INTERSTICES 08 43

Introduction

The concepts of the coming community, which we discover in Giorgio Agamben’s 
work, and of a future people, treated by Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari in What is  
Philosophy?, appear to be utopian formulations of community. They seem to forestall,  
indefinitely, the arrival or satisfaction of community, making it an impossible 
project. Yet, to assume the perpetual deferral of the coming community does 
not allow for the ontological and ethical striving that participates, not in a fixed 
idea of community, but in a fluid structure that opens up the possibility for new 
forms of collective sociability. I would like to argue that the striving for a coming  
community, and the formation of a future people, is an ethico-aesthetic activity  
suffused with an affirmative joy that we can associate with Deleuze’s treatment 
of the concept of a life. The insistence on the indefinite article, a life, determines 
that no life in particular can be denominated, but that the singularity of any 
life can participate in community. While admitting that utopia is not the best  
possible word, Deleuze and Guattari stress that utopia as an idea can become useful  
through an active engagement with contemporary geopolitical problems  
(Deleuze and Guattari, 1994: 100); for example, the question of refuge. 

Within the specific limits of the discipline of architecture, how can we frame a  
utopia (no-where) for the problems (now-here) of the present? The architectural 
theorist, Reinhold Martin, has recently speculated on what he calls utopian realism  
as a means of transforming feelings of helplessness. This vision is directed not 
at the distant, inaccessible future, but suggests that in the present things can be  
otherwise (2005: 5). With such a vision of hope in mind, this essay will address 
ways in which the concepts of a coming community, a future people and a life can 
be activated as a practical utopian attitude; an attitude that helps to confront the 
problems of present architectural discourse and production in a globalized world, 
where socio-political relations have become increasingly fraught. This essay cannot  
offer a fixed answer to the question of what kind of architecture will solve the 
problem of a coming community. Instead, what I attempt here is the articulation 
of different philosophical constructions of community, to suggest ways in which 
architecture might reframe its material and theoretical projects.

Striving for a Coming Community
and the Question of a Life

Hélène Frichot



 

INTERSTICES 08 45INTERSTICES 08 45

The Structure of the Coming Community  

The structure of the coming community allows us to address contemporary  
problems, which remain with us as part of our legacy, which demand our attention  
in the present, and which threaten to pass into the future unresolved unless we 
take up their challenge. To do so, we need to think, using creative, conceptual 
processes in the ever mobile and elastic present. As Deleuze suggests: “to think 
means to be embedded in the present-time stratum that serves as a limit: what I 
can see and what I can say today?” He adds: “thought thinks its own history (the 
past), but in order to free itself from what it thinks (the present) and be able finally  
to ‘think otherwise’ (the future)” (1988: 119). To frame a practical philosophy,  
Deleuze turns to 17th century Dutch philosopher, Benedict de Spinoza, for whom 
the theme of a life evolves through the diminution and increase in our power to 
act in a world. The greater our capacity to act, the stronger our force of existence, 
and the more open we are to being affected. Of our relations and acts of creation 
across a common plane of immanence, Deleuze suggests: “it is a long affair of 
experimentation, requiring a lasting prudence” (125).1 The ethico-aesthetic task of 
inventing a new people, and a new future, is never one that can be satisfied once 
and for all.

What is required is the understanding that we are never separate from our 
common world, and that we do not know in advance what we are capable of, 
nor what good or bad compositions of the socio-political we might enter into. 
Deleuze argues that there are “laws of composition and decomposition of  
relations which determine both the coming into existence of modes, and the end 
of their existence” (1990: 211). Every thing, person, institution, comes into being 
through a series of relations, and is transformed in response to encounters, new 
situations and the admixture of further materials and relations. “When a body 
encounters another body, or an idea another idea, it happens that the two relations  
combine to form a more powerful whole, and sometimes one decomposes the 
other, destroying the cohesion of its parts” (1988: 19). From an architectural 
point of view, it is important to apprehend that these compositions are not only  
assembled from the socio-political relations between people, their thoughts and 
actions.2 In the midst of these relations, different kinds of architectural materials  
and surrounds, and different kinds of human and other bodies intermingle.  
Architecture can augment forms-of-life by recognizing that its material is animate  
and inanimate, made up not only of steel, concrete and glass, but also of the  
social relations between people. New compositions arise through explorative  
experimentation. Existence becomes an ethical test, though not to determine what 
is right or wrong. Rather, it determines whether life is augmented or diminished, 
depending on what compositions it enters into (Deleuze, 1988: 40-41). Whether at 
the scale of the single cell, the human body, the building, or the institution, these 
formations are made coherent by relations and compositions, or decompositions, 
in response to different situations.

