International Journal of Analysis and Applications ISSN 2291-8639 Volume 14, Number 1 (2017), 20-26 http://www.etamaths.com ALGEBRAIC HYPER-STRUCTURES ASSOCIATED TO NASH EQUILIBRIUM POINT AND APPLICATIONS A. DELAVAR KHALAFI AND B. DAVVAZ∗ Abstract. In this paper, we generalize some concepts of the game theory such as Nash equilibrium point, saddle point and existence theorems on hyper-structures. Based on new definitions and theo- rems, we obtain some important results in the game theory. A few suitable examples have been given for better understanding. 1. Introduction and preliminaries Algebraic hyperstructures are suitable generalizations of classical algebraic structures. In a classical algebraic structure, the composition of two elements is an element, while in an algebraic hyperstructure, the composition of two elements is a set. More exactly, if H is a non-empty set and P∗(H) is the set of all non-empty subsets of H, then we consider maps of the following type: fi : H×H −→P∗(H), where i ∈ {1, 2, . . . ,n} and n is a positive integer. The maps fi are called (binary) hyperoperations. For all x,y of H, fi(x,y) is called the (binary) hyperproduct of x and y. An algebraic system (H,f1, . . . ,fn) is called a (binary) hyperstructure. Usually, n = 1 or n = 2. Under certain conditions, imposed to the maps fi, we obtain the so-called semihypergroups, hypergroups, hyperrings or hyperfields. Sometimes, external hyperoperations are considered, which are maps of the following type: h : R×H −→P∗(H), where R 6= H. Usually, R is endowed with a ring or a hyperring structure. Several books have been written on this topic, see [1, 2, 6, 13]. Hyperstructure theory both extends some well-known group results and introduce new topics leading us to a wide variety of applications, as well as to a broadening of the investigation fields, for example see [4, 5, 8, 10–12]. A recent book on hyperstructures [2] points out on their applications in rough set theory, cryptography, codes, automata, probability, geometry, lattices, binary relations, graphs and hypergraphs. Another book [6] is devoted especially to the study of hyperring theory. Several kinds of hyperrings are introduced and analyzed. The volume ends with an outline of applications in chemistry and physics, analyzing several special kinds of hyperstructures: e-hyperstructures and transposition hypergroups. The theory of suitable modified hyperstructures can serve as a mathematical background in the field of quantum communication systems. Optimization theory is the study of the extremal values of a function: its minima and maxima. In mathematics, optimization refers to choosing the best element from some set of available alternatives. Nonlinear programming deals with the problem of optimizing an objective function in the presence of some constraints. In [8], we generalized the optimization theory on algebraic hyperstructures. The game