Title of the Paper [16 point font] © Fernando Leal. Informal Logic, Vol. 41, No. 2 (2021), pp. 219–243. Argumentation Ab Homine in Philosophy FERNANDO LEAL Department of Education University of Guadalajara 150 Parres Arias, Zapopan, Jal., 45132 Mexico ferlec@hotmail.com Abstract: Argumentation that uses the beliefs of one’s opponents to refute them is well known (ad homi- nem in the classical sense). This paper proposes that there is a hitherto unnoticed counterpart to it, to be called ab homine, in which speak- ers/writers argue through the manner in which they deliver a message. Since the manner of delivery can never be turned into a premise or premises, this form of argumenta- tion—although somewhat resembling Aristotle’s ethos—is much closer to the peculiar force of Socratic elen- chos. Résumé: L’argumentation qui utilise les croyances de ses adversaires pour les réfuter est bien connue (ad homi- nem au sens classique). Cet article propose qu'il y ait une contrepartie jusqu'ici inaperçue, appelée ab homi- ne, dans laquelle les orateurs/ écrivains raisonnent par la manière dont ils délivrent un message. Puisque le mode de livraison ne peut jamais être transformé en une ou plusieurs prémisses, cette forme d’argu- mentation —bien qu’elle ressemble quelque peu à l’éthos d’Aristote —est beaucoup plus proche de la force particulière de l’élenchos socratique. Keywords: ad hominem, ab homine, argumentation, elenchos, ethos, philoso- phy 1. Introduction In this paper, I propose to demonstrate the existence of an argu- mentative procedure that I shall call ab homine, a phrase coined as a counterpart to ad hominem. In spite of the well-known ambiguity of the latter phrase, at its most basic, it simply denotes argumenta- tion directed to someone—the hearer or reader. Similarly, the phrase ab homine hints at the origin of the communicative act, meaning argumentation directed from someone—the speaker or writer. In a sense, all this is utterly trivial, for all argumentation is 220 Leal © Fernando Leal. Informal Logic, Vol. 41, No. 2 (2021), pp. 219–243. both ad hominem and ab homine given that it always comes from someone and goes to someone. Still, we all use the phrase ad hominem to highlight a special and remarkable way in which argumentation is directed to. This exact same reason moves me to propose the parallel phrase ab homine as denoting a special way in which argumentation is directed from. The paper has three unequal parts. First, I shall briefly describe the special way in which argumentation is sometimes markedly “from someone” as well as “to someone” (§2). Then I shall ana- lyze in some detail three argumentative texts that are as different from each other as possible yet can be shown to contain argumen- tation ab homine in the sense described (§3). Finally, I shall re- spond to some objections that might be made to such an analysis (§4). 2. A question of terms It is by now well known that before the nineteenth century, the phrase ad hominem referred to argumentation that uses premises admitted by one’s opponents in order to refute them. Sometime during the nineteenth century, writers began to use the phrase in a curiously distorted sense to signify argumentation that uses per- sonal characteristics of one’s opponents to “win the argument.” Given that such a “victory” was obtained by not engaging with the argument itself, this somehow became a “fallacy,” although I do not know when exactly this shift of meaning happened or who was behind it.1 In any case, the original meaning of the phrase ad hominem is at least as old as Aristotle, who uses the exact equiva- lent Greek phrase or similar ones.2 1 In Schopenhauer’s now quite famous 1830 manuscript on “eristics” (first published by Frauenstädt, 1864, pp. 3-35), it is possible to see the transition in meaning, as it were, in statu nascendi (compare tricks 16 and 29; English translation: Saunders, 1896, pp. 27-28 and 34-35; see also p. 13). In that text, Schopenhauer suggests the felicitous phrase ad personam to be reserved for the fallacy of textbook lore whilst keeping ad hominem for the older meaning. 2 De sophisticis elenchis 178b17: πρὸς τὸν ἄνθρωπον; cf. Metaphysics K, 1062a3: πρὸς τόνδε, ad istum, “to this one”; Physics Θ, 263a15: πρὸς τὸν ἐρωτῶντα, ad interrogantem, “to the questioner”; De caelo Β, 294b9: πρὸς τὸν τἀναντία λέγοντα, ad contra dicentem, “to the one who contradicts.” The Argumentation Ab Homine in Philosophy 221 © Fernando Leal. Informal Logic, Vol. 41, No. 2 (2021), pp. 219–243. The discoverer of argumentation ad hominem, however, was not Aristotle but Socrates. This is pretty clear from Plato’s and even from Xenophon’s dialogues, in which Socrates often says to his interlocutor, I am arguing with you, not with Gorgias nor with Homer nor with any author of a speech or book which you may have listened to or read and memorized. You alone are my witness, and I don’t need any other. I want to know what you think, what you believe, what you would say that justice, virtue, or whatever is” (see, for in- stance, Hippias Minor 365C-D, Meno 71D, Gorgias 471E-472C, 474A; Xenophon, Memorabilia IV 2). And, as we know, Socrates always asked questions in order to elicit premises from his interlocutor that could then be used to refute him or to make him contradict himself. Thus far, we are in familiar territory. Nonetheless, there is a profound difference between Aristotle and Socrates. For Aristotle, argumentation ad hominem is purely dialectical and not apodictic, a matter of opinion not science, and a methodi- cal procedure preparatory but inferior to proof (see Zingano 2017). A superficial reading of Plato or Xenophon seems to confirm that Socrates invented a technique that Aristotle later codified, mainly in his Topics. Plato’s Apology, however, clearly shows that Socra- tes’ ultimate purpose was not limited to refuting half-baked thoughts or finding inconsistencies in his interlocutor’s speeches. Socrates was not just examining other people’s beliefs but their whole lives, in the same way that he said he had examined and kept examining his own life. So, the Aristotelian ad hominem could not be farther from the Socratic one. When Socrates is examining someone, taking him as a witness, there is, as it were, a surface structure to the argumenta- opposite term is not always πρὸς τὸ πρᾶγμα, ad rem, “to the thing”; cf. De soph. el. πρὸς τὸν λόγον, “to the argument”; this is inverted in De caelo 293a25-26: πρὸς λόγους καὶ δόξας vs. πρὸς τὰ φαίνομενα). In the anonymous paraphrasis of Aristotle’s De soph. el., §22 (Hayduck 1884, p. 53, l. 11) we have as opposites not only Aristotle’s own πρὸς τὸν λόγον (“to the argument”), but also πρὸς τὴν ἀλήθειαν (“to actual truth or reality”), and of course πρὸς τὸ πρᾶγμα. Behind the Aristotelian opposition lies, of course, his distinction between dialectical and apodictic syllogisms (Topics A 100a25-b23). 