Beatitude is a perplexing Spinozist concept, or, rather, a state of being, which is 
of especial importance in Deleuze’s late essay, Immanence: A Life … A life, or that 
which participates in absolute immanence, is said to achieve complete potential,  
and complete beatitude (Deleuze, 2001: 27).3 An entire chapter of Deleuze’s  
Expressionism in Philosophy: Spinoza is dedicated to this important concept, 
which frequently confuses secular audiences. Through the concept of beatitude,  

1. In a similar vein, Agamben insists 
that the concept of a life constitutes  
a pressing problem for a coming  
philosophy, one that can be re- 
turned to a practical calling  
(Agamben, 1999: 238).

2. An alternative term for compo-
sition developed by Deleuze and 
Guattari is assemblage. Different 
assemblages, for instance, machinic  
assemblages and collective assem-
blages of enunciation, combine  
bodies, actions, passions, and 
acts, statements and incorporeal  
transformations respectively. See 
Deleuze and Guattari (1987).

3. In the English translation by 
Anne Boyman, we find the term 
beatitude diluted by being replaced 
with the term, bliss.



INTERSTICES 08 45

 

INTERSTICES 08 45

4. Through the concept of beati- 
tude Deleuze and Guattari de-
scribe how Spinoza gives infinite  
movement to thought : “there he  
attains incredible speeds, with  
such lightening compressions that 
one can only speak of music, of 
tornadoes, of wind and strings” 
(1994: 48).

5. I will not directly address  
Blanchot’s unavowable commu-
nity, which is made in response 
to Nancy. Though Blanchot’s  
murmur might still be heard ask-
ing whether it is possible to belong 
to any community at all, especially 
that community to which we are 
obliged to avow our allegiance.

6. This essay is translated as  
“Beyond Human Rights” in 
Agamben (2000). Its original  
title, “We Refugees”, is inspired  
by an essay written by Hannah  
Arendt, also called “We  
Refugees” (1943). 

Deleuze and Guattari describe how Spinoza gives infinite movement to thought: 
“there he attains incredible speeds, with such lightning compressions that one 
can only speak of music, of tornadoes, of wind and strings” (1994: 48). While 
this paper aspires to arrive at the conceptual moment of beatitude, a turn in 
experience that transports us to an image of thought, it will in all likelihood, 
and perhaps necessarily, fail.4 What I will focus on is the ethical striving for, and 
composition of, the coming community, and a future people, which is driven 
by a striving toward beatitude, or what is also known as Spinoza’s third kind 
of knowledge. To achieve this I will, alongside Agamben, and Deleuze and  
Guattari’s work, pass briskly through Jean-Luc Nancy’s concept of the inopera-
tive community.5 Aside from an orientation directed toward a future, Deleuze,  
Agamben, and Nancy all describe a circulation of singularities in their  
formulations of a community to come. I propose that architecture is at the same 
time composed of singularities, and can be seen as that medium in which further 
singularities co-mingle. 

 
Giorgio Agamben’s Whatever Singularities

Agamben’s coming community is presented to us as a series of fragments, more 
affective than effective in their argumentation. Agamben does not even give a 
description of the coming community, which we are to conceptually place in  
conjunction with a coming philosophy and a coming politics. Instead, he intimates 
that there is no such community, that it is perhaps nowhere, and, as such, utopian. 
The coming community appears to be without a place; what’s more, it appears to 
be a community that has never been. Resisting identification as this or that thing, 
the coming community is patched together out of what Agamben names ‘whatever  
singularities’, co-mingling and without identifiable attributes (Agamben, 1993: 
85). A difficulty arises here with respect to what can be said about architecture if 
it cannot be ascribed attributes. 

