LEAP 3 2015 LAW, ETHICS AND PHILOSOPHY LEAP Eric BlumEnson Harry BrigHousE Paula casal micHaEl Da silva ana DE miguEl luara FErracioli anca gHEaus JEsÚs mora valEria oTTonElli gina scHouTEn saraH sTrouD aDam swiFT vicTor TaDros PiErrE-ÉTiEnnE vanDammE PHiliPPE van PariJs anDrEw williams Law, Ethics and Philosophy (LEAP) LEAP is a new peer-reviewed, open access international journal dedicated to work in ethics, legal theory, and social and political philosophy. It welcomes clear, rigorous and original submissions that address concrete issues of public concern as well as more abstract theoretical questions. It also has the distinctive aims of (a) fostering work drawing on a variety of disciplines within the social and natural sciences, including biology, economics, history, and psychology; and (b) promoting dialogue between the Anglophone and non-Anglophone worlds. We invite submissions of articles up to 10,000 words, discussion notes up to 5,000 words, and replies and exchanges not exceeding 3,000 words. All published submissions will have undergone blind review, and the journal will notify authors of submitted pieces about the progress of their submission within six weeks. Although LEAP accepts exclusively submissions in English, the journal strongly encourages submissions f rom authors who also w rite in languages other than English, and will always strive to ensure that their work is assessed on the basis of its content and not primarily its mode of expression. Where necessary the editorial process provides authors with guidance regarding matters of English style. The journal is published by Pompeu Fabra University and hosted by RACO, the Catalan repository of open access journals (http://raco.cat/index.php/leap) Enquiries regarding the journal may be directed to: leap.journal@upf.edu. http://raco.cat/index.php/leap mailto:%20leap.journal%40upf.edu?subject= Law, Ethics and Philosophy Vol. 3 2015 Law, Ethics and PhilosophyLEAP Editorial Board Editors Paula Casal, ICREA & Pompeu Fabra University Iñigo González-Ricoy, University of Barcelona José Luis Martí, Pompeu Fabra University Serena Olsaretti, ICREA & Pompeu Fabra University Hugo Seleme, National University of Córdoba, Argentina Andrew Williams, ICREA & Pompeu Fabra University Associate Editors Ingvild Almås, Norwegian School of Economics Samantha Besson, Fribourg University Jordi Ferrer, University of Girona Ernesto Garzón Valdés, Johannes Gutenberg University, Mainz Cristina Lafont, Northwestern University Genoveva Martí, ICREA & University of Barcelona Lukas Meyer, University of Graz José Juan Moreso, Pompeu Fabra University Félix Ovejero, University of Barcelona Zofia Stemplowska, University of Oxford Editorial Board Aulis Aarnio, Tampere University Lucy Allais, University of the Witwatersrand Elizabeth Anderson, University of Michigan Richard Arneson, University of California, San Diego Gustaf Arrhenius, Stockholm University Michael Baurmann, University of Düsseldorf Juan Carlos Bayón, Autonomous University, Madrid Carmen Bevia, Autonomous University, Barcelona David Bilchitz, South African Institute for Advanced Constitutional, Public, Human Rights, and International Law Geoffrey Brennan, University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill Ian Carter, University of Pavia Joseph Chan, University of Hong Kong Thomas Christiano, University of Arizona Bruno Celano, University of Palermo Antony Duff, University of Minnesota John Ferejohn, New York University Víctor Ferreres, Pompeu Fabra University Roberto Gargarella, University of Buenos Aires Robert Goodin, Australian National University Axel Gosseries, University of Louvain Lori Gruen, Wesleyan University Riccardo Guastini, Genova University Alon Harel, Hebrew University of Jerusalem Daniel Hausman, University of Wisconsin- Madison János Kis, Central European University Matthew Kramer, University of Cambridge David Lefkowitz, University of Richmond Kasper Lippert-Rasmussen, Aarhus University Frank Lovett, Washington University in St. Louis Stephen Macedo, Princeton University Jeff McMahan, Rutgers University Jane Mansbridge, Harvard University Adèle Mercier, Queens University, Ontario Liam Murphy, New York University Ingmar Persson, University of Gothenburg Philip Pettit, Princeton University Thomas Pogge, Yale University Wlodek Rabinowicz, Lund University Joseph Raz, Columbia University Debra Satz, Stanford University Julian Savulescu, University of Oxford Seana Shiffrin, University of California, Los Angeles Anna Stilz, Princeton University Victor Tadros, University of Warwick Larry Temkin, Rutgers University Jeffrey Tulis, University of Texas at Austin Philippe Van Parijs, University of Louvain Georgia Warnke, University of California, Riverside Ruth Zimmerling, Johannes Gutenberg University Mainz Pompeu Fabra University http://www.raco.cat/index.php/LEAP CONTENTS Law, Ethics and Philosophy (LEAP) Vol. 3, 2015 Page 1. Offsetting the Harms of Extinction .................................................. 8 Michael Da Silva 2. The Limits of Moral Argument: Reason and Conviction in Tadros’ Philosophy of Punishment .............................................. 30 eric BluMenSon 3. Response to Blumenson ................................................................... 56 victor taDroS SyMPOSiuM On PHiLiPPE vAn PARijS’ ‘FOuR PuzzLES On GEndER EquALiTy’ 4. unjust Gender inequalities .............................................................. 74 Paula caSal 5. Four Puzzles on Gender Equality ..................................................... 79 PhiliPPe van PariJS 6. distributive justice and Female Longevity ...................................... 90 Paula caSal 7. Women’s Greater Educational Efforts as a Consequence of inequality ........................................................ 107 JeSÚS Mora 8. do Women Enjoy a Political Advantage? Majority Position and democratic justice ....................................... 116 Pierre-Étienne vanDaMMe Page 9. A Blatant Case of Over-Accommodation .......................................... 125 valeria ottonelli 10. Are unequal incarceration Rates unjust to Men? ........................... 136 Gina Schouten 11. The Rich also Cry .............................................................................. 151 ana De MiGuel 12. Real Freedom for all Women (and Men): A Reply ............................ 161 PhiliPPe van PariJS SyMPOSiuM On HARRy BRiGHOuSE And AdAM SWiFT’S FAMiLy juSTiCE:THE ETHiCS OF PAREnT-CHiLd RELATiOnSHiPS 13. Family values: An introduction ........................................................ 178 anDrew williaMS 14. Egalitarian Family values? ............................................................... 180 Sarah StrouD 15. is There a Right to Parent? ................................................................ 193 anca GheauS 16. Why the Family? ............................................................................... 205 luara Ferracioli 17. Advantage, Authority, Autonomy and Continuity: A Response to Ferracioli, Gheaus and Stroud .................................. 220 harry BriGhouSe & aDaM SwiFt Acknowledgments We wish to acknowledge the help of Marcos Picchio, Laura Sánchez de la Sierra and Hannah Weber in proofreading the papers of this volume, also to John French for typesetting. The symposium on Harry Brighouse’s and Adam Swift’s Family Values and The Ethics of Parent-Child Relationships was funded by Serena Olsaretti’s ERC Consolidator Grant (648610) on Justice and the Family: An Analysis of the Normative Significance of Procreation and Parenthood in a Just Society. Funding was also provided by the Department of Law at Pompeu Fabra University. LEAP 3 (2015) Offsetting the Harms of Extinction1 M iCH A E L dA Si LvA University of Toronto ABSTRACT Many people assume that the extinction of humanity would be a bad thing. this article scrutinizes this apparent badness and demonstrates that on most plausible consequentialist frameworks, the extinction of humanity is not necessarily bad. the best accounts of the badness of the extinction of humanity focus on the loss of potential utility, but this loss can be offset if it is the result of sufficiently large gains by the present generation. Plausible mea ns of ca lcu lat i ng t he good ness of outcomes accord i ng ly sug gest hastening extinction even in some circumstances where the alternative is a long period of human existence at a high level. Keywords ethics, consequentialism, existential risk, harms, extinction introDuction Many fear the potential extinction of humanity due to the common intuition that extinction is bad and should be avoided.2 yet what it means for extinction to be ‘bad’ is not obvious. this article scrutinizes the apparent badness of extinction. the most plausible candidate explanations for the badness of extinction do not rely on extinction itself being bad but on extinction pairing with other negative effects or forestalling other potential goods. not all extinction scenarios have these implications. extinction is not an impersonal bad and need not be personally bad even if we grant potential persons some moral personhood. extinction is thus not necessarily bad. even imminent extinction may be preferable to the continued existence of humanity for 1 thank you to Derek Parfit and Jeff McMahan for comments on the earliest version of this article, which was drafted for their graduate seminar at rutgers universit y. thank you also to the other students in that course for thoughtful conversations on many issues and to the anonymous reviewers for feedback on more recent drafts. 2 as larry temkin notes, “anything…anyone…writes on this topic should be taken with a large grain of salt” (2008: 193). it is hard to know what the futures below would look like. this may affect intuitions about some cases and the theories used to explain them. ‘extinction’ here refers to the extinction of humanit y. the argument has implications for other extinctions. Offsetting the Harms of Extinction 9 LEAP 3 (2015) very long periods of time on plausible means of calculating the value of outcomes if the extinction is brought about under the right circumstances. once one recognizes that the badness of extinction is reducible to this lost potential utility, confidence in the intuition that imminent extinction is a bad thing that is to be avoided and/or delayed can be challenged on most plausible forms of outcome analysis that take potential utility into account. the lost potential utility of even a large number of future generations living lives that are worth living could be less than the amount of utility accrued by the current generation.3 extinction scenarios thus do not give one reason to choose between competing theories of outcome valuation. the argument for these claims consists of six substantive parts. the first section assesses competing theories of the good and demonstrates that the badness of ex t inct ion is reducible to t he lost potent ia l ut i lit y of f uture generations that could exist but for the extinction (and any negative effects on existing persons). the second section brief ly canvasses the best means of calculating the value of potential utility and outcomes including potential utility. i argue that intuitions that extinction is a bad thing to be avoided and/or delayed are undermined regardless of which mainstream position one takes. on total-, average- or Perfection-based analyses, the badness of extinction can be outweighed if it takes place as a consequence of an act that creates sufficiently good benefits for existing persons. the third and fourth sections demonstrate that this is true in cases where there is a choice between extinction and humanity continuing to experience lives worth living for a short period and cases where the alternative to extinction is humanity continuing to exist with very good lives for very long periods. the f if t h sect ion exa mines t he sig nif ica nce of potent ia l f uture f lourishing generations in the analyses of the badness of outcomes. the final substantive section further defends the approach to extinction above by highlighting how it explains a separate intuition that the death of the last person is not the worst death in the history of humanity. 