222 Leal © Fernando Leal. Informal Logic, Vol. 41, No. 2 (2021), pp. 219–243. tion. This surface structure certainly has to do with beliefs, prem- ises, and propositions; it can be analyzed, diagrammed, and even formalized. However, there is also a deep structure: something else is being said, if rather indirectly. If Gorgias is unable to express the nature of rhetoric, Laches the nature of courage, Meno the nature of virtue, Thrasymachus the nature of justice, whilst main- taining that they know those natures, then what kind of men are they? That is the whole point of the ad hominem. But it is the man, only him, only the man who has been examined, who has to see the point; nothing would be gained and indeed much would be lost if Socrates would rub it in. Still, for this second, deeper, underly- ing argument to sink in, to have an effect, someone with a particu- lar ethos had to deliver the treatment. It was only the sheer power of Socrates’ persona that enabled such an examination. That is the whole point of the ab homine.3 The evidence, as far as I can interpret it, indicates that Aristotle never quite understood what was going on in the Socratic dia- logues. And so, by dint of codifying the Socratic method, he trans- formed it into something completely different. On the one hand, he first transformed the ad hominem aspect of argumentation into a dialectical game of refutation in the Topics (cf. Moraux 1968), and then he took distance from it as not scientific (Prior Analytics A 24a22-b15). On the other hand, he converted the ab homine aspect of argumentation into ethos, a means of persuasion—the most powerful one, he says (Rhetoric Α 1356a5-13)—only to turn it into advice to orators about how to defeat their opponent by means of ethos (see Rhetoric Γ 1419b14-17). In other words, Aristotle in- strumentalized a living practice into a learnable technique. The focus on examining the lives of flesh and blood people was re- placed by an instrument to be used according to this or that pur- 3 It is to the immense merit of Livio Rossetti to have gone into the depths of what is really going on in Plato’s and Xenophon’s Socratic dialogues (see especially the studies collected in Rossetti 2011). Although I discovered the structure explored in this paper in the texts analyzed in §3, it was after reading Rossetti that it dawned on me that he, starting from Plato and Xenophon, arrived first to a similar view. In fact, it could be that what he calls “formatting” (Rossetti 1994) is the right explanation for this kind of argumentation, but such a discussion goes beyond what can be done in a single paper. Argumentation Ab Homine in Philosophy 223 © Fernando Leal. Informal Logic, Vol. 41, No. 2 (2021), pp. 219–243. pose.4 In Socrates, ethos and elenchus and ab homine and ad hominem were the two sides of one and the same coin; they were not separated as in Aristotle, and they were, in the last instance, aimed at conversion. However, I submit that, in practice, many philosophers, if not indeed all of them, ultimately use the properly Socratic way of argumentation, even if sans le savoir. Let us consider some examples. 3. The examples In this section, I shall analyze three texts widely separated in time: a polemic essay by a contemporary “analytic” philosopher of science (Moulines 1977), the famous Vorrede or “preliminary discourse” to Hegel’s Phenomenology of spirit (1807), and Des- cartes’s Discourse on method (1637)—or rather a few sentences from each text. By a curious coincidence, there are exactly 170 years separating the first case from the second and the second from the third. For the record, I did not choose these texts, but they chose me, as it were. As part of my workshops on argumentation in a graduate program in philosophy, I routinely give my students philosophical texts for analysis and evaluation, trying to capture as much diversity as I can in terms of periods, languages, disciplines, and styles. As I was preparing for the discussions of these three texts, it started to dawn on me that something was amiss with them. This suspicion was confirmed by the points raised in class as I went through them with my students. According to the brief description of the ab homine given in §2, we should distinguish between the argumentation that is actually going on between the lines in those texts and the surface argu- ments that those lines ostensibly contain. To show this gap, we must begin with an analysis of those surface arguments. Such an analysis will reveal that, behind or underneath, there is another 4 I cannot emphasize enough that the pistis by ethos in Aristotle is something radically different to what Socrates was represented as doing in the Socratic dialogues. Alan Brinton’s ēthotic argument (1986) is even more different. If readers compare my examples with Brinton’s (pp. 251-254), they will easily identify the numerous points of contrast. 224 Leal © Fernando Leal. Informal Logic, Vol. 41, No. 2 (2021), pp. 219–243. argument, which is never quite verbalized, and in fact it could not be without destroying its force. 3.1 Why is a philosopher of science not a materialist? (Moulines 1977) The first text is an 11-page paper, published in Spanish in a journal devoted to what we are used to calling “analytical philosophy.” However, it is not an ordinary paper of the sort routinely published in such a journal. In fact, it is a pièce d’occasion, a short polemical tract, a pamphlet in the sense usual in nineteenth-century Britain or America. The paper triggered a controversy in the small world of Spanish-speaking analytic philosophy, as was probably intended (see Esquivel 1982). Already, the title, “Why I am not a materialist,” is unusual. The ‘I’ in this title is clearly not metaphorical or faux-generic, as in Dennett (1981, 1984). In the paper we are discussing, ‘I’ means quite precisely the author, Ulises Moulines. It is similar to Rus- sell’s famous “Why I am not a Christian,” in which Russell want- ed to justify his personal attitude towards the Christian religion, in fact toward any religion. The text I want the reader to consider first is made up of the first four sentences of the paper (Moulines 1977, p. 25; bracketed numbers added): El materialismo es una doctri- na confusa. Si se cree que el materialismo es una doctrina clara, es porque afirma que só- lo existe la materia y porque se supone que todo el mundo sa- be lo que es la materia. Pero este supuesto es falso. Nadie sabe hoy día a ciencia cierta lo que es la materia. [1] Materialism is a confused doctrine. If people believe that [2] materialism is a clear doc- trine, that is because [3] it as- serts that only matter exists, and because people assume that [4] everybody knows what matter is. But this assumption is false. [5] Nobody knows in any scien- tifically informed way what matter is. The point of the added numbering in the translation is to highlight the five points put forward in this text and to allow tracking of the argument. Argumentation Ab Homine in Philosophy 225 © Fernando Leal. Informal Logic, Vol. 41, No. 2 (2021), pp. 219–243. The text pits an expert opinion, namely claim [1], against a popular opinion. Popular opinions are indeed usually countered by expert opinions, as in this case. Moulines is an expert whose philo- sophical authority in matters concerning physics is well estab- lished, at least for