The ‘whatever singularities’ composing Agamben’s coming community own no 
common ground, no set of beliefs or practices that conjoin them; they merely  
appropriate belonging as such, according to a structure of being-such (1993: 2). 
Agamben argues that this is the greatest threat the coming community can level 
against the state-apparatus. If the state has no means to identify the outlines of this 
community, how can it placate, order and contain it? We might add that this does not 
necessarily stop the state from denominating identity. For instance, a community  
of suspect others may be manufactured on the basis of perceived threat, as in the 
war against terror, or in the treatment of refugees in the Australian context. In 
contrast, the striving for a coming community requires that the citizen learn to 
acknowledge the refugee that he or she is. In We Refugees,6 Agamben goes so far 
as to suggest that our political survival depends on the recognition that we are 
all, in one way or another, refugees: “The refugee is perhaps the only thinkable  
figure for the people of our time and the only category in which we may see 
today … the forms and limits of a coming political community” (2000: 16). We 
slowly realize that the so-called citizen has, in a global state of exception, or 
emergency, become as vulnerable as the refugee. 

Agamben asks us to look in the direction of the camp and the figure of the refugee  
(rather than the nation-state and the figure of the citizen) to begin to imagine 



 

INTERSTICES 08 47INTERSTICES 08 47

a community to come (2000: 16). But how might we begin to imagine a coming 
community which – as Mark Holland suggests regarding Blanchot’s concept of 
community – may “never constitute a community except in this mode of ‘yet to 
be’”? (1996: 188). The formulation of a coming community as a state for which we 
might yearn, but which remains always just out of grasp, only appears to deny the 
very immanent particularities of a here and now. The permanent flux inherent in 
the concept of a coming community is akin to becoming, that is, a transformative  
metamorphosis that draws us into the sphere of life, so that new forms-of-life 
might be created. Architecture can contribute here, not so much in terms of fixed  
attributes of durability, beauty, or utility, but by opening up a flexible and responsive  
material field for new forms-of-life to emerge. Encompassing an intimate  
relationship with the present as it passes, and expanding into the past as into the 
future, the coming community does not have to be located in an evasive ‘yet to 
be’. Finally, the coming philosophy must take the concept of life, or a life, as its  
pressing concern (Agamben, 1999: 238).

 
Jean-Luc Nancy’s Singular Plural Being

In contrast, Nancy’s coming community has always already arrived. Paradoxically,  
this does not mean that the necessity of heeding its coming is in any way  
diminished. In his essay The Inoperative Community, Nancy argues against the most 
ancient myth of the Western world: the conception of a lost community as a lost 
capacity after which we still yearn (1991: 9). For Agamben, the coming community 
has never been; for Nancy, community has never been lost, and there is no such 
person as the one who has nothing in common. Even in the extreme context of 
the concentration or extermination camp, where we discover the “will to destroy  
community”, we can also discover resistance (35). From time to time, such resistance  
has become visible in Australian refugee camps; for instance, through acts of  
arson, hunger strikes, lip sewing, or successful and unsuccessful attempts at escape.

Nancy identifies community as a “resistance to immanence” (1991: 35): “It is  
precisely the immanence of man to man, or it is man, taken absolutely, considered  
as immanent being par excellence, that constitutes the stumbling block to a  
thinking of community” (1991: 3). This move away from immanence seems to 
pit Nancy against Deleuze. However, the immanence Nancy critiques places the  
human subject at its centre. On Deleuze’s plane of immanence, neither subject 
nor object is given prominence, but relations between different moments of  
becoming appear briefly only to fade away again. Nancy’s community is about 
compearing: an event of singularities, or singular beings, appearing together,  
a co-appearance that exposes us to our very finitude (1991: 28). Equally, it  
depends on the concept of partage, a sharing out or division of singular being: “at 
the limit, the exposition of singular beings to one another and the pulse of this  
exposition: the compearance, the passage, and the divide of sharing” (1991: 38). 
An incomplete passage of sharing conjoins at the same time as it splits us apart, 
by turn distinguishing us, and making us indistinguishable. Nancy calls this 
an “exposing-sharing” (29), that is, the paradoxical construction of the singular  
plural. Nancy’s community, which has never been lost, while at the same time 
never achieving completion, participates in a coming: “And what remains thus, 
or what is coming and does not stop coming as what remains, is what we call 
existence” (Nancy, 1997: 132). As such, the passage of the coming community  