theory is another framework which has been generalized of optimization theory. The famous mathematician Von Numan has been proposed his important game theory in 1928. Game theory is an important branch of applied mathematics in which decision maker chooses his strategy with regards to strategies of other players. In this theory any player tries to choose his best strategy for obtaining maximum pay off function. The methods and applications in the game theory are very different. In [9], bileaner two person nonzero sum game has been considered. In the mathematical domain the extensions of the previous works are very popular. Our contribution in this paper is the extensions of some previous concepts in game theory on the hyperstructures and have considered several new examples that we can’t solve them via usual game theory. It means that we have obtained a new widespread in the game theory. 2010 Mathematics Subject Classification. 20N20, 91A99. Key words and phrases. algebraic hyperstructure; optimization; game theory; Nash equilibrium point. c©2017 Authors retain the copyrights of their papers, and all open access articles are distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License. 20 ALGEBRAIC HYPER-STRUCTURES ASSOCIATED TO NASH EQUILIBRIUM POINT AND APPLICATIONS 21 2. Game Theory In this paper, we address a hyper-structures as follows: ? : H ×H → H ⊗H ⊆P∗(H), (2.1) · : F ×H → H, + : H ×H → H, where H 6= ∅, ? is a commutative hyperoperation such that ?(H×H) = H⊗H, · and + are commutative binary operations and F is a filed. Henceforth, let F = R. Convex and concave functions play an important role in almost all branches of mathematics as well as other areas of science and engineering. Convex and concave functions have many special and important properties. In this paper we use some these properties in game theory . Let define P∗(X) = {x ? y ∈ H ⊗H : x, y ∈ X} for all non-empty subset X in H. Now, we formulate the n-person game theory problem on hyper-structures as follows: Define the function fi : P ∗(X1) ×···×P∗(Xn) → R, i = 1, · · · ,n, where Xi is any non-empty subset of H and fi and Xi are a pay off function and a strategy set of i-th player, respectively. Let W = X1 ×···×Xn. The next definition plies an important role in the following discussions. Definition 2.1. The n-tuple (x1 ?y1, · · · ,xn ?yn) ∈ P∗(X1)×···×P∗(Xn) is called Nash equilibrium point, if the following inequalities hold. f1(x1 ? y1, · · · ,xn ? yn) 6 f1(x1 ? y1, · · · ,xn ? yn), (2.2) for all x1 ? y1 ∈ P∗(X1), ... fn(x1 ? y1, · · · ,xn ? yn) 6 fn(x1 ? y1, · · · ,xn ? yn), for all xn ? yn ∈ P∗(Xn). Henceforth, for simplicity let consider n = 2. As a special case we consider the following situation. If we have f1(x1 ? y1,x2 ? y2) + f2(x1 ? y1,x2 ? y2) = 0, for all (x1 ?y1,x1 ?y1) ∈ P∗(X1)×P∗(X2). Thus, the Nash equilibrium point satisfies in the following inequalities, f1(x1 ? y1,x2 ? y2) 6 f1(x1 ? y1,x2 ? y2) 6 f1(x1 ? y1,x2 ? y2), (2.3) for all (x1 ? y1,x2 ? y2) ∈ P∗(X1) ×P∗(X2), or equivalently f2(x1 ? y1,x2 ? y2) 6 f2(x1 ? y1,x2 ? y2) 6 f2(x1 ? y1,x2 ? y2), (2.4) for all (x1 ? y1,x2 ? y2) ∈ P∗(X1) ×P∗(X2). The next definition plays an important role in the game theory. Definition 2.2. The pair (x1 ? y1,x2 ? y2) ∈ P∗(X1) ×P∗(X2) is called the saddle point, if satisfies the first inequalities (3) or second inequalities (4). Suppose that v = inf x2,y2∈X2 sup x1,y1∈X1 f(x1 ? y1,x2 ? y2) and v = sup x1,y1∈X1 inf x2,y2∈X2 f(x1 ? y1,x2 ? y2). Clearly, we have v ≤ v. Definition 2.3. The strategy x1, y1 ∈ X1 is called max-min if v = inf x2,y2∈X2 f(x1 ? y1,x2 ? y2), and similarly, the strategy x2 ? y2 ∈ X2 is called min-max, if v = sup x1,y1∈X1 f(x1 ? y1,x2 ? y2). The following theorem gives us a necessary and sufficient condition that guaranties the existence of saddle point. 22 DELAVAR KHALAFI AND DAVVAZ Theorem 2.1. Suppose that the pay-off function f(x1 ? y1,x2 ? y2) on X1 ×X2 is given. There is a saddle point (x1 ? y1,x2 ? y2) if and only if sup x1,y1∈X1 inf x2,y2∈X2 f(x1 ? y1,x2 ? y2) = inf x2,y2∈X2 sup x1,y1∈X1 f(x1 ? y1,x2 ? y2). (2.5) In addition x1 ? y1 ∈ P∗(X1) and x2 ? y2 ∈ P∗(X2) are max-min and min-max, respectively. Proof. Suppose that (x1 ? y1,x2 ? y2) is a saddle point. We have v ≤ sup x1,y1∈X1 f(x1 ? y1,x2 ? y2) = f(x1 ? y1,x2 ? y2) = inf x2,y2∈X2 f(x1 ? y1,x2 ? y2) ≤ v, so the equation (5) is held. Now, suppose that we have the equation (5) and x1 ? y1 and x2 ? y2 are max-min and min-max strategies, respectively. Then, f(x1 ? y1,x2 ? y2) ≤ sup x1,y1∈X1 f(x1 ? y1,x2 ? y2) = v = v = inf x2,y2∈X2 f(x1 ? y1,x2 ? y2) ≤ f(x1 ? y1,x2 ? y2). This completes the proof. � The saddle point does not always exist. The following example denotes such a situation. Example 2.1. Suppose that H = R and X1 = X2 = [0, 1]. We define f : P∗([0, 1]) −→ R and ? respectively as follows: x ? y = x, f(x1 ? y1,x2 ? y2) = 3x 2 1 − 5x1x2 + 3x 2 2. Clearly, M(x1 ? y1) = min x2,y2∈X2 f(x1 ? y1,x2 ? y2) = 11x21 12 . Then, we have: v = max x1,y1∈X1 11x21 12 = 11 12 , x1 = 1. Similarly, N(x2 ? y2) = maxx1,y1∈X1 f(x1 ? y1,x2 ? y2) = max{3x22, 3x22 − 5x2 + 3}, x2 = 3 5 . Therefore, we have v = min x2,y2∈X2 N(x2 ? y2) = 27 25 , v < v. Now, we obtain max-min and min-max strategies. As min x2,y2∈X2 f(1 ? y1,x2 ? y2) = min x2∈X2 3 − 5x2 + 3x22 = 11 12 = v, max x1,y1∈X1 f(x1 ? y1, 3 5 ? y2) = max x1∈X1 3x21 − 3x1 + 27 25 = 27 25 = v. Therefore, {1 ? y1 : y1 ∈ [0, 1]} and {35 ? y2 : y2 ∈ [0, 1]} are max-min and min-max strategy set, respectively. According to Theorem (2.5), (1 ? y1, 3 5 ? y2) is not a saddle point. The above example shows that we must generalize the previous saddle point definition. Definition 2.4. Let � > 0. The pair (x�1 ? y � 1,x � 2 ? y � 2) ∈ P∗(X1) ×P∗(X2) is called �-saddle point of f(x1 ? y1,x2 ? y2) on X1 ×X2, if f(x1 ? y1,x � 2 ? y � 2) − � ≤ f(x � 1 ? y � 1,x � 2 ? y � 