the readers of the journal in which this essay was published. The widespread opinion is [2], which is incompati- ble with [1]. Now, [2] is supported by the conjunction of [3], which is simply a definition of the term ‘materialism’, and [4], which again is a widespread opinion. This second widespread opinion is countered by Moulines’s counterclaim [5], again an expert opinion opposed to a popular opinion. The passage quoted is thus a quasi-logical argument in the sense of Perelman and Olbrechts-Tyteca (1958, §45; in English 1969, pp. 193-195). If [5] is true, then [4] is false; if [4] is false, then the conjunction of [3] and [4] is false; if the conjunction of [3] and [4] is false, then [2] is false as well; and if [2] is false, then [1] is presumably true. At least, [1] is true if ‘confused’ is defined as ‘not clear,’ which can be safely assumed to have been Moulines’s meaning and his readers’ understanding. Now, the body of the paper, that is, almost everything that comes after the passage quoted (Moulines 1977, pp. 25-34), con- sists of a continuous, relentless argument purporting to prove [5] by showing, in a nutshell, that physicists’ theories do not include the concept of matter and that none of the concepts that are includ- ed in those theories look like the concept of matter. If this pro- tracted argument should be considered sound, then claim [1] must be admitted as true. Materialism is a confused doctrine. Of course, as I usual in philosophy, the argument in favor of [5] has not been considered sound by anyone who has cared to con- sider it publicly, even though each critic has attacked different aspects of it. Two years after the original publication, the author offered an over 30-page response to his various critics (Moulines 1979). This response has apparently been unconvincing, for later commentators have also failed to accept Moulines’s argument (see the whole controversy in Esquivel 1982). I myself must confess to be much more persuaded by Moulines’s argument than by the objections of its detractors; but the purpose of this paper is not to take sides in the materialism 226 Leal © Fernando Leal. Informal Logic, Vol. 41, No. 2 (2021), pp. 219–243. controversy, but rather to point out that the description of the paper’s argument, as I have presented it, is incomplete. Claim [1] is not, and cannot be, the end of it. The title of the paper clearly, even loudly and provocatively, expresses what Moulines wants to argue for—Why I am not a materialist, where the ‘I’ refers to him personally, to Dr. Moulines himself. That it is a personal matter is borne out by the fact that the paper’s title is followed by an aster- isk that refers us to a footnote (Moulines 1977, p. 25): Debo el estímulo para escri- bir este artículo a mi amigo Adolfo G. De la Sienra, quien, al preguntarse asom- brado cómo alguien como yo podía no ser materialista, me indujo a poner en orden mis ideas. What spurred me on to write this paper was a question raised by my friend, Adolfo G. de la Sienra. He wondered why it was possible that someone like me was not a mate- rialist. It is that question that moved me to try and put my ideas in order. So, the purpose of the paper is indeed a personal matter (“someone like me”), originating from a personal question. It is not an impersonal question such as whether the philosophical doctrine of materialism—the “ontological” claim that “only matter exists”—is clear or confused, nor even the “epistemological” question—whether or not we know what matter is. Neither the argument purporting that [5] is true nor the argument leading from [5] to [1] is complete in itself. Something is missing from each, something vital—namely, it is the answer to the personal question raised in wonder by the author’s friend. What, then, is the argument leading from [1] to such an an- swer? Towards the end of the paper, we find the following state- ments (Moulines 1977, p. 34): Las dificultades del materialis- mo expuestas hasta aquí me pa- recen muy graves para alguien que quiera sostener el materia- lismo con honestidad intelectual. Ello no implica que las conside- re por principio insalvables. El The troubles of materialism presented up to this point seem to me too severe for whoever may want to uphold material- ism with intellectual honesty. I don’t mean they cannot be overcome. The point is just Argumentation Ab Homine in Philosophy 227 © Fernando Leal. Informal Logic, Vol. 41, No. 2 (2021), pp. 219–243. caso es simplemente que la doc- trina me parece tan problemática que considero filosóficamente prudente abstenerse de comulgar con ella, al menos en la situa- ción actual. that this doctrine seems to me so problematic that I deem it philosophically prudent to abstain from sharing it, at least in the current situation. Notice the highly impersonal reference to two principles: intellec- tual honesty and philosophical prudence. The first principle concerns the question of whether we know what matter is. In one passage, Moulines says that if physicists are honest, they will answer that they do not know (p. 26), and in another, he says that if atomistic philosophers are honest, they will answer that they do not know but the physicists surely do (p. 28). Yet Moulines does not say that he cherishes intellectual honesty. Instead, through the meticulous argument supporting [5], he shows us that he does. If he did just say that he is intellectually honest, a skeptical reaction would be in perfect order. It is much more diffi- cult to resist the serious, frank, straightforward tone with which the argument was presented. That tone is what gives his argument for [5] an ab homine character. Now, I have already said that there is another argument leading from [5] to [1]. If our best science does not know what matter is, then materialism can only be a confused doctrine. But the story would end there were it not for the second principle mentioned by Moulines: if materialism is confused, then philo- sophical prudence advises us to reject it as a rash doctrine. But again, Moulines does not say that he is philosophically prudent. All he does is argue from [5] to [1], yet that argument itself is what justifies his personal answer—his answer to the personal question in the title. The reason he is not a materialist is that materialism is a confused doctrine. Now, this may look like an incomplete argument, but it is not. If it were, then the missing premises would be something like: (a) Philosophical prudence forbids upholding confused doc- trines. (b) I, Moulines, am philosophically prudent. 