INTERSTICES 08 47

 

INTERSTICES 08 47

remains inconclusive (35). Importantly, community is not a work to be produced, 
though it might be imagined through the creative impulses of writing, art or  
architecture. These creative practices should not be concerned with erecting 
monuments, but with facilitating action for the time being. For instance, in a 
striving for community, the monumentalizing impulse of architecture would 
have to be redirected to more provisional ends. Despite his questioning of  
immanence, Nancy shares with Deleuze a belief in the emancipatory promise of 
the creative act, as well as a formulation of community that does not anticipate 
a moment of completion. In unison with Agamben, Nancy is also insistent that 
community owns no essential attributes, but, instead, is an ongoing activity.7

 
The Ethico-Aesthetic Practice of Concept Creation

Like Nancy, Deleuze and Guattari believe that what a future people have in common  
is resistance: “their resistance to death, to servitude, to the intolerable, to shame 
and to the present” (1994: 110). Importantly, a resistance to capture, in a movement  
of absolute deterritorialization (101), provides the potential for a new earth 
and a new people. Deleuze and Guattari use the concept of utopia as a figure  
of political promise, as a critical point from which the present milieu can  
consider itself and its pressing problems. They appropriate Samuel Butler’s  
formulation of Erewhon (utopia) to designate not only no-where, but also now-here: 
the patch of new earth where we can pitch our tent for the meantime. A provisional  
architecture, modest in its aspirations and durable only for as long as the  
immediate circumstances dictate, could provide a space of potential for this kind 
of realist utopia.

The coming community of a future people circulates around the construction of 
new concepts and the identification of contemporary problems. Unlike Nancy’s  
inoperative community, it seems to have work to do. Deleuze and Guattari tell us  
that a concept is acquired by “inhabiting, by pitching one’s tent, by contracting a  
habit” (1994: 105), but concepts can also be repulsive, and some tents become  
despicable in their distribution and use. Concepts, much like built archi- 
tectural forms, can create life possibilities but can also restrict forms-of-life.  
In any event, the creation of concepts calls for a place where philosophy  
and art, life and concept can converge, a place to which we can proceed  
according to a practical, ethico-aesthetics and where the coming community  
can engage in what Deleuze describes as “the problem of the work of art yet  
to come” (Deleuze, 1990: 248). This work must constantly resist the  
deadliness of banality, and the insistence of opinion and cliché. We can  
work through the power of concept creation as an ethico-aesthetic activity,  
but first we must increase our power so that we are capable of creative activity. 

One of the most radical aspects of Deleuze and Guattari’s creative philosophy is 
that concept creation – as well as the construction of affects and percepts of art, 
the propositions or functions of science, even the framing capacity of architecture 
– constitutes ethical and properly political activity. Foucault wrote of Deleuze and 
Guattari’s first collaborative work, Anti-Oedipus, that it was a work of ethics, the 
first book of ethics to be written in France for quite a long time (1983: xiii). The last 
book Deleuze and Guattari collaborated on was What is Philosophy?. In pursuing 
the restless question of the title late in their lives, they were not merely reflecting 

7. The temporal orientation of 
Deleuze and Guattari’s future 
people, or a people to come, also 
sets us upon a passage toward the 
future, but with less passivity than 
evinced by Nancy. Parenthetically, 
Michael Hardt and Antonio Negri 
argue in their influential book, 
Empire, that Deleuze and Guattari 
have not gone far enough here. 
They suggest that the pair manage 
to articulate a future people “only 
superficially and ephemerally, as 
a chaotic, indeterminate horizon 
marked by the ungraspable event” 
(Hardt and Negri, 2000: 28).