1. aPProacheS to valuinG eXtinction the claim that extinction is bad could mean several things. this section presents several alternatives and demonstrates weaknesses with many of them by way of defending the relative plausibility of a particular view. the most common view on the value of extinction is probably something like: a. extinction is intrinsically bad. John Broome helpfully explains the structure of this view (but does not 3 ‘utility’ here refers to whatever is valuable in life. those who are queasy about hedon- focused utilitarianism can substitute their own units of measurement. 10 Michael Da Silva LEAP 3 (2015) defend it) (2012: 180-181). contrary to (a), however, there are cases where many would not want to avoid (even near-term) extinction. all-else-being- equal, it is implausible to deny that one should choose extinction now over a million years of people living lives not worth living. Moreover, this position seems confused on terminological grounds. non-existence has no intrinsic features/properties. if the badness of extinction is not intrinsic, it is likely tied to its effects on the amount of utility that is realized in the world. this raises issues in moral mathematics that can be fruitfully explored in extinction cases. one type of value assessment appeals to purely person-affecting principles in which the goodness and badness of outcomes is determined by their effects on persons. the most common response to extinction may be best explained by what Derek Parfit calls the narrow Person-affecting Principle, according to which one of two outcomes cannot be worse if it would be worse for no one (1984: 393-395). common aversive responses to extinction likely stem from imag ined lin ks bet ween suf fering a nd ex t inct ion. in severa l plausible scenarios, painful deaths act as a prelude to full extinction. common responses to such cases support: b. ex t inct ion is bad because t he ef fects on (including ha rms to) existing persons are sufficiently great to render it bad. if extinction were to take place as a result of a disaster that brought untold suffering with few benefits, (b) would be true. But determining whether extinction is necessarily (even comparatively) bad or necessarily includes bad-making features requires sifting out contingent facts. extinction need not include such effects on ex isting persons. a n impartial non-human obser ver interested in utilit y could lament the suffering in (b), but this would not entail lamenting the fact of extinction. if the early deaths are the price for a shorter period of an extreme well-being greater than the amount of well-being expected for any potential extra years of life, it is plausible that early death would not harm them. imagine an extinction case where this is true for all existing persons such that no one currently alive is harmed by extinction. (b) is false in such circumstances and many others. Further, Strict Person-affecting views, which calibrate the goodness of outcomes using the effects on persons alone, tend to have unintuitive determinations about the supposed badness of extinction. on these views, extinction is bad iff the sum of utility of existing people lost by the act of extinction is larger than the sum of the utility gained. this does not always hold true. therefore, Offsetting the Harms of Extinction 11 LEAP 3 (2015) extinction is not always bad here.4 issues with (b) lead theorists to seek other ways in which extinction is a bad thing. one attempt merely modifies the Person-affecting Principle. this implausible approach can be dealt with brief ly. the badness of extinction is often thought to go beyond its effect on the currently living. Some thus suggest that extinction is bad because of its effects on future persons. they explain the badness of extinction by extending the scope of the Person- affecting Principle to include potential future persons who do not exist because humanit y goes extinct prior to their birth. on such v iews, the badness of extinction can be calculated by some mixture of the effects on existent and potential persons, resulting in views like: c. extinction is bad because the effects on potential persons (which do not include direct harms) are sufficiently great to render it bad. and d. extinction is bad because the effects on ex istent and potential persons are sufficiently great to render it bad. these views likely describe the common views of lay persons, but are mistaken. at the time of extinction, potential future persons do not exist and cannot be harmed in the person-affecting sense.5 if potential persons cannot be harmed, future generations are not directly harmed by extinction either. it is not, then, enough to appeal to person-affecting principles about what might be in or against the interests of presently existing people and future people when analyzing outcomes if one wants to salvage the intuition that extinction is always bad. the modified Person-affecting view nonetheless hints at an important point: there is reason to take future generations into accou nt when ma k i ng mora l decisions today a nd t he sense i n wh ich f ut u re persons a re mora l ly releva nt ex pla i ns why we shou ld usua l ly avoid/delay extinction. it is more plausible that the badness of non-existence stems from the fact that the history of the world would be better if extinction came later or never came about. the badness of extinction is impersonal. Jeff McMahan 4 complex Person-a f fecting ca lcu li better demonstrate t he potentia l badness of extinction. James lenman (2002) suggests we care about future generations for selfish reasons (e.g., joy of knowing about future generations analogous to the joy of having children). this const r uct ion i ncludes a persona l bad, but ha rd ly suppor ts t he idea of ex t i nct ion a s a n impersonal bad whose badness extends beyond its effect on persons. Samuel Scheff ler (2013) suggests that the badness of extinction partly stems from the way that it negates our ability to value and thus destroys utilit y in the present and future. these contingencies may be undermined in some cases below. 5 they w ill not ex ist unless we act in certain ways. Slight policy changes produce different future persons. recall Derek Parfit (1984: chapter 16). 12 Michael Da Silva LEAP 3 (2015) (2013) plausibly ties together this impersonal bad and the potential interests of future persons. he suggests that the non-existence of a potential person is an impersonal loss. one cannot care for these persons morally for their own sake. McMahan nonetheless holds that one has a reason to bring a better off person into existence rather than a worse off person, which he suggests implies a reason to bring the better off person into existence rather than no person at a l l. to br i ng a person i nto ex istence is to con fer a “non[-] comparative” benefit on him/her (9). extinction is potentially problematic because it forestalls the granting of many non-comparative benefits and thus produces a history with less utility than a history in which extinction either never takes place or comes much later and non-comparative benefits are bestowed on new persons. the most important implication of McMahan’s view for the extinction case is that there are impersonal reasons to bring people into existence due to the value they will add to the world. the perspective of the aforementioned impartial non-human observer interested in utility is the best point of view from which one can assess the potential badness of extinction. From this perspective, extinction is bad because it forestalls potential utility. Potential persons do not lose something by failing to come into existence. instead, if causing people to exist would be good for them, their not coming into existence is bad despite not being bad for them.6 if these people could have had lives worth liv ing, their non-ex istence is an impersonal loss of value. the lack of benefits is a detriment in the history of the world. comparisons of the utility of worlds with future generations and those without them help identify the bad of extinction: potential utility is not realized in the world where extinction is earlier. one should, then, count the potential future utility of presently non- existent people when choosing between outcomes. this is not because of a duty to potential persons or because existence would be good for them. it is because it is comparatively better to have more utility in a given history than less utility. all-else-being-equal, it is better to bring about an outcome that realizes more of what is now merely potential utilit y than one that rea l i z es less of it . i f we cou nt potent ia l ha r m s i n ou r c a lc u lu s of t he badness of extinction, two plausible views arise. Given the contingency of an extinction scenario harming current individuals, one may adopt a view focused on impersonal loss alone: e. extinction is comparatively bad if the loss of potential utility that would have accrued had the currently living people existed for a longer period of time and had other persons lived in the future is greater than 0. 6 our “moral reason to ensure the existence of future generations is at least in part a moral reason to provide, or not to prevent, the enormous benefits of life for the enormous number of people who might exist in the indefinite future” (McMahan 1986: 335). Offsetting the Harms of Extinction 13 LEAP 3 (2015) yet even the truth of (e) depends on how extinction arises. those interested in utility more broadly should take account of the utility of existing persons as well. while the badness of extinction may be reducible to (e), full utility- based outcome analyses cannot ignore when an outcome includes the suffering of current existing persons; contingent suffering is relevant when present. the impartial non-human observer cannot ignore it. an alternative thus combines person-affecting and impersonal perspectives: f. extinction is comparatively bad if the sum of the suffering it imposes on living persons, the loss of potential utility that would have accrued had the currently living people existed for a longer period of time and had other persons lived in the future, or some combination of the two is greater than 0. richard Kraut, an opponent of absolute/intrinsic value, supports something like (f). For Kraut, the extinction of any species is bad iff the loss of the species is bad for the earth’s other creatures (2011: 169). the loss of beings that can and do experience and produce more good is worse than the loss of being who can and do experience and produce less good (185). humans, including future humans, can experience and produce more good than any other species. thus, the extinction of humanity would be the greatest of all catastrophes (164). like McMahan, Kraut takes future generations into account when assessing outcomes. he thereby commits to a v iew whereby potential utilit y must be weighed in our moral calculations. Both the last generation of humanity and their possible beneficiaries in future generations would be negatively affected by an extinction scenario, reducing total utility in the world (164- 165). occasionally, Kraut makes it sound as if future generations could be harmed by extinction, but to the extent that he can be plausibly be read as endorsing (f ), his view appears more plausible than alternatives. extinction scenarios, then, are most likely bad because of their negative impact on existing persons (to the extent that such effects are present) and because of the loss of the possible goodness of the people who might have ex isted and had good lives. the follow ing explains how to compare the values of histories including the potential utility of future persons and how plausible ca lcu lat ions st i l l lead to scena rios where ex t inct ion today is preferable t ha n ma ny yea rs of cont inued huma n ex istence. it t hereby explains why one should adopt a new approach to the badness of extinction, which is introduced in the next section. 