228 Leal © Fernando Leal. Informal Logic, Vol. 41, No. 2 (2021), pp. 219–243. We may accept premise (a) as a “warrant” (Toulmin 1958, chapter III) or as a pragmatic optimum (van Eemeren and Grootendorst 1992, chapter 6), but we cannot accept premise (b), for (b) would just say what has to be shown.5 And the only way one can show philosophical prudence is by acting prudently, that is, by rejecting materialism in actu against a widespread but wrongheaded con- sensus. This the author does in the most visible part of his paper: its title. The active resistance to popular opinion, as embodied in Moulines’s paper, makes his whole text an argument ab homine whose conclusion is the answer to the initial question. Now, it could be argued that Moulines is justifying himself or at least justifying his non-allegiance to widespread materialism among his colleagues. The way to justify oneself or one’s philo- sophical position is by argument. If we succumb to the temptation to understand the purpose of the paper in this way, then there is no way around adding premises that claim, for Moulines, certain intellectual virtues (intellectual honesty and philosophical pru- dence), and perhaps denying those same virtues to his materialist readers. But by so doing, we would destroy the moral force of the paper. It is quite easy to instead imagine Moulines as a modern Socrates who questions people if not in the agora, then at least in the halls of academia. In fact, the argument leading to [5] is writ- ten as a succession of possible answers to the question of what matter is and then refutations of those answers by means of propo- sitions that are very difficult to deny for “analytic” materialists. The paper is profoundly Socratic, an élenchos whose purpose is philosophical conversion. It is thus less about Moulines justifying himself as it is about putting facile and shallow claims to shame. 5 As I said, there is an argument leading to [5] and another leading from [5] to [1]. If we should be so misguided as to reconstruct the bulk of the paper, then the argument leading to [5] would also need two premises: (c) “intellectual honesty forbids believing that materialism is a clear doctrine” and (d) “I, Ulises Moulines, am intellectually honest.” Then, we would have an argument effec- tively answering the question in the title, but, again, such a full argument is exactly what cannot be verbalized without destroying the force of the paper. Argumentation Ab Homine in Philosophy 229 © Fernando Leal. Informal Logic, Vol. 41, No. 2 (2021), pp. 219–243. 3.2 What should a preface be like? (Hegel 1807) Now we come to an author who could not be further from the tradition of analytic philosophy that Moulines belongs to. It is a historical fact that G. E. Moore and Bertrand Russell launched the “analytic philosophy” tradition—perhaps the most consistent one of the last hundred years—precisely by way of a rejection of He- gel. In spite of that, and in spite of the obvious differences be- tween Moulines’s text and the text we are going to analyze now, I shall endeavor to show that Hegel argues ab homine very much like Moulines does. Hegel is famous for the numerous and intricate introductory texts he wrote for his major works, but none is more intricate than the first of the two introductory texts he wrote for his first major work, the Phenomenology of Spirit, under the title of a “prelimi- nary discourse” (Vorrede). Its first two sentences have a somewhat paradoxical sound to them (Hegel 1807, pp. I-II): Eine Erklärung, wie sie einer Schrift in einer Vorrede nach der Gewohnheit vorausgeschickt wird, —über den Zweck, den der Verfasser sich in ihr vorgesetzt, sowie über die Veranlassungen und das Verhältnis, worin er sie zu andern frühern oder gleichzeitigen Behandlungen desselben Gegenstandes zu stehen glaubt,— scheint bei einer philosophischen Schrift nicht nur überflüssig, sondern um der Natur der Sache willen sogar unpassend und zweckwidrig zu sein. Denn wie und was von Philosophie in einer Vorrede zu sagen schicklich wäre, —etwaeine historische Angabe der Tendenz und des Standpunkts, des allgemeinen Inhalts und der Resultate, eine Verbindung von hin und her sprechenden Behauptungen und An explanation, such as people customarily place in a preliminary discourse before the text itself—about the aim the author pursues in it, as well as the occasion behind it, and the relation- ship to other, earlier or contemporary, treatments of the subject matter in which the author believes to stand—seems in the case of a philosophical text not only superfluous but improper for the sake of the thing and subverting of the aim pur- sued. For the content and style in which it would be becoming to talk in a prelim- inary discourse—say, a notice about approach and perspective, a general ac- count and an abstract of 230 Leal © Fernando Leal. Informal Logic, Vol. 41, No. 2 (2021), pp. 219–243. Versicherungen über das Wahre —kann nicht für die Art und Weise gelten, in der die philosophische Wahrheit darzustellen sei. results, a collection of state- ments and assertions about what is true, one going this way, the other that way— cannot rightfully apply to the method of exposition of philosophical truth. My translation may not be the smoothest, but it tries to be faithful to the meaning of the words actually used by the author in view of the purpose of this paper. If you pay attention to that meaning, you will see that this text brims with what we may call, for the sake of brevity, “value judgments.” In fact, Hegel draws a clear opposition between two sets of “values.” On the one hand, we have the cus- tom of writing prefaces in a certain way; we believe certain things are becoming in regard to the content and style of a preface. On the other hand, we have intimations of the immeasurably higher standards imposed by philosophy in matters of exposition. The habits of the literary crowd are set against the stringent duties of the philosopher. The immediate effect of this oppositional gambit upon the attentive reader is not altogether dissimilar to that of the famous painting by René Magritte, in which the sentence Ceci n’est pas une pipe (This is not a pipe) is written just below what appears to be a pipe. We have all by now probably learned the Belgian paint- er’s lesson: the image of a pipe, a painted pipe, is, precisely, not a pipe at all. In the case of Hegel, what we see is the word Vorrede (preliminary discourse) printed above a couple of sentences that imply that the text we have just begun to read will, precisely, not be a Vorrede. If we understand what Hegel is doing, we shall understand that it cannot be one. How is this effect produced? Each of the two sentences in the quoted passage is artfully constructed as a mirror image of the other. In each, the subject is separated from the predicate by an inserted remark placed between hyphens. Each one of the three constituents of the first sentence has a parallel in a constituent of the second sentence: (a) each grammatical subject denotes what is customary and becoming in a preface; (b) each parenthetical re- mark specifies the denotatum in some detail by telling us the kinds Argumentation Ab Homine in Philosophy 231 © Fernando Leal. Informal Logic, Vol. 41, No. 2 (2021), pp. 219–243. of things that are expected in a preface; and (c) the predicate final- ly denies the fit between the denotatum and what philosophy requires. The parallel between the constituents in each sentence is so perfect that some readers might be misled to think they are being treated to a tautology. But are the two sentences tautologi- cal? That would be bad writing, for Hegel connects the two sen- tences by means of an argumentative