 

INTERSTICES 08 49INTERSTICES 08 49

on lives well lived, but laying out a new plan for ethical becoming. In Deleuze and 
Guattari’s shared project, creativity and ethical activity operate simultaneously.  
Their project requires a double becoming, a zone of exchange between philosophy 
and non-philosophy that enables the constitution of a people to come, and a new 
earth (1994: 109). Though, at first, the temporal structure of the coming community  
might appear to require perpetual deferral, the ontological and ethico-aesthetic  
striving we experience toward the constitution of community should not be  
under-estimated.8 

In response to Deleuze’s essay, Immanence: A Life …, Agamben argues that  
Deleuze’s attempts to account for a life remain thwarted. A life is not something 
that can be represented, only intimated. A life is impossible to approach directly, 
for it shies from our face-to-face confrontation. Yet, something happens on the  
approach to this question that is inextricably interconnected with the problem 
of a coming community, a future people and a new earth. With respect to the  
question of a life, Deleuze writes: “the life of the individual gives way to an im- 
personal and yet singular life that releases a pure event freed from the accidents  
of internal and external life” (2001: 28). However, we should not forget that  
the “singularities and the events that constitute a life coexist with the accidents  
of the life that corresponds to it” (2001: 29).9 Our passivity and our passions, the 
life we lead, make up the necessary length of the passage toward community, and 
toward the profound stillness of Spinoza’s third kind of knowledge, beatitude. 
For Nancy, this passivity is non-productive; for Deleuze (after Spinoza), we find it 
is a matter of progressing from passive to active affections by conjoining life and  
concepts; that is, it is a matter of becoming active and creating concepts that enable 
us to enact very material tests on the world in which we are immersed. 

Deleuze and Guattari suggest that the passage from joyful passive affections to 
active affections (Spinoza), or from the inadequate (yet adequate enough) ideas 
and images of the imagination to the adequate ideas of reason,10 is more akin to 
the uncoordinated leaps of a dog than the explanations of a reasonable person. 
Caught up in haphazard movements, we proceed through an apprenticeship, 
which advances in a futural direction not only toward an increase in the power of 
corporeal and intellectual being, but toward the construction of signs of art that 
help inaugurate the emergence of another world. Thus, we take a passage that 
will eventually lead us toward Spinoza’s beatitude, as a third kind of knowledge,  
and through a network of passages along which one becomes, in turn, both lost 
and found. We will always find ourselves amidst sad and joyful passions. Power  
constitutes a passage, or point of conversion, the capacity to shift from  
passions to actions at a moment where ”we stop striving to think the world 
and begin to create it” (Hardt, 1993: 59). We – however this ‘we’ is differentially  
composed – arrive at a hiatus of sorts, a pause in our striving, only to continue again 
into the active creation or construction of concepts, an ethico-aesthetic activity  
that is fundamental to the ongoing creation of community. Finally, the task is  
never complete; neither is community, as such, identified through determined  
attributes. By striving to create new kinds of social relations, and new forms-of-life  
in relation to environmental situations, community perpetually unfolds.