2. calculatinG the BaDneSS oF eXtinction there is, then, a comparative harm in future people failing to come into existence if they would experience utility that would not otherwise be realized. 14 Michael Da Silva LEAP 3 (2015) this harm is impersonal. if the badness of extinction is comparative and its value is exhausted by the loss of potential utility (and perhaps the disutility experienced by existing persons when the extinction scenario arises), this raises questions about how to calculate potential utility and the overall utility of an outcome. the loss of potential utility stemming from an early extinction is a bad- making feature of an extinction scenario. comments on how bad it would be are necessarily speculative,7 but an impartial non-human observer would likely possess better measurement tools than i do. this piece thus assumes determinations on how much potential utility future persons would realize if brought into existence can be made, bracketing one source of uncertainty in population ethics, uncertainty about value, to assess the badness of extinction. one cannot place potential utility valuation completely in a black box, but attempts to answer hard questions about such valuation raise several problems. Pract ica l decisions rely on informat ion ava i lable to modern humans, not impartial non-human observers. when comparing potential histories, we want to know if, for example, we should discount benefits to future persons or if potential utility is equivalent to actual utility (see e.g., Bostrom 2002: 15-16). Black boxing may thus be practically problematic. For present purposes, however, it suffices to note that the loss of potential utility is non-negligibly bad.8 regardless of how one values potential future 7 John Broome agrees that we must take potential persons into account (2012: 175). the absence of persons accounts for our intuitions about the badness of extinction, even if we do not think it can explain why we think extinction is any worse than any other massive drop in the potential population. yet Broome is more skeptical than McMahan about the ultimate badness of large absences of persons: intuitively it seems most plausible that…[absences] are bad….But…we still have a lot of work to do before we can be sure that this is so….[e]ven if we can be sure a collapse of population would be bad, we have no idea how bad it would be. we have empirical work to do in predicting what would have been the well-being of the absent people, had they lived (183). this provides reason to question (e), (f), and (g). Broome suggests we cannot be sure of our utility calculations and thus may not be able to do the moral mathematics necessary to support the views. if this is true, any comments on the value of potential utility, including comments on the value of outcomes that rely on potential utility calculi, are necessarily speculative. 8 i am tentatively wont to provide such a discount based solely on the uncertainty identified by Broome, but the claim that the badness of extinction can be outweighed by other relevant circumstances even when the alternative would be many years of continued human ex istence does not depend on such a discount. e.g., Parfit offers a two tier view, according to which we give greater weight to the badness of outcomes that would be worse for particular people, but give some weight to non-person-affecting good and bad outcomes (2011: 219-233). Questions concerning whether extinction is always bad and whether we should always attempt to delay it arise even on versions of the two-tier view that give significantly less weight to effects on future well-being that do not affect particular people. Offsetting the Harms of Extinction 15 LEAP 3 (2015) utility, it should be included in assessments of the good of outcomes. the more pressing concern is how to calculate the overall utility of an outcome given fixed inputs of the utility of existing persons and potential utility of future persons.9 two popular candidate principles for such determinations are the total Principle and the average Principle. the former holds that “other things being equal, the best outcome is the one in which there would be the greatest quantity of whatever makes life worth living” (Parfit 1984: 387), but unfortunately entails the repugnant conclusion (388). the latter holds that the best scenario is one in which the average amount of utility experienced by each person is highest and may have similar implications in its widest form (399). it is also subject to further critiques, including the levelling Down objection (described in temkin 2012: 75-76). there is thus reason to question the most intuitive non-Person-affecting views. nearby views suffer from similar defects10 and extinction cases like the ones below raise similar problems.11 all principles of valuation suffer from some defects and are thus not obvious candidates for use in the valuation of the badness of extinction. the following possibility, which is agnostic about the competing principles, helps avoid these problems, but also supports the view that extinction is not necessarily bad: g. extinction is not comparatively bad if the sum of any negative disutility experienced in the process bringing about extinction and the impersonal negative effects of the potential utilit y of ex istent and future persons failing to be realized can be negated by earlier benefits conferred on existing persons. the scenarios below suggest followers of total-, average- and Perfection- based outcome valuation principles should all prefer imminent extinction 9 For simplicit y’s sake, calculations here ignore Different People choices, wherein different persons will be born depending on which of two scenarios arise and we assess the relative value of their lives (Parfit 1984: 356). the choice is between only this generation existing and any future generation existing. 10 Given space limitations, other principles cannot be canvassed. yet it should be reasonably clear that nearby view suffer from similar defects. e.g., those who understand the case demonstrating how the average Principle may lead to repugnant conclusion should understand how these arguments also apply to the average utility Principle. Small differences in particular cases are dealt with brief ly below. the key is that the treatment of (e)-(g) above remains true when reformulated to account for average utility. 11 t he i mper sona l tot a l a nd average P r i nc iples a l so ent a i l t hat, u nder cer t a i n circumstances, extinction is preferable to long periods of continued human success. indeed, the cases below suggest that extinction may be preferable on any plausible valuations. Given the similar problems between these views and their nearby alternatives on the margins, it is likely that the total badness in (e) and (f) can be negated by earlier benefits conferred on existing persons regardless of whether the loss of utility is calculated in totals or as deviations from an average. 16 Michael Da Silva LEAP 3 (2015) provided that the limit on the amount humans are able to flourish is sufficiently high. (g) is thus true regardless of whether one calculates the value of outcomes from a total-, average- or even Perfection-based perspective.12 Given that the most plausible outcome valuation theories all rely on one of these principles, one should not choose a theory solely to account for one’s pre-theoretical intuitions that extinction is bad and should be avoided or delayed to the greatest extent possible. regardless of whether one assesses the comparative badness relative to the possible total sum of utility that would have been contained in the lives of people who would have otherwise existed, on their quality of life, or some combination of these, imminent extinction may be preferable to long continued periods of human existence even at a high level of well-being. this does not entail that extinction is always the better outcome, but only that an early extinction may be a better outcome than a later one (from an outcome perspective) and a history with extinction in it may be preferable to one without it. this is an argument against those who consider extinction to be intrinsically bad and argue that it is always the worst, including those who say it would be intrinsically worse than humanity’s continuing to exist for longer.13 the main arguments for this claim are case-based and appear below. Following theories to their logical extremes to derive implausible results is common in ethics. i hope to show that any view on valuation may have the implausible result that extinction could be preferable to continued human instance. this is not meant to be an argument against consequentialism, but it should help demonstrate that one should not accept a particular form of consequentialism just to avoid the conclusion that extinction is preferable to alternatives.14 For instance, McMahan uses the badness of extinction as a datum for why one should admit non-comparative benefits, the aforementioned benefits that “cannot be explained in counterfactual comparative terms” (2013: 9), into one’s moral mathematics (26). For McMahan, extinction appears to be “the worst of those possible tragedies that have more than a negligible 12 Perfectionists believe ensuring people have a high quality of life is most important. Perfectionism too produces results where extinction is preferable to even long periods of continued human existence. e.g., the impartial perfectionist who is only concerned with the potential humanity being fully realized may prefer a world in which humanity f lourishes to the greatest extent possible now even if the non-existence of many future generations who would otherwise exist is a necessary consequence. 13 i will not address an extreme view one could read into David Benatar (2006: 194): h. earlier extinction is preferable to a later one because coming into existence is always harmful. we are obligated not to harm people and thereby obligated to hasten extinction by not procreating. 