indicator, ‘for’ (denn in the original German text), so that the second sentence is quite clearly presented as a reason for the first one. But if so, what is the argument? It could be summarized as follows (inverting the order of the sentences so as to emphasize the argument structure): (H) The materials considered acceptable for inclusion in a preface do not fit the requirements of philosophical exposi- tion; therefore, a preface would appear to be contrary to the purpose of philosophy. Here we have a purely impersonal argument. In fact, some theo- rists of argumentation would say that Hegel is not so much arguing in the sense of justifying as he is just explaining the connection of certain norms and aims (those of philosophy) with certain facts (what an ordinary preface can, or rather cannot, do to satisfy those norms and attain those aims). But surely something more is afoot here; we feel that the author is not explaining in such a dull sense of the word. The point is that the proper conclusion is not really that a preface, if written in the customary way, subverts the pur- pose of philosophy. The proper conclusion is rather that it should not be so written, or even that it will not be so written. But, if we, having seen that, now try to analyze this in the way usual in argu- mentation studies, then the new, proper conclusion would have to be considered as following from two missing premises: (a) Honoring the purpose of philosophy forbids writing pref- aces as usual. (b) I (Hegel) should, and will, honor the purpose of philoso- phy. 232 Leal © Fernando Leal. Informal Logic, Vol. 41, No. 2 (2021), pp. 219–243. Again, for the sake of the argument, we may concede premise (a) as a warrant or a pragmatic optimum. But premise (b) would only invite skepticism. The reader might be excused for thinking “Yeah, that’s what everybody says. We all want to honor the purpose of philosophy, so what?” Proclaiming one’s “values” utterly spoils the effect. Moreover, the proper conclusion is not to say that something should be done but to just do it right there in front of the reader.6 And this is precisely what Hegel does. For the rest of his “prelimi- nary discourse” does indeed treat, philosophically, those require- ments that “the method of philosophical exposition” embodies. It is a philosophical argument in defense of those requirements that shows them in action. For that long argument that follows the first two sentences of the Vorrede is precisely an exposition of the nature of philosophical knowledge that itself embodies and honors those requirements. It is not a mere preparation for what is to come when, after the preface, the real philosophical work begins; it is already that philosophical work, carried out as Hegel best under- stood it. It does not talk about what the book will do; it starts doing it. By doing it in the way that it should be done, Hegel does not need to tell the reader what his “values” are; his writing incarnates them. In other words, beyond argument (H), there is another, more powerful argument, one in which this man does that which has to be done. By doing it, by showing how it is done, he proves his point. Here again, it could be argued that Hegel is justifying his be- liefs about philosophy and its method before the interested public. However, if we were to represent the Vorrede as an argument where some missing premises purport to claim that Hegel possess- 6 At this point, an anonymous reviewer of the present paper mentioned Aristo- tle’s practical syllogism. This is exactly right and reinforces my point. We could say that the first two sentences of Hegel’s Vorrede are indeed a complete argument, namely (H), but they correspond to the premises of a practical syllo- gism whose conclusion is an action, namely, the actual thinking done and deployed in the rest of the Vorrede. But note that the conclusion is not the content of the complex argumentation following the two sentences, but the arguing in that way itself. Argumentation Ab Homine in Philosophy 233 © Fernando Leal. Informal Logic, Vol. 41, No. 2 (2021), pp. 219–243. es certain virtues, the whole purpose of the ab homine argumenta- tion would be defeated. This is, by the way, as much true of Hegel as it is of his arch-enemies, the analytic philosophers, as I endeav- ored to show elsewhere (Leal-Carretero and Favila-Vega 2015). It may have been naïve of Diogenes to refute Zeno and his paradoxes by walking in front of him, but in philosophy this is perhaps the only way to show what one really means by a method.7 Although there is an affinity between Hegel and Moulines, there is also an important difference: in his long argument towards [5], which makes up the bulk of his paper, he can safely assume that his concepts and methods are shared by his readers (after all, his paper was published in an analytic philosophy journal), whereas Hegel is writing for readers who share with Kant the basic idea of critique, namely, that one can talk about philosophy without doing it. It is this idea that he tries to refute in actu. 3.3 Is good sense optimally distributed? (Descartes 1637) Let us now go farther back in time, to the beginning of early mod- ern philosophy. The text chosen for analysis comes from both a great arguer and a great mathematician, as well as one of the few great writers that philosophy can boast of: Le bon sens est la chose du monde la mieux partagée ; car chascun pense en estre si bien pouruû, que ceux mesme qui sont les plus dif- ficiles à contenter en toute autre chose, n’ont point coustume d’en desirer plus qu’ils en ont. En quoy il n’est pas vraysemblable que Good sense is the thing best distributed in the world; for everyone thinks already to have got so much of it that even those who are hardest to satisfy in every other field are not used to want more of it than they already have. 7 Johnstone gives us a beautiful example of how this goes when he tells us the story of the life-changing experience he had when, as a young and self-righteous analytic philosopher, he was hired by a department of philosophy brimming with real-life Hegelians (1978, pp. 1-4). They did not talk about Hegel in a dogmatic manner but rather subjected Johnstone’s empiricist prejudices to a Socratic élenchos conducted by the kind of questioning of perception that is featured at the beginning of the Phenomenology of Spirit. His colleagues did not convert Johnstone to Hegelianism, but they surely started him on his well- known path towards the rapprochement of philosophy and rhetoric. 