8. Passive, though passionate 
passage.

9. Community incorporates  
singularities in corporeal mixtures  
and through the circulation of  
incorporeal effects. For Agamben 
these are whatever singularities, 
for Nancy they are singular beings,  
or singular plural beings as distinct  
from individuals. Finally, for  
Deleuze, singularities are less to 
do with singular beings, as they 
contribute to both physical states 
of affairs and to incorporeal,  
immaterial events: “Singularities 
are turning points and points of 
inflection: bottlenecks, knots,  
foyers, and centers; points of  
fusion, condensation, and boiling 
points; points of tears and joy, 
sickness and health, hope and  
anxiety, ‘sensitive points’” (1990: 
52). Singularities are not to be 
confused with the individual, 
the subject or the object. For 
instance, Deleuze tells us that 
very small children, who might 
be viewed on the one hand as all 
alike, have singularities, “a smile, a 
gesture, a funny face”(2001: 30). 
Singularities are turning points  
between affections and processes 
of creation and contribute as much 
to the constitution of community 
as they do to the question of a life. 
Manuel Delanda, commenting on 
Deleuze, insists upon a scientific  
account of singularities that takes 
us back to Henri Poincaré (2002: 
14, 15). Singularities, for Delanda, 
suggest the long-term tendencies  
of a given system and lead to new 
ways of viewing the genesis of 
physical forms. While Delanda’s  
definition might prove reassuring 
to some, it is worthwhile remem-
bering that even if the genealogy 
of Deleuze’s use of the concept 
of singularities can be returned 
to mathematics and geometry, 
the philosopher is far more  
interested in what concepts can 
do once placed in contemporary  
assemblages.

10. As well as the parallel passage  
of thought (mind) and extension  
(body), and the parallel  
movement of theory and practice.



INTERSTICES 08 49

 

INTERSTICES 08 49

The Architectural Problem of the Contemporary Refugee Camp

As an ethical test of our existence, and the ramifications of our modes of being  
and becoming, we can begin to apply the above to real spatial coordinates. As  
Deleuze explains, this is not a moral test, but rather like the way in which “workmen  
check the quality of some material” (1990: 317). Ethics, in this context, is opposed 
to moral judgment, which determines in advance, according to a fixed code or 
imperative to act, how a situation will be assessed (Deleuze, 1988: 40). Applying 
the ethical test of existence is a difficult task, for there are no clear assessment 
criteria; we are grappling with contemporary problems in the midst of things. 
We are to remain attuned to how we affect others, and are affected in turn, and 
that we are never separable from our relations in and with a world. Agamben  
expressly includes the refugee in the midst of this ‘we’, and Deleuze allows not 
just for human, but animal and other bodies. In addition, Martin points out that: 
“we cannot use the pronoun ‘we’ to denote a self-consistent, geographically, 
culturally, or economically unified agent” (2006: 15). Any coming community is 
composed of diverse relations, compositions and decompositions. It is a matter 
of aspiring toward the best possible composition, given the situation at hand.

From the midst of things, which situates us upon a plane of immanence, the  
Australian processing and reception centre, that country’s  local rendition of a  
refugee camp, presents a contemporary problem. It could be argued that  
the camp does not constitute a problem in the arena of architectural en- 
deavour. On the contrary, I would insist that it is part of the task of architecture  
to recognize the extent of the imbrication of the built environment  
with modes of life. The body, in its compositions, can be thought of in spatial  
terms; that is, that the body includes the coordinates of the architecture  
through which it moves. Within architecture it may discover itself  
captured in a bad composition, one that leads to its disintegration, or its  
decomposition. 

If the desert camp at Woomera, South Australia, was a bad composition,  
the Immigration Processing and Reception Centre at Baxter, in the same state, is  
even worse. From the relative appearance of temporariness at Woomera  
(composed of so many tents and reterritorialized existing military infra- 
structures), a permanent and rigid, spatial structure has evolved at Baxter.  
This purpose-built desert camp, five hours drive from Adelaide,  
is arranged as a series of nine rectilinear compounds with chamfered corners,  
expressing a spare architecture. Further, each compound is organized around  
a grassed courtyard, turning upon its own independent universe, operating  
in isolation even from the desert setting. The detainees are further fragmented,  
isolated into groups based on gender, ethnicity, or on whether they can 
be collected in a family group, or whether they are a threat to themselves  
and others. The community composed here is arranged so as to form  
non-communicating cells, and attributes are forced upon the inmates as  
ready-made templates inhibiting active community formation. Relations between 
peoples and spaces is regulated and coagulated. The fragile compositions formed 
are apt to decompose. 