14 if (g) is true, those who believe that extinction is necessarily bad need to look outside utility-based analyses for justification. a rule-based approach to ethics may justify this belief. adopting such an ethics may be the right application of the argument’s conclusion. this piece merely seeks to identify implications of utility-based analysis. Offsetting the Harms of Extinction 17 LEAP 3 (2015) probability of actually occurring”, not merely due to its effects on existing persons, but also due to the loss of potential future utility by potential future persons (26). Since potent ia l f uture persons when choices concerning extinction are being made, there may be no relevant counterfactual in which they are comparatively benefitted or harmed. the purported losses of extinction thus appear non-comparative. extinction produces impersonal losses. McMahan’s view’s ability to explain the general plausibility of (e) and (f ), in which extinction will almost always be at least comparatively bad, cou nts i n its favor. t he loss of potent ia l va lue i n (e) a nd (f ) a re best understood as non-comparative or impersonal. one should not, however, assume that (e) and (f ) are true. indeed, even McMahan’s mathematics can be used to create a choice scenario where extinction is not the worst outcome. Plugging non-comparative harms into (e) and (f) can still result in ‘extinction is bad’ reading false. the badness of extinction alone thus does not justify admitting non-comparative benefits and harms into our moral calculations. McMahan is aware of other problems with non-comparative benefits and harms, but these considerations suggest that the extinction case may not provide adequate reason to accept them in the first place. to the extent that one prefers one’s intuitions about the badness of extinction to one’s ability to make plausible moral calculations, this is a problem with utility-based theor y. others should be moved to reconsider their distaste for certain imminent extinction scenarios. the remainder of this piece will demonstrate that one should not admit the potential utility of future persons into one’s moral calculations merely to explain pre-theoretical intuitions about the badness of extinction. this is because the addition of these people into our moral calculus will not always allow us to maintain these intuitions. Providing future individuals with the means to realize their potential utility is good. Since this good is merely comparative, however, it is not morally necessary that one bring it about in all cases. Since it is impersonal, no one is harmed by failing to realize it. when the potential utility calculus is paired with the most plausible means for analyzing the overall goodness of outcomes, the loss of potential utility of a hastened extinction will not rule out choosing extinction over histories where human beings live longer in certain circumstances. extinction today may be preferable to millions of years of continued human existence in some circumstances. 3. eaSier caSeS the extinction of humanity, then, is not intrinsically bad and any potential negative effects on existent and potential persons can in principle be negated by earlier benefits conferred on ex isting persons. the follow ing cases, focused on the use of pills that are unavailable in the physical world but 18 Michael Da Silva LEAP 3 (2015) common in phi losophy, suppor t t he more f unda menta l f irst conjunct concerning the intrinsic value of extinction. one may prefer a history with an earlier extinction to a latter one and a history with extinction in it to an alternative without it. Moral mathematics does not always demand choosing an outcome that avoids extinction. nick Bostrom notes that it is not “a conceptual t r ut h t hat ex istent ia l catast rophes a re bad or t hat reducing existential risk is right” (2013: 24). if one is solely concerned with outcomes, it also may not be a substantive truth that extinction is necessarily bad. harder cases below suggest early extinction may be preferable to circumstances in which humanity survives for a very long time. i first address less contentious cases where humanity will only continue to exist somewhat longer. the supposed badness of extinction is often demonstrated with hypothetical scenarios, but such scenarios also undermine this supposed badness. larry temkin provides an example of a scenario in which mass sterility leads to extinction to suggest that an outcome where regular regeneration continues is better than one giving current people immortality; contra Jan narveson, if we developed a pill enabling each of us to live wonderful lives for 120 years, it would be terrible for us to take the pill if the cost of doing so were the extinction of humanity. this is so even if taking the pill were better for each individual who took it, and hence everyone whoever lived, collectively….[i]f the cost of immortality would be a world without infants and children, without regeneration and rejuvenation, it wouldn’t be worth it….[t]his is so even if each immortal would be better off than each mortal (2008: 208)15. intuitions about similar cases are supposed to demonstrate the badness of extinction. yet i suspect that our intuitions about the case will differ if it is altered such that existing persons are made sufficiently well off. extinction may be the worst outcome of a given decision, but if we remove personal ha rms f rom t he scena rio, ex t inct ion ca n be persona l ly good. in such circumstances, the impersonal loss is merely a function of the lost potential utility of future generations that would have otherwise existed. a sufficient level of personal good for existing persons could outweigh this loss. From a pure outcome perspective, case-based reasoning suggests that a histor y including extinction may be preferable to an indefinitely long history without one.16 imagine a choice between: 15 My thoughts on this topic were furthered by two temkin-inspired cases in nick Beckstead’s doctoral dissertation (2013: 63). Gregory Kavka provides another famous pill case (1982: 98). 16 t hese i nt u it ions a f f i r m l en ma n’s cla i m t hat “[f ]rom a n i mpersona l, t i meless perspective it is hard to identif y good reasons why it should matter that human extinction comes later rather than sooner” (2002: 253). Offsetting the Harms of Extinction 19 LEAP 3 (2015) the highest high: an intergalactic travelling salesman arrives on earth. the salesman offers the earth’s inhabitants a pill that allows ever yone currently alive to reach the highest level of f lourishing possible. infertility is a side effect. the salesman is only on earth for a brief period of time and will not make the offer again, but will only provide it to the current generation on the condition that everyone agrees to take it. ever yone agrees to take the pill. humanit y goes extinct when the last currently alive person dies.17 rejecting the offer 1: the intergalactic travelling salesman makes his offer, but it is rejected. humanity continues to develop, but extinction comes within a few hundred years due to natural circumstances. rejecting the offer 2: the intergalactic travelling salesman makes his offer, but it is rejected. humanity development plateaus due to unforeseen technological problems. extinction comes within a few hundred years due to the natural circumstances from rejecting the offer 1. return to the repugnant conclusion: the intergalactic travelling salesman makes his offer, but it is rejected. human development regresses. a large number of humans continue to exist for an indefinite period of time with lives barely worth living. the pill’s extraterrestrial origin removes contingencies in other pill cases.18 Many of the worries surrounding extinction are also removed. Preferences can be satisfied. voluntariness is not undermined. even the violent ends of the last generation that add to the badness of extinction in similar scenarios are not present.19 Most forms of uncertainty are removed from the comparative equation. the possible outcomes are stipulated to identif y whether one with the extinction of humanity in it is necessarily 17 For simplicity’s sake, assume that the last people die together, everyone enjoys full material comforts, and no family members see each other suffer. this avoids pains in lenman (2002: 255). 18 in the absence of an ‘all or nothing’ decision on whether to take the pill, it is best to delay taking it until either scientists develop it without the sterility side effect or it is clear t hat t he side ef fect cou ld not be remedied. it rema ins importa nt to determine whet her extinction following f lourishing is problematic rather than focusing on when one can know the follow ing periods w ill not be better. if the side effect could not be remedied, the case would be akin to the extraterrestrial introduction in all relevant respects. 19 lenman provides a famous example of such a scenario and poses two questions: Suppose it is w ritten in the Book of Fate that one day we w ill be w iped out in a nast y catastrophe. Many millions of people will die in terrifying circumstances involving great pain and distress. the only thing the Book of Fate is silent about is when this is going to happen….the question is – Should we care? Does it matter how soon this happens? (2002: 255). 20 Michael Da Silva LEAP 3 (2015) worse than the alternatives.20 it is not obvious that the highest high is the worst scenario. it is thus not obvious that extinction sooner rather than later is necessarily a bad outcome. human beings’ ability to f lourish could be limited by their nature and psychology. if so, a relatively small number of future generations existing below the limit may produce a larger number of posit ive benef its t ha n t he pi l l. if, however, t he level of f lou r ish i ng is sufficiently high, then the highest high creates more utility than rejecting the offer 1 and 2. it thus appears to be the preferable outcome. the choice above may be a mere choice between existential risks,21 but this does not undermine the broader implications of the example. w hen compared with return to the repugnant conclusion, the mere presence of extinction in the rejecting the offer scenarios does not make the situation worse than an alternative without it in any substantial way.22 nick Beckstead (2013) is likely right that a given period with people in it is better than a period without sentient life, but the preceding choice scenario suggests that the disvalue of empty periods can be outweighed by sufficiently good periods when we look only at histories. 4. harDer caSeS one may charge that the important comparison involves not just a few more centuries, but a much longer survival of humanity. Parts of Parfit’s Reasons and Persons (1984) and other influential works in population ethics assume that the human race could continue to exist for a long time.23 they then question whether an earlier extinction would be preferable to such long histories. even those who prefer the highest high to rejecting the offers 1 and 2 would likely find it less obviously preferable to a future where human beings continue to live for longer periods. 20 Broome’s uncertainty about value potentially remains. this lingering uncertainty about the extent to which things are good or bad is no worse than what we find in any other scenario. even Broome notes that expected value theory will not help with this uncertainty (2012: 184). 21 e.g., rejecting the offer 2 includes a long period of stagnation (which is not nick Bostrom’s “permanent stagnation” (2013: 20) since extinction occurs). 