234 Leal © Fernando Leal. Informal Logic, Vol. 41, No. 2 (2021), pp. 219–243. tous se trompent ; mais plutost ce- la tesmoigne que la puissance de bien iuger, & distinguer le vray d’auec le faux, qui est proprement ce qu’on nomme le bon sens ou la raison, est naturellement esgale en tous les hommes ; et ainsi que la diuersité de nos opinions ne vient pas de ce que les vns sont plus rai- sonnables que les autres, mais seu- lement de ce que nous conduisons nos pensées par diuerses voies, & ne considerons pas les mesmes choses. Car ce n’est pas assez d’auoir l’esprit bon, mais le prin- cipal est de l’appliquer bien. Les plus grandes ames sont capables des plus grands vices aussy bien que des plus grandes vertus ; et ceux qui ne marchent que fort len- tement, peuuent auancer beaucoup dauantage, s’ils suiuent tousjours le droit chemin, que ne font ceux qui courent, & qui s’en esloignent. About which it is not likely that all are deceived; but, on the contrary, this is a sign that the ability to judge well and to distinguish between the true and the false, which is what is properly called good sense or reason, is by nature equal among all men; and so the diversity of opin- ions does not come from some people being more reasonable than others, but only from the fact that we follow different paths in our thinking and do not focus on the same subjects. For it is not enough to have a good mind, but the main thing is to use it right. The greatest souls are capable of the greatest vices as much as of the greatest virtues; and those who walk but quite slowly can progress further if they keep a straight course than those who run and depart from it. We all know how intensely personal the Discourse on Method is, but here, in its first paragraph, the tone is, again, as in the two texts analyzed before, utterly impersonal. From the second paragraph on, Descartes speaks to his reader in the first person (“Pour moy, ie n’ai iamais presume…,” “As for myself, I have never pretend- ed…”). The first paragraph appears to be different. Nonetheless, I want to show that Descartes is there arguing ab homine although in a way that is markedly different from Hegel and Moulines. Descartes argues by a procedure I propose to call “double irony.” Take the first sentence. It has the form of an argument. First, a claim is put forward: Argumentation Ab Homine in Philosophy 235 © Fernando Leal. Informal Logic, Vol. 41, No. 2 (2021), pp. 219–243. Good sense is the thing best distributed in the world. For this claim, a reason (evidence, data) is then offered: For everyone thinks already to have got so much of it that even those who are hardest to satisfy in every other field are not used to want more of it than they already have. Right? Well, not quite because readers of this text, being, for obvious reasons, intelligent and cultured people, will detect an irony here. Surely, Descartes cannot mean what he says. It is true, the reader thinks, that everyone believes themselves to be smart enough already, but most people deceive themselves as to how smart they are. There are natural inequalities among human be- ings; some are clearly smarter than others, and moreover, a few are vastly superior; more than a few are not a match for these superior intellects but are still all right; many more are just average; and so on down to the really stupid. One is tempted to think that Des- cartes actually means to make the reverse argument: Everyone thinks they already have so much good sense that even those who are hardest to satisfy in every other field are not used to wanting more of it than they already have; there- fore, good sense is anything but evenly distributed. In other words, Descartes is being ironical: he means the opposite of what he says. However, the next sentence surprises the reader by directly embracing people’s assessment of their capacities: “It is not likely that all are deceived.” Of course, it is not, the reader suddenly realizes. Some people may be wrong, but surely not all of them. They may be wrong about unimportant things, but not about— what? What is exactly this good sense of which Descartes speaks? Our first impulse is to think of something like intelligence, which is clearly not evenly distributed. That is exactly the reason why we believed Descartes was being ironical. But, if it is not intelligence we are talking about, then what? The philosopher right away 236 Leal © Fernando Leal. Informal Logic, Vol. 41, No. 2 (2021), pp. 219–243. explains what he means—the ability to judge well and to distin- guish between the true and the false, in one word: reason. This is “by nature equal among all men.” For we are all rational animals, are we not? Some readers may be rash and suggest that reason is not evenly distributed either. But by now it is clear to at least the most per- ceptive readers that Descartes is serious, deadly serious. He is not fooling around; he is not saying one thing and meaning another. Good readers have been stopped in their tracks. This is what I mean by “double irony.” For the irony was not meant, as we thought at first, to be directed to “everyone,” but rather to us read- ers, who judged too quickly. Such is the effect that Descartes’ discourse is meant to have on us. This man, evidently a superior mind, has tricked us into an error of judgment. When the reader thought Descartes was gently mocking all those poor benighted souls who believe they are the equals of the intelligent readers, the latter felt complicit in the mockery. Full of their self-importance, they felt for a moment to be equals of Descartes hovering high above the common run of mortals. But they have now been put in their place by the author. They will not commit the same mistake again. No, they must now sit quietly and read carefully, for the meaning of this text is deeper than they thought. Descartes goes on with his lecture. He now takes the “diversity of opinions” as the fact to be explained. Does it stem from some people being more reasonable than others? No, it does not. It stems from some people thinking in different ways and about different things. Now, that is a thought! The reader becomes pensive. This man Descartes seems to have a point. And then the hammer goes down: “For it is not enough to have a good mind (esprit), but the main thing is to use it right.” It is very difficult to oppose this, especially considering how rash our initial reading was. Then the final nail in the coffin comes as Descartes reminds us that the best people can also be the worst, and that losing one’s bearings has lost many a soul, no matter how well endowed. The whole argument is presented as coming from this man, even though this man (Descartes) has not said a word about who he is—that will come later. Rather, he has shown us who he is Argumentation Ab Homine in Philosophy 237 © Fernando Leal. Informal Logic, Vol. 41, No. 2 (2021), pp. 219–243. precisely by the way he conducted his argument, by the way he talked. And in fact, in the rest of the Discourse on Method, he proceeds by presenting himself as an ordinary man, rather average in all his cognitive faculties and yet capable of transcending those by virtue of possessing a method. We are presented with some rules for thinking that will allow the evenly distributed good sense to be exercised, even if one’s memory, intelligence, and imagina- tion are not as strong as those of other people—the same message we find in Francis Bacon.8 This message, characteristic of early modern Europe, was, in 1637, still new and revolutionary, and the mode of argumentation, ab homine, was chosen to make the read- ers open their minds to it. Of course, you can take the first paragraph of the Discourse on Method and separate claims and reasons, order