Similar socio-political, and very real, material compositions, are also to be found 
in the midst of Australian cities; for example, in the suburban camps of Villawood 



 

INTERSTICES 08 51INTERSTICES 08 51

(Sydney) and Maribyrnong (Melbourne). They exemplify Agamben’s intimation 
that the contemporary city is increasingly indistinguishable from the camp. At the 
end of tramline 57, the Maribyrnong Immigrant Detention Centre (MIDC), currently 
the only federal detention centre in Victoria, is set in the gradually, but obviously, 
gentrifying and redeveloping suburb of Maribyrnong. The briefest of histories of 
the site reveals different successive compositions, which suggest ways in which a 
coming community is either welcomed or rejected from within the body politic. 
Initially, the site was home to British and other migrants who used the original 
Maribyrnong Migrant Hostel as a transitory refuge before establishing a permanent  
home in Melbourne. In sharp contrast, the detention facilities today occupy a 
small wedge of land, a much reduced area of the former allotment. The larger 
part of the original site, now owned by Victoria University, houses a somewhat 
ramshackle student village into which the historic buildings have been seamlessly  
transformed. On either side of a high security wall, mandatory detention and  
student accommodation are set in a curious adjacency, while the land to the west 
is being developed into a housing estate. 

Inside the razor wire fence of the camp, building works continue to cramp the 
living conditions of the mostly invisible inmates (see Frichot, 2006). An ethical 
test applied to the potential composition of a coming community fails here on a 
number of counts. The camp is spatially segregated, which means that singularities  
are rendered immobile, thwarting the promise of new expressions of subjectivity.  
The identity of the camp’s inmates is over-determined; they are figured as  
unwanted others, and a possible threat to the broader community. The potential 
of the coming community, as it pertains to the Australian context, is diminished 
exactly through this architectural process of exclusion and stigmatization. Thus, 
the camp reflects directly on the Australian body politic, negatively determining  
its attributes. However, this reflection is difficult to perceive for much of the body 
politic, due to successful attempts to render this suburban camp invisible. The  
architecture is resolutely non-descript, without expression, generally blank where 
it faces the outside world. The entire complex is set back from major roads and 
hidden from view. 

From its inception as a migrant hostel after World War Two, to its present day 
composition of student village and detention centre (the latter surrounded by a 
double layer of fence and under constant electronic surveillance), the architecture  
of the site reflects the political attitude at our current socio-political juncture (see 
Frichot, 2006). It is important to remember that architecture never acts alone in 
such instances; it remains entangled with the actions effectuated by government  
policy, material infrastructures existing and new, the migrations of peoples, 
emerging subjectivities and so forth. Relations that circulate amidst a future 
people and a coming community have the potential to allow for the creation  
of socio-political compositions that augment life. In contrast, a composition 
such as the Australian camp generally removes the capacity to create, and  
particularly to imagine and create new forms of sociability and community. 
As Martin suggests, the architectural imagination needs to remain open to the 
promise that this is not the only possible world, and certainly not the best of all  
possible worlds (2006: 15). How might architecture, as a specific set of activities, 
create more positive compositions?



INTERSTICES 08 51

 

INTERSTICES 08 51

In the situation of the contemporary refugee camp, we discover the maximum 
of sad encounters, not just on the part of the asylum seeker, but on the part 
of those who seek to capture, contain and isolate them, even from their fellow  
inmates. Thus, the question of the composition of the camp, which decomposes  
the singularities captured within its confines, and impacts upon the ways in 
which a coming community might be imagined, becomes an ethical question 
in the Australian socio-political context today. Therefore, the test is how to  
concatenate joyful passions, passions that may facilitate common notions that 
orient active affections or joys toward the positive power of creation and even 
beatitude. The architectural theorist, Martin, has suggested two simple tasks for 
architecture: one aesthetic and the other territorial. Architects have the capacity 
to participate in the aesthetic creation of new built environments that participate  
in new forms of community. Likewise, architecture can participate in the  
reconsideration of territorial boundaries that presently dispossess those on the 
inside as well as those on the outside (Martin, 2006: 21). Yet, there can be no 
hard and fast moral or ethical rules, as these work against the possibility of  
responding to the particularities of each new encounter as it presents itself. Hardt 
suggests that Deleuze “posed the common notion and its process of assemblage 
as part of an ethical project (becoming active, becoming adequate, becoming 
joyful)”; but, he asks, “how can we recognize this project in properly political 
terms?” (Hardt, 1993: 108). If only we could learn to create our mixtures, and 
form our compositions with some confidence, for as Spinoza frequently reminds 
us, we are more apt to sad passions. Success or not, it is important to recognize 
that there are no lasting instructions toward the best possible way of composing  
community, nor of composing an architecture that responds to the promise of 
a future people. And since there is never just one approach to a happy life, a 
form-of-life, a people, a community, our compositions depend on a combination  
of chance and necessity. We will always wind up with something different, 
something that could not have been imagined beforehand, for we do not know 
in advance what we are capable of, nor what good or bad compositions of the 
socio-political we might enter into.