2) ≤ f(x � 1 ? y � 1,x2 ? y2) + � (2.6) for all x1, y1 ∈ X1, x2, y2 ∈ X2. Lemma 2.1. Let x1 ?y1, x2 ?y2 are max-min and min-max strategies, respectively and � = v−v ≥ 0. Then, (x1 ? y1, x2 ? y2) is an �−saddle point of f(x1 ? y1,x2 ? y2) on X1 ×X2. Proof. If v = v, so x1 ? y1, x2 ? y2 is a saddle point. Let � = v −v > 0. Clearly, x1 ? y1, x2 ? y2 is an �−saddle point. � Using the above definition, we consider the following example. Example 2.2. In Example 2, let � = v −v. As f(x1 ? y1, 3 5 ? y2) − � = 3x21 − 3x1 + 27 25 − ( 27 25 − 11 12 ) ≤ f(1 ? y1, 35 ? y2) = 27 25 ≤ f(1 ? y1,x2 ? y2) + � = 3 − 5x2 + 3x22 + ( 27 25 − 11 12 ), ALGEBRAIC HYPER-STRUCTURES ASSOCIATED TO NASH EQUILIBRIUM POINT AND APPLICATIONS 23 for all x1, y1 ∈ X1, x2, y2 ∈ X2, so (x�1 ? y�1,x�2 ? y�2) = (1 ? y1, 3 5 ? y2), is a �−saddle point of f(x1 ? y1,x2 ? y2). Similar to saddle point, we can generalize the concepts of min-max and max-min as follows: Definition 2.5. Let � > 0. The strategies x�1 ? y � 1 and x � 2 ? y � 2 are �− max-min and �−min-max, if inf x2,y2∈X2 f(x�1 ? y � 1,x2 ? y2) ≥ v − � and sup x1,y1∈X1 f(x1 ? y1,x � 2 ? y � 2) ≤ v + �. In the remaining part, we consider the some new topology characters of hyper-structures [7] and their applications in game theory. Let H be a metric space, X, Y be compact subsets of H and Y (x1 ? y1) = Arg min x2, y2∈X2 f(x1 ? y1,x2 ? y2) = {x̂2 ? ŷ2|x̂2, ŷ2 ∈ X2, f(x1 ? y1, x̂2 ? ŷ2) = min x2, y2∈X2 f(x1 ? y1,x2 ? y2)}. Theorem 2.2. Suppose that the pay off function f(x1?y1,x2?y2) is a continuous function on X1×X2 and P∗(X1), P ∗(X2) are compact sets in H ⊗ H. Then, the function g(x1 ? y1) = min x2, y2∈X2 f(x1 ? y1,x2 ? y2) on X1 is a continuous function. Proof. Let {xk1} and {yk1} be two sequences in X1 such that convergence to x1 and y1, respectively. By considering g(xk1 ? y k 1 ), we can prove that it converges to g(x1 ? y1). In contradiction, there are subsequences {xkl1 }, {y kl 1 } in X1 such that lim l→∞ g(x kl 1 ? y kl 1 ) 6= g(x1 ? y1). Choosing sequence {xkl2 ?y kl 2 ∈ Y (x kl 1 ?y kl 1 )}, based on compactness of X2, we have lim l→∞ x kl 2 ?y kl 2 = x2 ?y2. We must show that x2 ? y2 ∈ Y (x1 ? y1). By definition xkl2 ? y kl 2 , we have g(x kl 1 ? y kl 1 ) = f(x kl 1 ? y kl 1 ,x kl 2 ? y kl 2 ) ≤ f(x kl 1 ? y kl 1 ,x2 ? y2), for all x2, y2 ∈ X2. In the above inequality, when l →∞, we conclude that f(x1 ? y1,x2 ? y2) ≤ f(x1 ? y1,x2 ? y2), for all x2, y2 ∈ X2. Therefore, x2 ? y2 ∈ Y (x1 ? y1), that is lim l→∞ g(x kl 1 ? y kl 1 ) = lim l→∞ f(x kl 1 ? y kl 1 ,x kl 2 ? y kl 2 ) = f(x1 ? y1,x2 ? y2) = g(x1 ? y1). � Under what conditions is the function Y (x1 ? y1) continuous? We assert the sufficient condition, that guaranties the continuous function Y (x1 ? y1). Theorem 2.3. Suppose that the conditions of previous theorem have been satisfied and for any x1, y1 ∈ X1, Y (x1 ? y1) = {x2 ? y2} be a singleton. Then, Y (x1 ? y1) is a continuous function on X1. Proof. Suppose that the function Y (x1 ?y1) isn’t continuous in x1 ?y1 ∈ P∗(X1), so there is a sequence {xk1 ? yk1} in P ∗(X1), such that it converges {x1 ? y1}, but {xk1 ? yk1} = {x k 2 ? y k 2} does not convergent to Y (x1 ?y1) = {x2 ?y2}. Therefore, there is an �−Neighborhood N?