the whole thing into a nice argument map, and even supply missing premises where possible if you wish. It can be done; in fact, it can be done pretty easily because Descartes was a careful reasoner. If some readers should find this exercise useful, let them carry it out; I will not because, after all, my point is that this will just reconstruct the surface structure of the Cartesian argument. Behind or underneath that structure, there is a different kind of argument that works its magic because it manages to prove to readers that they jump to conclusions and they are not as smart as they thought. Method, or the right path to follow in order to discover the truth in the scienc- es, is something we all should learn “for it is not enough to have a good mind, but the main thing is to use it right.” Nonetheless, this other argument cannot be put into a premise-conclusion structure without ruining it. There are many differences between this text and the preceding ones. The most obvious one concerns historical importance. Des- 8 Bacon, Instauratio magna, Book I, §XLI: “Our method of discovering the sciences is such as to leave little to the sharpness and strength of wit, but rather to level wit and intellect. For, as in the drawing of a straight line or a perfect circle, much depends upon the hand’s steadiness and practice, if one does it with one’s own hand, but little or nothing if a ruler or compass be employed— our method works exactly like that.” In the following century, that revolutionary thought, so characteristic of modernity, had been thoroughly assimilated, as witnessed by Adam Smith (1776, Book I, Chapter II; see Peart and Levy 2005). 238 Leal © Fernando Leal. Informal Logic, Vol. 41, No. 2 (2021), pp. 219–243. cartes’s Discourse is nothing less than a re-founding of philoso- phy, the beginning of what we call “modern philosophy.” As for Hegel, he works within the framework created by Descartes al- most two centuries earlier. Still, within that framework, Hegel creates a niche of his own. His Phenomenology is the first really significant work he produced, and it made him immediately fa- mous. The main thing for Hegel was, however, to show how his way of philosophizing marked a serious departure from the Kanti- an way. Kant believed that before starting to philosophize, there was a place for examining questions of method. In that way, he was, of course, like Locke and all the others: a follower of Des- cartes. In contrast, Hegel was adamantly opposed to the idea that you can talk about philosophy from the outside as it were and discourse on method without already doing philosophy and com- mitting oneself to a method. This departure, which we call Hegeli- anism, represents an important inflection in the history of philoso- phy so that, even if the Phenomenology is not in the same league as Descartes’ Discourse, it is nonetheless a highly significant work. Moulines’s paper is, in comparison, of very little im- portance. Another obvious difference is in the use of irony. We can dis- cern an undertone of mockery in both Moulines and Hegel, but Descartes is far more subtle and adroit. Nonetheless, all three are castigating their readers, putting forward values that their readers are supposed to respect, and endeavoring to make those readers shift their allegiances. The purpose could not be more Socratic, which is why the ab homine is very much to the point. For it to work, of course, the author should prove himself a man from whom such a lesson can be taken to heart. The similarities are thus much stronger than the differences. In all three cases, we find that the underlying argument consists of showing how things should be done. We have seen this in the case of Hegel and Moulines. As for Descartes, consider that the first paragraph of his Discourse is immediately followed by an autobi- ographical depiction of how he came by his method and what its rules are, which again is nothing but a preface to the actual speci- mens of that method: the Dioptrics, the Meteors, and above all the Geometry. Seen from that perspective, the purpose of the first Argumentation Ab Homine in Philosophy 239 © Fernando Leal. Informal Logic, Vol. 41, No. 2 (2021), pp. 219–243. paragraph is to carry out a kind of élenchos directed to smug read- ers who believe themselves to be oh so superior. And, like Socra- tes before him, Descartes puts them in their place. In this way, although it is on an altogether different level, he is performing the exact same operation that Hegel, in his own smaller way, and Moulines, in his even smaller way, also performed. For this is what ab homine argumentation is designed to do. 4. Objections and replies Enough with the examples. Let us now face the objections that may be levied against the idea of ab homine argumentation. 1. “Three swallows do not a summer make. Let us admit that there is something going on in these texts that can be so described, but that we cannot generalize. Most philosophical arguments, God forbid, are not like that.” This objection misses the point, for I was not trying to generalize. If the reader admits that the examples given prove the existence of ab homine argumentation as de- scribed, then I am satisfied. The question of how widespread the thing may be can be tackled some other day. 2. “The three texts analyzed occur in a particular position, namely at the beginning of the particular work to which they belong. What you call ab homine argumentation is not likely to occur anywhere else in a proper philosophical text.” I do not know that this is true. Many passages in Plato’s dialogues show the ab homine character more or less everywhere, as intimated at the beginning of this paper. Take also Pascal or Nietzsche or Feyera- bend. Moreover, I suspect that the whole argumentation in Quine’s celebrated “Two dogmas of empiricism” is very much ab homine. In any case, research on the issue deserves pride of place in the study of the relation between philosophy and rhetoric. 3. “Your three pieces of ab homine argumentation are pretty bad arguments. It is more than dubious that the lack of a consensus about the concept of matter among scientific experts in physics justifies avoiding professing philosophical materialism; Hegel’s insights about philosophical truth, in particular those opposed to mathematical truth, are anything but true insights; the modernist experiment to equalize cognitive abilities by means of method was 240 Leal © Fernando Leal. Informal Logic, Vol. 41, No. 2 (2021), pp. 219–243. and is a resounding failure.” I am far from sure that these asser- tions are correct, but this is neither here nor there. I was not trying to show that my examples of ab homine argumentation are exam- ples of good arguments (whatever those may be) but only to show that they are a real phenomenon that has so far escaped attention. 