 
References

Agamben, G. (1993). The Coming Community (M. Hardt, Trans.). Minneapolis: University 
of Minnesota Press.

Agamben, G. (1995). “We Refugees”. Symposium (49) 2, 114-120.

Agamben, G. (1999). Potentialities (D. Heller-Roazen, Trans.). Stanford (Cal.): Stanford  
University Press.

Agamben, G. (2000). Means Without Ends: Notes on Politics (V. Binetti & C. Casarino, Trans.). 
Minneapolis: Minnesota University Press.

Arendt, H. (1943). “We Refugees”. The Menorah Journal (3).

Blanchot, M. (1988). The Unavowable Community (P. Joris, Trans.). Barrytown (NY): Station 
Hill Press. 

De Cauter, L. (2004). The Capsular Civilization (P. Bouvier, Trans.). Rotterdam: NAi Publishers.

Delanda, M. (2002). Intensive Science and Virtual Philosophy. New York: Continuum.

Deleuze, G. (1988). Foucault (S. Hand, Trans.). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota 
Press.

 



 

INTERSTICES 08 PB

Deleuze, G. (1988). Spinoza Practical Philosophy (R. Hurley, Trans.). San Francisco: City Lights 
Books.

Deleuze, G. (1990). Expressionism in Philosophy: Spinoza (M. Joughin, Trans.). New York: 
Zone Books.

Deleuze, G. (2001). Pure Immanence: Essays on a Life (A. Boyman, Trans.). New York: Zone 
Books.

Deleuze, G. and Guattari, F. (1987). A Thousand Plateaus (B. Massumi, Trans.). Minneapolis: 
University of Minnesota Press.

Foucault, M. (1983). Preface. In Deleuze, G. and Guattari, F. Anti-Oedipus: Capitalism and 
Schizophrenia (R. Hurley, M. Seem, and H. R. Lane, Trans.). Minneapolis: University of  
Minnesota Press.

Frichot, H. (2006). The Biopolitical Wall in the Midst of Our City. In S. Basson, J. Stephens, 
T. McMinn, (Eds.). SAHANZ: 2006: Contested Terrains (pp.151-158). Perth, Western Australia: 
University of Curtain. 

Hardt, M. (1993). Gilles Deleuze: An Apprenticeship in Philosophy. Minneapolis: University of 
Minnesota Press.

Hardt, M. and Negri, A. (2000). Empire. Cambridge (Ma.): Harvard University Press.

Holland, Mark, (Ed.). (1996). The Blanchot Reader. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.

Martin, R. (2005). “Critical of What? Toward a New Utopian Realism”. Harvard Design  
Magazine (22 Spring/Summer), 1-5.

Martin, R. (2006). “Moment of Truth”. Log ( 7 Winter/Spring), 15-20.

Mills, C. (2004). Agamben’s Messianic Politics: Biopolitics, Abandonment and Happy Life. 
Contretemps (5, December), 42-62.

Nancy, J-L. (1991). The Inoperative Community (P. Conner, L. Garbus, M. Holland & S. Sawhney, 
Trans.). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

Nancy, J-L. (1997). The Sense of the World (J. S. Librett, Trans.). Minneapolis: University of 
Minnesota Press.

Sorkin, M. (Ed.). (2005). Against the Wall, New York: The New Press.