22 one may argue that this would result in a decrease in morally relevant diversity, but a fully realized human contributes to diversity in the history, resulting in a tradeoff of the loss of diversity. there is reason to question the long-term relevance of this diversity criterion even in the absence of that tradeoff. as lenman argues (2002: 255), it seems more important that humanity exist at some point in a history to contribute to diversity than for it to continue to exist indefinitely. Diversity could be a bad-making feature of extinction at any given time, but if we take a sufficiently impartial view and analyze outcomes of whole histories, it is no longer relevant. Diversity over a history may additionally benefit from humans failing to exist if some species can only exist where humans do not. 23 Bostrom suggests this is an issue with many existential risks (2013: 22). Offsetting the Harms of Extinction 21 LEAP 3 (2015) it is important to examine these harder cases comparing early extinction to a history where humans continue to live for longer periods. yet the only fundamental difference where one is using the most plausible outcomes valuations is that the amount of utility the current generation would need to experience to make imminent extinction preferable is much higher than it is in the easy cases. even if we grant that the loss of potential persons could make a history worse, extinction is not worse than even alternatives where humans continue to live even very good lives for thousands or even millions of years if it came about as a consequence of existing people being guaranteed lives that were very much better. consider: rejecting the offer 3: the scenario in rejecting the offer 1 takes place but thousands of years pass before the extinction of the human race due to natural circumstances. rejecting the offer 4: the scenario in rejecting the offer 2 takes place but thousands of years pass before the extinction of the human race due to natural circumstances. Given a sufficiently long period of time, one may plausibly believe that the gains in quantity of lives in these outcomes when compared with the highest high would be outweighed by the lower quality of people’s lives. Much longer time periods make hastened extinction less compelling.24 if one accepts Beckstead’s claim that “it is not absurd to consider the possibility that civ ilization continues for a billion years, until the earth becomes uninhabitable” (43), rejecting the offer 3, in which humans continue to develop, or rejecting the offer 4, where human development plateaus, could be plausible constructions of these long histories.25 variations on rejecting the offers 3 and 4 suggest that extinction should often be avoided, but, given certain assumptions, the highest high may still be preferable. From an outcome-based perspective, extinction should be avoided where the positive benefits of an act that w ill result in or hasten extinction will not outweigh the loss of potential utility of future generations. For any given comparison with a potential future, one should focus on the potential utilities of future histories. to determine whether the highest high is preferable to rejecting the offers 3 and 4, one must be able to calculate the total amount of utility in each. whether the highest high will outweigh 24 one may worry that these additional numbers will eventually lead to return to the repugnant conclusion. the structure of rejecting the offers 3 and 4 ensures a relatively high amount of well-being in both scenarios. i nonetheless discuss this concern below. 25 return to the repugnant conclusion is unlikely. Broome says “we cannot reduce t he cha nce of ex tinction to zero” (2012: 179). richa rd K raut ag rees (2011: 163). they a re likely right. 22 Michael Da Silva LEAP 3 (2015) rejecting the offers 3 and 4 depends in part on what ‘the highest level of f lourishing possible’ in the highest high means. it is easy to see how, all- else-being-equal, much longer periods of time w ill create much greater amount of utility over the history of humanity. rejecting the offers 3 and 4 thus include more utility than rejecting the offers 1 and 2 respectively. whether they will include more utility than the highest high is not obvious. it is natural to assume that we will eventually reach a point where the amount of time is sufficient long that even a much smaller amount will sum (or even average) to a higher amount than the pill in the highest high could possibly reach. return to the repugnant conclusion is supposed to make this clear. in cases where extinction will eventually take place, albeit millions of years later, the question of whether more people experiencing less good for longer periods of time includes more utility than everyone alive today experiencing the highest amount of utility possible depends on how much utility the present generation could enjoy. it is hard to imagine ‘indefinite utility’ that could offset any potential lesser good in the future. there likely is a limit to the amount of utilit y any person could experience, but (g) remains true where the alternative histor y extends for thousands or even millions of years iff the limit on the amount of utility currently existing persons could accrue is sufficiently high that they could accrue more utility than many future generations. if the limit is sufficiently high, it may be such that the good current persons get from taking the pill is greater than thousands, millions or even billions of years of existence in any of the four rejecting the offer scenarios. if the gap between present utility levels and our maximal utility levels is sufficiently high and one is only interested in choosing bet ween better outcomes, then, one may choose the highest high over rejecting the offers 3 and 4. Given what we know about human physiology and psychology, the gap between humanity’s current utility level and the maximum amount we could enjoy is likely insufficiently large to offset millions of years at current or even lesser levels of utility. But imagine a pill that brings us beyond our current maximal capacity such that the highest level of utility is beyond current human limitations and results in each of us experiencing bliss much greater than the cumulative well-being of hundreds of persons at our current level living long lives. if this is the pill on offer in the highest high, humanity would not err in collectively agreeing to take it on risk of sterility. even if humanity would continue to develop such that future generations would flourish much more than we do today, experiencing goods far beyond our current capacities, a pill that could take existing persons beyond that level and provide the maximal amount of utility possible could produce more ut i l it y prov ided t hat t he ma x i ma l a mou nt of ut i l it y possible is suf f icient ly high. Offsetting the Harms of Extinction 23 LEAP 3 (2015) one may suggest t hat beings who took t hat pi l l wou ld no longer be recognizably human. the pill would then result in the immediate extinction of humanity by another name. yet most theorists agree that any history of humanity that will continue for thousands, let alone millions, of years needs to appeal to human beings’ descendants (e.g., Beckstead 2013: 43). the relevant comparison thus assumes we are dealing w ith beings that may not be recognizably human (but are closely related). while some will reject this assumption, it is sufficiently pervasive to support my demonstration that there is a way of understanding the highest high that makes it preferable to rejecting the offers 3 and 4.26 if the limit of human flourishing is sufficiently low, the highest high may not be preferable to different rejecting the offer scenarios. eventually there w i l l be a long enough period of t ime t hat w i l l ma ke reject ing t he pi l l necessary given a sufficiently long period of time and some cap on the highest level of utility possible. a problem for this salvation of anti-extinction-based intuitions nonetheless threatens. Perhaps any time extension of this sort would create a gap between the level of well-being of pill takers and future generations such that the scenario would mirror return to the repugnant conclusion in certain respects. the idea that a world with more persons who are less well-off could be better than a world that has a smaller but still considerably large number of persons (and, indeed, more than enough for society to function) who are much better off strikes many as implausible, but the source of the repugnance of the repugnant conclusion is hotly debated. the repugnant conclusion seems to demonstrate that, once a sufficient number of persons exist, the aim should not merely be to ensure more people exist, but also to ensure that each person experiences a certain level of well-being. Given that the persons in both worlds are living lives worth living, the problem cannot be that the level of well-being in either world is too low in an absolute sense. the repugnance of the repugnant conclusion only occurs in comparative analyses. one explanation for it is that the gap in well-being bet ween persons in the first possible world and those in the other is too large to be justifiable. the gap in quality of life across worlds makes the creation of lives worth living seem repugnant even when the lives would otherwise be worth living. if return to the repugnant conclusion is problematic not because of the much lower amount of well-being allotted 26 Depending on how one individuates species, it is possible that Beckstead’s multiple pha ses of hu ma n it y/post-hu ma n it y w i l l cont r ibute to d iversit y more t ha n t he i nsta nt development of the pill in the highest high. one may argue that this would be a further bad-ma k ing feature of ex tinction in t his circumsta nce t hat is not adequately covered by utility calculations. even if one grants that the manner of species individuation that would undermine my position is correct, it is possible that the number of species that could f lourish in the absence of humanity would be greater than the number of post-human species. Such speculation should be examined elsewhere. 24 Michael Da Silva LEAP 3 (2015) to each person in the world with more persons as such, but because it is much lower than what we take to be acceptable, perhaps a sufficiently high level of maximal utility could make existence even at the a very good level seem repugnant compared to the blissful level produced by taking the pill. even the existence of many more persons for a long period of time at a current level of well-being may seem repugnant when one compares the quality of life at the blissful level with the quality of life at our current levels of well- being. rejecting the offer 4, where human development plateaus, seems particularly problematic here, though development at a slow enough pace in rejecting the offer 3 could also be worrisome. i suspect that the comparative explanation for the repugnance of the repugnant conclusion is the wrong tack, but the fact that the lives in return to the repugnant conclusion are wor t h l iv i ng ma kes t he cla i m t hat t he y a re absolutely, r at her t ha n relatively, bad implausible. Defenders of rejecting the offers 3 and/or 4 need to ex pla i n why we prefer t he hig hest hig h to ret u r n to t he repug na nt conclusion without appealing to the large gap in the relative well-being of persons across the scenarios or risk a similar gap in the relative well-being of persons in the highest high and rejecting the offers 3 and 4 undermining their position. the badness of extinction is still not as obvious as it seemed. if we can limit the maximal amount of utility that could be brought about by the pill, lengthen the amount of time in the rejecting the offer scenarios to a sufficiently long period that the total utility in the scenario would be g reater t ha n t hat a mount, a nd ex pla in why return to t he repug na nt conclusion is worse than the highest high without appealing to a comparison that is mirrored by any rejecting the offer scenario and the highest high, then it is easy to construct scenarios where even one who is only concerned with total utility in an outcome should refuse to take the pill. the number of conditions here would, however, likely surprise many. laypersons likely believe their intuitions that hastening extinction is a bad thing will survive most scenarios. this jolt to intuitions strengthens the claim that the highest high reveals a non-obvious truth about the badness of extinction on outcome- based analyses: it is comparative and can be offset. 