4. “The phenomenon you point out is real enough, but it per- tains to the field of persuasion not argumentation. Your so-called ab homine arguments may be striking and even convincing to some people, but they are not proper arguments. Why, you practi- cally admit that they cannot be analyzed based on premises and conclusion. No argument map or diagram can be built to show their components and layout. So, they are not really arguments.” This objection seems weightier than it really is. First of all, an ab homine argument can, of course, be reduced to the premise- conclusion form, and it can be diagrammed. However, there is no point in such a reduction. The argument does not work by saying but by showing if I may again use Wittgenstein’s distinction. In fact, by “completing” it and putting it into the PC sequence format (Levi 1995), you will only destroy its strength. Or are we not interested in the strength of an argument anymore?9 5. “In the end, as you yourself conceded at the beginning of this paper, all arguments come from a particular person and produce their effect by coming from that person. So, there is nothing spe- cial about ab homine argumentation. All arguments are ab homine, so, you are not saying anything of importance.” This comment is most welcome, even though it is opposed to some of the above objections. Indeed, it is trivial that all arguments come from a 9 I can discern a possible route to follow in pursuing the question arising here as to whether only PC sequences are arguments. The sociolinguist Deborah Tan- nen has called our attention to the fact that every message unavoidably carries with it what she calls a pragmatic meta-message, which crucially involves the relationship between sender and receivers (Tannen 1986, 1989, passim). You can neither erase the pragmatic metamessage from your message nor can you make it explicit by turning it into a message, for this new message will have its own metamessage, which will usually counteract the original metamessage. For instance, people who insist that they are sincere will usually be perceived as less trustworthy. The explicit argument in my three examples would then be the message and the underlying argument the metamessage. Such an elaboration would require another paper. Argumentation Ab Homine in Philosophy 241 © Fernando Leal. Informal Logic, Vol. 41, No. 2 (2021), pp. 219–243. particular person. Still, only some arguments work because of the kind of person that has issued them. Aristotle insisted that of all the means of persuasion, ethos was the most powerful. But that does not mean it is always powerful. Aristotle also said that ethos is not a reputational aura that precedes your speech but is rather produced by that speech (dia tou logou 1356a9). Again, few argu- ers speak or write so well that they thereby create a persona, exude an aura, and project an image that moves the listeners or readers in the special way of ab homine argumentation. In a sense, the error behind both this objection and the one before it is that they take the Aristotelian distinction of logos–pathos–ethos too literally. The argument that most theorists of argumentation focus on, the verbal set of premises and conclusion, is only one aspect of logos, the other one being as a carrier of ethos (and pathos). When a philosopher argues ab homine in a way that commands attention, it is always this human being, talking in this way, that is the important thing. References Brinton, Alan C. 19868. Ēthotic argument. History of Philosophy Quar- terly 3 (3): 245-258. Dennett, Daniel. 1981. Where am I? In Brainstorms: Philosophical essays on mind and psychology, 310-323. Cambridge (MA): The MIT Press. Dennett, Daniel. 1984. I could not have done otherwise—so what? The Journal of Philosophy 81 (10): 553-565. Descartes, René (1637). Discours de la méthode, pour bien conduire sa raison, & chercher la vérité dans les sciences, plus la Dioptrique, les Météores et la Géométrie, qui sont des essais de cette Méthode. Lei- den: Ian Maire. Eemeren, Frans H. vans and Rob, & Grootendorst, Rob. 1992. Argumen- tation, communication, and fallacies: a pragma-dialectical approach. Mahwah (NJ): Lawrence Erlbaum. Esquivel, Javier, ed. 1982. La ppolémica del mmaterialismo. [the mate- rialism controversy.] Madrid: Tecnos. Frauenstädt, Julius, ed. 1864. Aus Arthur Schopenhauer’s handschrift- lichem Nachlaß: Abhandlungen, Anmerkungen, Aphorismen und Fragmente. Leipzig: Brockhaus. 242 Leal © Fernando Leal. Informal Logic, Vol. 41, No. 2 (2021), pp. 219–243. Hayduck, Michael, ed. 1884. Anonymi in Aristotelis Sophisticos elen- chos paraphrasis. Berlin: Reimer. [= Commentaria in Aristotelem graeca, XXIII, 4.] Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich. 1804. System der Wissenschaft I: Phänomenologie des Geistes. Bamberg and Würzburg: Joseph Anton Goebhardt. Johnstone, Henry W., Jr. 1952. Philosophy and argumentum ad homi- nem. The Journal of Philosophy 49: 489-498. Johnstone, Henry W., Jr. 1959. Philosophy and argument. University Park (PA): Pennsylvania State University Press. Johnstone, Henry W., Jr. 1978. Validity and rhetoric in philosophical argument: an outlook in transition. University Park, PA: The Dia- logue Press of Man & World. Leal-Carretero, Fernando and Víctor M. Favila-Vega. 2015. La retórica de los autores anti-metafísicos. Revista Iberoamericana de Argumen- tación 11: 1-31. Levi, Don S. 1995. The case of the missing premise. Informal Logic 17 (1): 67-88. Moraux, Paul. 1968. La joute dialectique d’après le huitième livre des Topiques. In Aristotle on Dialectic: The Topics, ed. G. E. L. Owen, 277-311. Cambridge (UK): Cambridge University Press. Moulines, Ulises. 1977. Por qué no soy materialista. Crítica: Revista Hispanoamericana de Filosofía 9 (26): 25-36. Peart, Sandra, and& David M. Levy, David M. 2005. The ‘Vanity of the philosopher’: from equality to hierarchy in post-classical economics. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press. Perelman, Chaïm, and & Lucie Olbrechts-Tyteca, Lucie. 1958. La nou- velle rhétorique: Traité de l’argumentation. Paris: Presses Universi- taires de France. Perelman, Chaïm, and& Lucie Olbrechts-Tyteca, Lucie. 1969. The new rhetoric: A treatise on argumentation. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press. Rossetti, Livio. 1994. Strategie macro-retoriche: la formatazione dell’evento comunicazionale. Palermo: Centro Internazionale Studi di Estetica. Rossetti, Livio. 2011. Le dialogue socratique. Paris: Les Belles Lettres. Saunders, T. Bailey, (trad. translator) 1896. The art of controversy and other post humous papers by Arthur Schopenhauer. London: George Allen & Unwin. Smith, Adam. 1776. An inquiry into the nature and causes of the wealth of nations. London: W. Straham and T. Cadell. Argumentation Ab Homine in Philosophy 243 © Fernando Leal. Informal Logic, Vol. 41, No. 2 (2021), pp. 219–243. Tannen, Deborah. 1986. That’s not what I meant! how conversational style makes or breaks your relations with others. New York: William Morrow. Tannen, Deborah. 1989. Talking voices: repetition, dialogue, and image- ry in conversational discourse. New York: Cambridge University Press. Toulmin, Stephen. 1958. The uses of argument. Cambridge (UK): Cam- bridge University Press. Zingano, Marco. 2017. Ways of proving in Aristotle. In Reading Aristo- tle: Argument and Exposition, eds. W. Wians and& R. Polansky, 7- 49. Leiden: Brill.