1997. Rodolphe Agricola. Ecrits sur la dialectique et
l’humanisme. Paris: Champion.
Pollaroli, Chiara and Andrea Rocci. 2015. The argumentative relevance
of pictorial and multimodal metaphor in advertising. Journal of Ar-
gumentation in Context 4/2: 158-200.
Rigotti, Eddo. 1979. Principi di teoria linguistica. Brescia: La Scuola.
http://www.icar.cnrs.fr/pageperso/cplantin/documents/1999b.doc
Emotions in argumentative narration 431
© Sara Cigada. Informal Logic, Vol. 39, No. 4 (2019), pp. 401–431
Rigotti, Eddo. 2011. Frans H. van Eemeren: Strategic maneuvering in
argumentative discourse. Extending the Pragma-Dialectical Theory of
Argumentation (Review). Argumentation 25: 261-270.
Rigotti, Eddo, Sara Cigada. 2013. La comunicazione verbale.
Santarcangelo di Romagna: Maggioli.
Rigotti, Eddo, Sara Greco Morasso. 2010. Comparing the argument
model of topics to other contemporary approaches to argument
schemes: The procedural and material components. Argumentation
24: 489-512.
Rigotti, Eddo and Sara Greco. 2019. Inference in argumentation. Cham:
Springer.
Rigotti, Eddo and Rudi Palmieri. 2016. Solomon's wise judgment: A
case study of argumentation in context. In Case studies in discourse
analysis, eds. Marcel Danesi and Sara Greco, 37-61. Munich: Lincom
Europe.
Rigotti, Eddo and Andrea Rocci. 2006. Le signe linguistique comme
structure intermédiaire. In Nouveaux Regards sur Saussure. Mé-
langes offerts à René Amacker, ed. Louis de Saussure, 219-247.
Genève: Droz.
Rocci, Andrea. 2017. Ragionevolezza dell’impegno persuasivo. In
Argomentare per un rapporto ragionevole con la realtà, eds. Paolo
Nanni, Eddo Rigotti and Carlo Wolfsgruber, 88-120. Milano:
Fondazione per la Sussidiarietà.
Rodolphus Agricola. 1542. De Inventione Dialectica libri III. Coloniae:
Iohannis Kempensis.
Thierry, Herman. 2008. Narratio et argumentation. In Argumentation et
Narration, eds. Emmanuelle Danblon, Emmanuel de Jonge, Ekateri-
na Kissina and Loïc Nicolas, 29-41. Bruxelles: Editions de
l’Université de Bruxelles.
Ungerer, Friedrich. 1997. Emotions and emotional language in English
and German news stories. In The language of emotions, eds. Susanne
Niemeier and René Dirven, 307-328. Amsterdam/Philadelphia: Ben-
jamins.
https://search.usi.ch/en/publications/16009/solomons-wise-judgment-a-case-study-of-argumentation-in-context
https://search.usi.ch/en/publications/16009/solomons-wise-judgment-a-case-study-of-argumentation-in-context