� (Y (x1 ?y1)) ⊂ P∗(X2) that does not contain infinite number of elements {xk2 ? yk2}. Rely on compactness of P∗(X2) −N?� (Y (x1 ? y1)), we have subsequence {Y (xkl1 ?y kl 1 )} = {x kl 2 ?y kl 2 }⊂ P ∗(X2) −N?� (Y (x1 ?y1)), such that it convergent to x′2 ? y ′ 2 6= x2 ? y2. According to the previous theorem, we conclude that x′2 ? y′2 = Y (x1 ? y1), which it contradicts to singleton. � Definition 2.6. Let f : P∗(X) → R, where X is non-empty convex subset in H. The function f is called a convex function on P∗(X) if f([λx1 + (1 −λ)x2] ? [λy1 + (1 −λ)y2]) ≤ λf(x1 ? y1) + (1 −λ)f(x2 ? y2) for each x1,x2,y1,y2 ∈ X, x1 ? y1, x2 ? y2 ∈ P∗(X) and for all 0 ≤ λ ≤ 1. The function is called strictly convex on P∗(X) if the inequality is satisfied as a strict inequality for each distinct x1 ? y1, x2 ? y2 ∈ P∗(X) and 0 < λ < 1. The function f is called concave (strictly concave) on X if −f is convex (strictly convex) on X. 24 DELAVAR KHALAFI AND DAVVAZ The following function is an example of convex function [8]. Example 2.3. Let H = R+ ×R+. Suppose that zmin = min{x1,x2,y1,y2}, zmax = max{x1,x2,y1,y2}, (x1,y1) ? (x2,y2) = [zmin, zmax] × [zmin, zmax] ⊆ R+ ×R+ and f : H⊗H → R is defined by f((x1,y1)?(x2,y2)) = zmax−zmin, for all (x1,y1), (x2,y2) ∈ X, where X is any non-empty convex subset in H. Suppose that ((x̄1, ȳ1), (x̄2, ȳ2), z̄) and ((x̂1, ŷ1), (x̂2, ŷ2), ẑ) in epi?f and x̄λ = λx̄1 + (1 −λ)x̄2, ȳλ = λȳ1 + (1 −λ)ȳ2, x̂λ = λx̂1 + (1 −λ)x̂2, ŷλ = λŷ1 + (1 −λ)ŷ2. One can show that max{x̄λ, ȳλ, x̂λ, ŷλ}− min{x̄λ, ȳλ, x̂λ, ŷλ}≤ λz̄ + (1 −λ)ẑ. That is, ((x̄λ, ȳλ), (x̂λ, ŷλ), λz̄ + (1 −λ)ẑ) ∈ epi?f. Therefore, epi?f is a convex set, so we conclude that the function f is also a convex function. Theorem 2.4. Let H = Rn, X1, X2 be convex and compact subsets of H and f(x1 ? y1,x2 ? y2) is a continuous function on X1 × X2. Suppose that for any x2 ? y2 ∈ P∗(X2), f(x1 ? y1,x2 ? y2) be a concave function with respect to x1 ?y1 ∈ P∗(X1) and for any x1 ?y1 ∈ P∗(X1) it is a convex function with respect to x2 ? y2 ∈ P∗(X2). Then, the function f(x1 ? y1,x2 ? y2) has a saddle point. Proof. : At first , we consider the special case that the function f(x1 ?y1,x2 ?y2) be a strictly convex w.r.t x2 ? y2 ∈ P∗(X2). Then, for any x1 ? y1 ∈ P∗(X1), the function f(x1 ? y1,x2 ? y2) obtains its unique minimum on X2 in Y (x1 ? y1). According to previous theorems, we conclude g(x1 ? y1) and Y (x1 ? y1) are continuous function on X1. Suppose that the function g(x1 ? y1) obtains its minimum on X1 in x1 ? y1. We can show that (x1 ? y1,Y (x1 ? y1)) is a saddle point of f(x1 ? y1,x2 ? y2) on X1×X2. Let x1 ?y1 ∈ P∗(X1) be arbitrary, 0 < λ < 1 and Y = Y ([(1−λ)x1 +λx1]?