5. PoSSiBle Future GenerationS who woulD Greatly FlouriSh if Beckstead’s speculation about the future is correct, however, it is more likely that anyone who will approach the blissful level will do so through a gradual process of development (like in rejecting the offer 3). the intergalactic salesman is unlikely to arrive soon. even if s/he could exist, it is likely that s/he w i l l on ly v isit in a fa r f uture in which we ca n communicate w it h extraterrestrials and interstellar commerce can be done efficiently. it is more likely that the highest level of flourishing will require continued technological Offsetting the Harms of Extinction 25 LEAP 3 (2015) development.27 it is, in other words, unlikely that we will f lourish more than any potential future generation that could exist. it is thus worth considering what we should believe about the possible existence of people whose lives would be vastly better than the lives of the most fortunate actual people, but a few comments will have to suffice here. if an impartial observer knew that the highest high would take place 1,000,000 years from now, then, all-else-being-equal (e.g., assuming there are no periods where everyone has lives that are not worth living in the interim), s/he would have reason to prefer a history that lasted that long. consider: weak Batch: the pill from the highest high is offered to humanity in a diluted form that will only bring the existent generation up to level of the best life anyone is currently living. the salesman says s/he could provide a better batch in the future that would bring a future generation up to the highest high. ingesting the weak batch now will produce infertility that would make such a trip useless. humanity takes the weak batch. the value calculations above suggest humanity should not take a pill that could raise all existing persons up to the level of the best currently existing persons with the same infertility side effect as the pill in the highest high if it knows that a much higher level of flourishing could be experienced by a future generation. the future generation would not be harmed by not being able to take the pill, but the history of the world would be worse if they were given the opportunity. even a massive boost in well-being for the current generation beyond what anyone experiences today cannot justify hastening extinction to an earlier date. a ‘Stronger Batch’ situation produces the same resu lt. From a n impa r t ia l perspect ive, t he current generat ion has no specia l standing. yet more interesting questions arise when we contemplate future periods of great levels of f lourishing below the maximal level in the highest high. consider: Good times ahead: Development in rejecting the offer 3 creates a period of overwhelming positive utility in the future, much higher than 27 Bostrom posits a technological completion conjecture: “if scientific and technological development efforts do not effectively cease, then all important basic capabilities that could be obtained through some possible technology will be obtained” (2009: 190). one can imagine a version that brings humanity to its highest level of f lourishing. Given certain technological developments, we may reach a point where humanit y’s highest ends can be realized even without the intervention of an intergalactic traveler. if reaching this point requires sterility a nd we k now t his side ef fect is unavoidable, t he choice scena rio is simila r to t hat of t he intergalactic traveler. this piece provides guidance on how to make that choice. See note 18. 26 Michael Da Silva LEAP 3 (2015) the level any human experiences today. the forgoing provides the tools necessary to decide whether one should prefer this to the highest high. if its “overwhelming utility” is greater than one would get by taking the pill, Good times ahead is preferable to the highest high. if the maximal level of utility in the highest high is sufficiently high and the “overwhelming positive utility” in Good times ahead is less than the maximal level, it is possible that the gap is such that even the addition of other periods could not result in utility at the level of the highest high. the highest high would thus be preferable. 6. eXPlaininG another intuition extinction, then, is not bad in certain circumstances on most plausible outcome-based analyses. this helps explain common intuitions about the relative badness of the deaths of the last person and others. Many do not think the death of the last person is worse than the death of others who preceded him/her. the fact that one death would bring about the extinction of humanity is not seen as conclusive proof that it is worse than others. the simplest explanation for this intuition that does not run afoul of other plausible ethical stances is that the outcome of this death, extinction, is not worse than the outcome of other deaths where other persons remain. the intuition about the relative badness of deaths is most easily raised when comparing the death of the last human and the death of the human immediately preceding him/her. it is stronger where we imagine that the last humans know each other. Many people do not believe that the last human death would be worse than the penultimate human death. the penultimate death may even be worse since the last person will mourn the penultimate person’s death in the circumstances, if s/he knew that person, and then live alone without interpersonal connections that provide most of life’s meaning. S/he could be deeply affected by the death of the penultimate person even if s/he did not know the penultimate person, but only knew of his/her existence. Samuel Scheffler “would choose not to live on as the only human being on earth even if the alternative were not that human society would survive after my death but rather that everyone including me would die… [this preference most importantly] ref lects the strongly social character of human valuing” (2013: 80). this claim is supposed to be evidence for the badness of extinction, but can support the claim that the death of the last human may not be the worst one. For Scheff ler, knowledge of imminent extinction renders one’s life plans meaningless and one’s projects valueless. one’s current values are likewise tied to the existence of other persons at the same time. we need other people to value our lives. if Scheff ler is right, the death of the last person is less bad than the death of second last person. Offsetting the Harms of Extinction 27 LEAP 3 (2015) Desires to ensure that one last person remains alive, even indefinitely, are thus curious. the fact that the last and penultimate persons are among the last members of society obscures a larger truth: we often think that the fact that the last person alive is the last person alive does not make his death any worse than the death of many, and perhaps even any, other persons. the mere fact that s/he was the last person in existence does not make his/her life any more valuable than another. Barring circumstances in which the person’s status as the last person was the result of virtues fully in his/her command, we often think that this status is arbitrary and could easily be otherwise. if this is the case, there is little reason to mourn his/her death any more than we would mourn the death of an equally valuable contributor to society today. the claim that the deaths are not worse than one another is slightly different from the claim that there is no reason to mourn one more than the other. the latter claim is trivially true if we consider mourning to be a strictly post hoc determination: there is by definition no one to mourn the last person on earth after his/her death. we must instead examine the former question in an ex ante manner and compare which of two deaths we would prefer not to take place in certain circumstances. this determination is similar to one on which death is worse all-things-considered from the standpoint of the impartial observer judging outcomes. Many think neither death is worse than the other. Some believe that the death of the last person on earth is better than the death of earlier persons in certain circumstances. the easiest explanation for these intuitions, treating one death as worse than the other seems arbitrary, is not the best explanation. the relative badness of the deaths of two persons who are otherwise the same should not be determined by the order of their death. reversing the order seems morally irrelevant. intuitions about the relative badness of the deaths of the last and penultimate persons thus cannot be fully explained by the irrelevance of the moral order of actions. the order of actions affects their independent moral status elsewhere.28 this could be true where the order ot her w ise seems to be a n a rbit ra r y dist ing uishing ma rk bet ween t wo cases. the best explanation for intuitions supporting the v iew that the death of the last human on earth is sometimes no worse than and even preferable to earlier human deat hs is simply t hat sometimes t he later deat h is preferable despite bringing about the extinction of a species. in other words, the best explanation is that the ultimate outcome of extinction is preferable to an alternative in which persons continue to live in limited circumstances. (g) helps explain intuitions about the relative badness of 28 McMahan plausibly argues that “the order does make a difference” in determining the permissibility of certain actions in the domain of abortion and prenatal injury (2006: 649). 28 Michael Da Silva LEAP 3 (2015) deaths without appealing to questionable claims about the moral irrelevance of the order of actions. this provides further reason to accept it. concluSion t he ex t i nct ion of hu ma n it y, t hen, is not i nt r i nsica l ly bad a nd m ig ht be comparatively bad only by being an absence of what would have been good. this absence can be out weighed by current goods. thus, the extinction of huma nit y is not a lways worse t ha n a lter nat ive possible f utures. even t he i m m i nent ex t i nc t ion of hu ma n it y may be prefer able to t he c ont i nue d existence of humanity for long periods of time at high levels of well-being on most plausible valuations of outcomes provided that extinction takes a certain for m. Met hodolog ica l ly, t hen, one shou ld not choose a mea ns of va luing outcomes merely to avoid imminent extinction. extinction may be preferable in certain circumstances regardless of what view ones takes. the insights here, then, have methodological value. they should also help clarify why extinction should not be hastened now and when it may not be the worst outcome. BiBlioGraPhy Beckstead, n., 2013: On the Overwhelming Importance of Shaping the Far Future, PhD thesis, Department of Philosophy, rutgers university. Benatar, D., 2006: Better Never to Have Been, oxford: clarendon Press. Bostrom, n., 2002: “ex istentia l risks: a na lyzing human extinction Scenarios and related hazards”, Journal of Evolution and Technology 9. — 2009: “the Future of humanity”, in New Waves in Philosophy of Technology, ed. Jan-Kyrre Berg olsen, evan Selinger and Soren riis, 186-216, new york: Palgrave McMillan. — 2013: “existential risk Prevention as Global Priority”, Global Policy 4: 15-31. Broome, J., 2012: Climate Matters, new york: w.w. norton & company. Kavka, G., 1982: “the Paradox of Future individuals”, Philosophy and Public Affairs 11: 93-112. Kraut, r., 2011: Against Absolute Goodness, new york: oxford university Press. lenman, J., 2002: “on Becoming extinct”, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 83: 253-269. McMahan, J., 1986: “nuclear Deterrence and Future Generations”, in Nuclear Weapons and the Future of Humanity, ed. avner cohen and Steven lee, 319-339, totowa, nJ: rowman & allanheld. — 2006: “Paradoxes of abortion and Prenatal injury”, Ethics 116: 625-655. — 2013: “causing People to exist and Saving People’s lives”, The Journal of Ethics 17: 5-35. Pa r f it, D.,1984: Reasons and Persons, oxford: clarendon Press. — 2011: On What Matters: Volume 2, oxford: oxford university Press. — 2013: “Death and the afterlife”, in Death & the Afterlife, ed. niko Kolodny, 15-110, oxford: oxford university Press. http://philosophy.rutgers.edu/dmdocuments/Nuclear%20Deterrence%20&%20Future%20Generations.pdf LEAP 3 (2015) temkin, l., 2008: “is living longer living Better?”, Journal of Applied Philosophy 25: 193- 210. — 2012a. Rethinking the Good: Moral Ideals and the Nature of Practical Reasoning, new york: oxford university Press. Offsetting the Harms of Extinction 29 LEAP 3 (2015) The Limits of Moral Argument: Reason and Conviction in Tadros’ Philosophy of Punishment1 E R iC BLu M E nSOn Suffolk University ABSTRACT For generations, philosophers of punishment have sought to revise or combine established