[(1−λ)y1 +λy1]). According to concavity of the function f(x1 ? y1,x2 ? y2) with respect to x1 ? y1 ∈ P∗(X1), we have (1 −λ)g(x1 ? y1) + λf(x1 ? y1,Y ([(1 −λ)x1 + λx1] ? [(1 −λ)y1 + λy1])) ≤ (1 −λ)f(x1 ? y1,Y ([(1 −λ)x1 + λx1] ? [(1 −λ)y1 + λy1])) +λf(x1 ? y1,Y ([(1 −λ)x1 + λx1] ? [(1 −λ)y1 + λy1])) ≤ f([(1 −λ)x1 + λx1] ? [(1 −λ)y1 + λy1],Y ([(1 −λ)x1 + λx1] ? [(1 −λ)y1 + λy1])) = g([(1 −λ)x1 + λx1] ? [(1 −λ)y1 + λy1]) ≤ g(x1 ? y1). Therefore, λf(x1 ?y1,Y ([(1−λ)x1 + λx1] ? [(1−λ)y1 + λy1])) ≤ λg(x1 ?y1). Divided by λ and it tends to zero, we have the following inequalities: f(x1 ? y1,Y (x1 ? y1)) ≤ g(x1 ? y1) = f(x1 ? y1,Y (x1 ? y1)) ≤ f(x1 ? y1,x2 ? y2), for all x1, y1 ∈ X1 and x2, y2 ∈ X2. In general we consider the following perturbed function f�(x1 ?y1,x2 ?y2) = f(x1 ?y1,x2 ?y2) + �h(x2 ?y2) where h(x2 ?y2) is a continuous and strictly convex function on X2. Clearly f�(x1 ?y1,x2 ?y2) is a continuous, concave with respect to x1 ?y1 and strictly convex with respect to x2 ? y2 function. Using previous discussion, we have f�(x1 ? y1,x � 2 ? y � 2) ≤ f�(x � 1 ? y � 1,x � 2 ? y � 2) ≤ f�(x � 1 ? y � 1,x2 ? y2), (2.7) for all x1, y1 ∈ X1 and x2, y2 ∈ X2. Let � = �k in the inequalities (7) and �k → 0+. Because of compactness of X1 and X2, we conclude that x � 1 ? y � 1 → x1 ? y1 and x�2 ? y�2 → x2 ? y2. Therefore, (x1 ? y1,x2 ? y2) is a saddle point of the function f(x1 ? y1,x2 ? y2). � 3. Applications In this section, we consider some examples in game theory and explain our theory in the previous section. ALGEBRAIC HYPER-STRUCTURES ASSOCIATED TO NASH EQUILIBRIUM POINT AND APPLICATIONS 25 3.1. Examples. The following examples show that, how we can use Nash equilibrium point in practice. First of all, we show that the Nash equilibrium point gives a generalization of usual optimization problem. Example 3.1. Since the optimization problem is a special case of the game theory with one player, so we obtain the optimization model as follows: f1(x1 ? y1) 6 f1(x1 ? y1), for all x1 ? y1 ∈ P∗(X1). This means that x1 ? y1 ∈ Argmin{f(x1 ? y1) : x1 ? y1 ∈ P∗(X1)}. Example 3.2. Let H = {f ∈ C|f : R → R} and X1, X2 ⊆ H, where X1 and X2 are such continuous functions that have left and right inverse. We define the following function. f1(g,h) = ∫ Dg ⋂ Dh [(g −h)(x)]2dx, where g and h are the left and right inverse of an arbitrary function and Dg and Dh are the domains of g and h, respectively. Let f2(g,h) = −f1(g,h). Clearly (g,g) = (f,f) is a saddle point, i.e., the left and right inverse are the same. 3.2. Numerical Examples. Example 3.3. In Example 3, we define X1 = {(x, 0) : 0 ≤ x ≤ M}, X2 = {(0,y) : 0 ≤ y ≤ N}. Clearly, X1, X2 are compact and convex subsets of H. According to Example 3, the function h(x1?y1) = zmax−zmin = max{x11,x21} and e(x2?y2) = zmax−zmin = max{y12,y22}, where x1 = (x11, 0), y1 = (x 2 1, 0), x2 = (0,y 1 2), y2 = (0,y 2 2), x1, y1 ∈ X1, x2, y2 ∈ X2 are convex functions. Let f(x1 ? y1, x2 ? y2) = e(x2 ? y2) −h(x1 ? y1). We can show that the function f(x1 ? y1,x2 ? y2) is a continuous, concave function with respect to x1?y1) ∈ P∗(X1) and convex function with respect to x2?y2) ∈ P∗(X2). Therefore, the all assumptions of Theorem (2.11) has been held. Clearly, {(x1 ? y1,x2 ? y2) : max{x11,x21} = max{y12,y22}} is the set of saddle points of the function f(x1 ? y1,x2 ? y2) on X1 ×X2. Example 3.4. Let define H = R and X1 = X2 = H, x ? y = [min{x,y},max{x,y}], f(x1 ? y1,x2 ? y2) = (x 2 2 + y 2 2) − (x 2 1 + y 2 1), for all x1, y1 ∈ X1 and x2, y2 ∈ X2. In this example, X1, X2 are not compact subset of H. We choose x1 = y1 = x2 = y2 = 0. Then, x1 ? y1 = {0}, x2 ? y2 = {0} and f({0},{0}) = 0. Therefore, (x1 ? y1,x2 ? y2) = ({0},{0}) is a saddle point, that is f(x1 ? y1,x2 ? y2) = −(x21 + y 2 1) ≤ f(x1 ? y1,x2 ? y2) = 0 ≤ f(x1 ? y1,x2 ? y2) = (x 2 2 + y 2 2), for all x1, y1 ∈ X1 and x2, y2 ∈ X2. Thus, Theorem (2.11) is a sufficient condition. References [1] P. Corsini, Prolegomena of Hypergroup Theory, Second edition, Aviani Editore, 1993. [2] P. Corsini and V. Leoreanu, Applications of Hyperstructure Theory, Advances in Mathematics, Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrecht, 2003. [3] I. Cristea and M. Stefanescu, Hypergroups and n-ary relations, Eur. J. Comb. 31 (2010), 780-789. [4] B. Davvaz, A. Dehghan Nezhad and A. Benvidi, Chemical hyperalgebra: Dismutation reactions, MATCH Commun. Math. Comput. Chem. 67 (2012) 55-63. [5] B. Davvaz, A. Dehghan Nezhad and A. Benvidi, Chain reactions as experimental examples of ternary algebraic hyperstructures, MATCH Commun. Math. Comput. Chem. 65 (2011) 491-499. [6] B. Davvaz and V. Leoreanu-Fotea, Hyperring Theory and Applications, International Academic Press, USA, 2007. [7] A. Dehghan Nezhad and B. Davvaz, Universal hyperdynamical systems, Bull. Korean Math. Soc. 47 (2010), 513-526. [8] A. Delavar Khalafi and B.Davvaz, Algebraic hyper-structures associated to convex analysis and applications, Filomat 26 (2012) 55-65. [9] A. Delavarkhalafi Solution methods for equilibrium points in bileaner non-zero sum games, Ph.D. Thesis (2002) (In Russian). [10] M. Ghadiri, B. Davvaz and R. Nekouian, Hv-Semigroup structure on F2-offspring of a gene pool, Int. J. Biomath. 5 (2012), Art. ID 1250011. [11] S. Hošková and J. Chvalina, Discrete transformation hypergroups and transformation hypergroups with phase tolerance space, Discre. Math. 308 (2008), 4133-4143. 26 DELAVAR KHALAFI AND DAVVAZ [12] V. Leoreanu-Fotea, B. Davvaz, Fuzzy hyperrings, Fuzzy Sets and Syst. 160 (2009), 2366-2378. [13] T. Vougiouklis, Hyperstructures and Their Representations, Hadronic Press, Florida, 1994. Department of Mathematics, Yazd University, Yazd, Iran ∗Corresponding author: davvaz@yazd.ac.ir 1. Introduction and preliminaries 2. Game Theory 3. Applications 3.1. Examples 3.2. Numerical Examples References