t heories of punishment in a way t hat cou ld reconci le t he utilitarian aims of punishment with the demands of deontological justice. victor tadros’ recent work addresses the same problem, but answers it w it h an entirely original theory of punishment based on the duties criminals acquire by committing their crimes. the unexpected appearance of a new rationale for punishment has already inspired a robust dialogue between tadros and his critics on many of the individual claims that, linked together, comprise his argument. this critique focuses instead on tadros’ theory as a whole and the methodology he uses to support it. it proposes that tadros’ argumentative strategy can’t justify his rationale by virtue of (1) the extent and complexity of the moral reasoning he invokes, (2) the counter-intuitive results his theory produces in an array of specific cases, and (3) the superiority of a negative- retributivist account in which moral reasoning and intuitive judgments, and the principles and applications that f low from each, are coherent and mutually supportive. victor tadros responds to these arguments in an essay following this critique. Key words : Moral philosophy, punishment, criminal law theor y, moral reasoning, tadros the philosophy of punishment covers enormous ground, but if one problem endu res at its core, it is t he con f l ict bet ween t he ut i l ita r ia n a i ms of punishment and the demands of deontological justice. they seem mutually 1 i am particularly grateful to victor tadros for responding to this critique, to participants at the nyc criminal law colloquium for their comments, and to carol Steiker and harvard law School for arranging the symposium with tadros at which i presented an early version of this paper. thanks are also due to Jeff alsdorf, Jeffery atik, claire Blumenson, Jeanie Fallon, Stanley Fisher, Gabriel lev in, Steven nathanson, Derek Parfit, Pat Shin, Ken Simons, ror y Smead, Marion Smiley, rayman Solomon, and terrell ussing for their comments and counsel. The Limits of Moral Argument 31 LEAP 3 (2015) exclusive in theory, and may often generate different sentences in practice. Finding a principled way to combine them has motivated generations of criminal law theorists. this challenge has served as a kind of conceptual rosetta Stone that, if met, might clarify much of the field. the philosopher victor tadros has applied his considerable skill to the problem and believes he has solved it. in his highly regarded 2011 book The Ends of Harm and in papers since refining some of his views,2 tadros offers a truly original justification for state punishment, and does so with impressive dept h a nd cla r it y. t he a ston ish i ng advent of a new mora l accou nt of punishment has already inspired three journals to publish symposia on its merits, and prompted punishment theorists to revisit widely varied areas of the field. tadros and his critics have commenced a robust dialogue on many of the individual claims that, linked together, comprise his argument. i join that endeavor in Part 1(B), infra, enumerating what i see as weak or missing links in tadros’ argument. although i raise these substantive objections to particular claims, my principal interest is in the argument as a whole, and the methodology tadros uses to construct it – subjects that are necessarily excluded from the piecemeal analyses that have occupied tadros and his interlocutors to date. a central claim is that this methodology is out of balance: it places too much faith in conceptual argument and too little in intuitive moral judgment; its extreme reliance on distended chains of reasoning leaves no role for deeply held convictions about specific cases.3 one can’t reach an end-point of reflective equilibrium with such a methodolog y, and i believe this, more than any 2 tadros has developed and in some respects revised his theory in response to critics (2012; 2013; 2015a) and in his response to this critique (2015b). 3 rawls distinguished three categories of normative beliefs that should play a role in the method of moral reasoning he called wide reflective equilibrium: considered judgments about specific cases, moral principles and rules, and moral theories (rawls 1971: 19-21, 48-51). the distinctions are orthogonal and overlapping, however, because we may also have considered judgments about moral principles and theories (rawls 1999: 286, 289; also see Brun 2014). “considered judg ments” a re a k in but not identica l to what ot hers ca ll “pre-t heoretica l convictions” or “moral intuitions.” as an example, one might believe that slavery to be immoral (a) by virtue of an intuitive conviction that such is the case, or (B) by inference from other beliefs that yield that conclusion; judgment “a” would qualify as a considered judgment in rawls’ usage if it also satisfied certain epistemological safeguards – stability over time, relevant knowledge, impartiality, etc.. “considered judgments about specific cases” thus supply two ingredients to mora l inquir y, bot h integ ra l to t he met hod of ref lective equilibrium: mora l conv ictions regarding particular cases, which in their specificit y can act as a check on more general principles and theories (and vice versa); and moral intuitions as provisionally credible sources of moral knowledge. Both dimensions of a moral belief are important to my critique. regarding its degree of generality, section 3 argues that specific sentences the Duty view would generate are so unacceptable as to warrant rejecting the theory. regarding its grounding, section 2 argues that intuitive moral judgments matter, and cast more doubt on tadros’ counter-intuitive conclusion than his distended chain of inferential reasoning can support. 32 Eric Blumenson LEAP 3 (2015) particular weakness in tadros’ reasoning, accounts for the theory’s failure to persuade t he numerous commentators who have sought to pick his argument apart. Methodological imbalance is not a problem for tadros alone, but constitutes an occupational hazard for moral and legal philosophy generally, given that conceptual argument is at the heart of what philosophers and law yers are trained to do. But tadros’ argument is an especially fruitful example with which to consider t he use of reason, intuit ion a nd judg ment in mora l argumentation generally: it is precisely because tadros’ moral reasoning is so exhaustive, accomplished and transparent that its frailties and limits come into view. this study proceeds as follows. Part 1 describes tadros’ justificatory theory of punishment, distilling his argument down to eleven sequential steps a nd ident if y ing severa l wea k or missing lin ks a mong t hem. the balance of the article puts these piecemeal critiques aside and evaluates the methodolog y and strength of the argument as a whole. Part 2 argues that tadros’ argumentative strategy can’t take him as far as he seeks to go, simply by v irtue of the extent and complex it y of the moral reasoning he invokes. Part 3 demonstrates the counter-intuitive results his theory would produce in an array of specific cases, and argues that results so at odds w it h st rong a nd sett led conv ict ions count heav i ly aga inst t hat t heor y. Fi na l ly, Pa r t 4 demonst rates t hat a n a lter nat ive – a for m of negat ive retributivism -- remains more persuasive than tadros’ theory because it leaves us in a position of ref lective equilibrium, in which moral reasoning and intuitive convictions, and the principles and applications that f low from each, are coherent and mutually supportive. 1. taDroS’ theory oF PuniShMent on one view, punishment is justified by the intrinsic goodness of a criminal’s suffering in proportion to his desert. tadros entirely rejects this idea; he believes that no one deserves to suffer and that suffering is never valuable in itself, whomever it aff licts. For tadros, the only possible ground for punishing someone lies in its beneficial effects. his rationale for punishment is exclusively instrumental. tadros calls his philosophy of punishment “instrumentalist” rather than “consequentialist” because he wants to distinguish clearly between his justification of punishment and the comprehensive theory of morality known as consequentialism (2011: 25, 39-40). were his theory consequentialist in the latter sense, he would face the familiar devastating objection: because The Limits of Moral Argument 33 LEAP 3 (2015) results are all that count, the theory could require imprisoning a mobster’s innocent mother when there would be utilit y in doing so, and even her execution if it would deter more killings than the one it would inf lict. this is unacceptable to tadros, but so is the retributivist solution that grounds punishment in the offender’s desert. tadros’ third way is a hybrid position: an instrumentalist rationale for punishment situated within a non-consequentialist moral theory. he insists that the value of punishment lies in its deterrent impact, but also recognizes deontological side constraints on pursuing it – most importantly, the Means Principle prohibition on using a person merely as a means to another’s benefit (13, 23). in tadros’ telling, this constraint places very stringent limits on government actions (so much so that only a libertarian state would seem to comply with it.4) we punish in order to reduce crime, but the Means Principle restricts its inf liction to the guilty, tadros claims, because only the guilty have a duty to submit to it. For that reason, tadros calls his theory the “Duty view” of punishment. of course, everything depends on establishing that this duty exists, and that it derives from something other than desert. (otherwise all tadros has done is change words, substituting a “duty to suffer punishment” for “just deserts.”) tadros’ starting point is the example of one person attacking another: uncontroversially, the assailant is morally liable to be harmed by defensive force. tadros then argues that if the assailant completes the crime, his liability to suffer harm persists, extending to a series of residual and remedial duties that culminate in a duty to deter crime by submitting to punishment. 4 tadros argues that the state may not tax people to finance retributive punishments, both because (1) liberal neutrality would rule out compelling people to finance a controversial, non-neutral conception of the good, and in any case, (2) citizens are not bound to expend resources to pursue the good unless they have a duty to do so (2011: 79-83). he argues that measures protecting people from crimes are not subject to either objection, because citizens have rights to securit y t hat create co-relative duties to prov ide it (82-3). By contrast, he classifies retributive justice as an impersonal good and “it is much more difficult to justif y forcing a person to make a contribution to the pursuit of goods that are not grounded in the rights of others,” like the promotion of natural beauty, because each citizen is entitled not to pursue them (81). of course, this objection would eliminate large areas of government funding well beyond the promotion of natural beauty or the arts. Massive infrastructure projects like america’s rural electrification project in the ‘30s or interstate highway system of the ‘50s are also not “grounded in the rights of others.” even funding such things as health care or occupational safety would seem to require a showing that people have rights to them and co-relative duties to provide them through the state. For that reason, the implications of tadros’ argument seem to approach the strict libertarianism robert nozick (1974) propounded, and bring to mind nozick’s famous claim that redistributive taxation is akin to forced labor. compare nozick 1974: 169 with tadros 2011: 79, wherein tadros argues that to “use resources that a person produces for the pursuit of [a] goal is perhaps not as coercive as forcing them to work for the sake of that goal, but the difference is not terribly significant.” 34 Eric Blumenson LEAP 3 (2015) that’s a very long road to travel. how does tadros get all the way from the permissibility of defensive force to the permissibility of state punishment? a highly distilled and simplified version of tadros’ argument as i understand it consists of the following multiple-step progression. 1.1 Tadros’ Argument in Eleven Steps Liability to be harmed by defensive force i. all persons have a moral duty to refrain from wrongful aggression against others. ii. if wrongful aggressor a commences an attack upon victim v, a has a residual duty to prevent its completion or harmful impact on v if possible. a’s obligation includes incurring a proportionate degree of harm if necessary to thwart the crime. note: a's obligation to incur harm does not arise because he deserves it. it stems in part from a principle of distributive justice, the choice Principle. on this principle, if someone must suffer, it is better that it be a person whose choice created the situation than someone merely trapped in it. (whether it is “better” prudentially because we all have reason to value choice, or morally because it is fairer, neither view treats deserved suffering as good.) here it was a’s choice to attack v that made the threat of harm inevitable (2011: 56).5 iii. v (or a third person) may enforce a’s duty to avert her threat by using defensive force against a that inflicts no more harm than a would have been liable to suffer in discharging her own duty to avert her threat. Residual duty to compensate victim by protecting against other crimes iv. if a’s attack succeeds and harms v, a has a residual duty to provide a remedy to the victim. v. the remedy a must provide v is protection from future crime, even at significant cost to herself, as long as that harm is (a) no more than a was liable to suffer from v defending himself at the time of the crime, and (b) proportional to the harm it would prevent. 5 tadros (2011: 56) says that while the opportunity to avoid being harmed will often coincide with culpability, it is the element of choice rather than desert that is basic. the obligation to submit to defensive force appears over-determined in tadros’ theory. w hether the choice Principle is necessary to his argument is left unclear given his sporadic reliance on the aggressor’s breach of her duty of non-aggression to justify, by itself, the residual duty to suffer defensive force that follows. if it is the latter, there is a question whether forcing the aggressor to do what he had a duty to do can fulfill the duty, because it may completely bypass the aggressor’s agency. (See Duff 2013: 116-117.) The Limits of Moral Argument 35 LEAP 3 (2015) note: suppose a 1 has just shot v when a 2 arrives on the scene and independently attempts to shoot v. v may use a 1 as a protective shield against a 2 ’s attack even though a 1 was not responsible for it, based on a 1 ’s remedial protective duty. w hile this uses the aggressor as a means, it does not v iolate the Means Principle because she has a duty-based liability to suffer that harm. regarding the specification of protection as the remedy, tadros argues that monetary compensation is ordinarily an inadequate remedy for a serious crime, and often unavailable in any event, so something more akin to specific performance is required of the aggressor: to protect the victim against a future crime of similar gravity (2011: 2, 277-78). vi. on efficiency grounds, criminal wrongdoers are obligated to pool their protective duties and take responsibility for protecting each other’s victims (193-94, 280). note: consider two assailants, each responsible to protect her particular victim from a future crime. if each assailant is unable to protect the person she attacked, but is able to protect the other’s victim, both have an enforceable duty to do so. in the previous example, a 1 was liable to be used as a shield to protect v from a 2 . as a result of this implied exchange, a 1 may now be used as a shield to protect someone else. Duty to submit to punishment v ii. if punishing wrongful aggressors can deter crimes against the victims they are responsible to protect, they have a duty to submit to punishment, subject to the same limits as step #5 (279-80, 291). State’s exclusive right and responsibility to punish viii. the state may enforce a wrongful aggressor’s duty to submit to pu n ish ment by punishing her (395). iX. Because all citizens have a modest duty of mutual protection, all victims are obligated to use their right to protection-through- punishment to protect others as well as themselves (298). X. For reasons of prudence, effectiveness and fairness, the state is best able to fulfill the v ictim’s dut y to punish. therefore, all victims have an obligation to transfer their rights to punitive compensation to the state (297-99, 304-05). X i. as the exclusive instrument of enforcement of both citizens’ and aggressors’ protective duties, the state is obligated to punish w rongful aggressors (293, 299-305). 36 Eric Blumenson LEAP 3 (2015) hence the core principle of the Duty view: the state has the exclusive right and responsibility to punish a wrongful aggressor for the purpose of general deterrence, provided that (a) the harm the punishment inf licts is proportional to its beneficial consequences, and (b) does not exceed that which the aggressor was liable to suffer in order to avert his crime. 1.2 Some Weak Links in the Argument critics who quarrel with a particular step in an argumentative chain often assume that the argument is only “as strong as its weakest link.” in fact, as the next section argues, an inductive chain of reasoning is not as st rong as a ny of its indiv idua l lin ks, however wea k or st rong, a nd t his problem may prove fatal to an argument as distended as tadros’. But first, with tadros’ individual claims now in mind, it is worth noting some particularly weak or missing links in that argumentative chain. Step 5 - the prior step has established that if a wrongdoer does not thwart the crime he started, he must do the next best thing: he must provide a remedy to the victim. Step 5 specifies that “[t]he appropriate way to remedy that wrong is by providing protection to victims and other citizens against future harm.” (2011: 2). But that claim dismisses alternative types of rectification – monetary payment in a theft case, for example, or surgery and long term care in a maiming case. this move has spurred a fair amount of argument between tadros and his critics which i need not repeat here, other than to note that nothing in tadros’ further arguments obviates the two problems noted in the margin.6 Step 6 - this step seeks to establish the aggressor’s obligations to people he has never threatened: he has a qualified duty to exchange responsibilities with other wrongdoers, so that each victim will be protected by somebody. the duty to pool responsibilities is contingent on the greater effectiveness 6 First, ma ndating a protective dut y rat her t ha n permitting moneta r y or ot her compensation deprives the victim of any choice in assessing how she might best overcome the damages she suffered. in a theory largely concerned with assuring respect for the moral status of autonomous persons, why shou ld t he state a rrogate t his choice to itself ? (See tanguay-renaud 2013: 154; Ferzan 2013: 193-94). responding to this criticism, tadros has argued that leaving this choice with the victim “may lead her to violate the duty of protection that she owes to others.” (2013: 307). as i argue later in this section, it is more likely that the state will violate its duty to protect the victim’s compensatory right by aggregating it with all others and trading off among them on utilitarian grounds. Second, t he residua l dut y is supposed to be t he nex t-best t hing to f u lf illment of t he original duty, and it is far from clear that the victim would be better off with protection from a possible future crime than with a remedy aimed at mitigating or compensating for damages the victim has already suffered (tanguay-renaud 2013; Ferzan 2013). tadros assumes monetary compensation is inadequate, but a remedy that is contingent on the possibilit y of future v ictimization may be more so. The Limits of Moral Argument 37 LEAP 3 (2015) of doing so. Suppose a assaulted v, and now wants to fulfill her protective obligation by purchasing a guard house on v’s street and spending hours a day there insuring v’s safety. assuming a’s work is sufficiently onerous so that it not only provides the protection but also exacts the degree of harm a could be required to bear, is a then exempt from the exchange, and thereby lacking the special duties to protect other victims that would ground a’s liability to punishment? if so, punishment will be imposed unequally, based on arbitrary factors like the wrongdoer’s wealth or the victim’s age. Step 7 - Step 7 specifies that the wrongdoer’s protective duty is to submit to punishment. having already established the wrongdoer’s duty to avert someone else’s threat – serving as a shield, for example - tadros says, “if punishing each wrongdoer can protect other victims of crime from future of fending, each w rongdoer ought to accept t hat he must be punished. (tadros 2011: 280) assume punishment can protect victims from future crime via deterrence; note that Step 7 still doesn’t establish that wrongdoers are restricted to fulfilling their protective duty by that means when there are other effective methods available. Punishment is only one of many methods of deterrence, and deterrence is only one of many methods of protecting people from crime. we may achieve deterrence w ithout punishment by increasing the neighborhood police presence, and we may reduce crime without deterrence through social work, job training, or other programs that ameliorate criminogenic conditions like poverty; so obligating offenders to undergo or help finance such programs might also fulfill their protective obligations. Given the suffering that punishment inflicts and tadros condemns, he needs a persuasive argument to bypass such non-incarcerative alternatives. as this step makes clear, tadros’ justification for punishment is entirely contingent on the effectiveness of deterrent punishments, a relationship that is notoriously contested and hard to determine; and if the required deterrent value is present, contingent as well on what other consequences might accrue, as tadros recognizes (2011: 40; also see ch. 15, sec. v discussing what consequences may properly count in determining proportionality; and 30, 338, 348, 352-53).7 Steps 9 and 10 - here tadros seeks to transform the victim’s individual right to protection-through-punishment into a collective right exercised exclusively by the state. in step 9, he establishes that victims have a duty to use their right to punish so as to protect others as well as themselves, based on the modest duty all citizens have to provide mutual assistance to each 7 america’s mass incarceration policy arguably resulted from an unduly narrow focus on crime control, to the exclusion of the social damage that would result from the removal of vast numbers of men from their communities, the diversion of resources away from policies that might ameliorate criminogenic conditions, etc.. 38 Eric Blumenson LEAP 3 (2015) other (“easy rescue”). Step 10 then argues that the victim’s duty to punish includes the obligation to authorize others to punish if they will do so more effectively and fairly, and that because the state is such an agent, the victim must transfer her individual compensatory right to protection-through- punishment to the state to enforce (301; also see 297-99, 302-07). one difficulty with this two-step argument is that it depends on a duty of mutual assistance that can’t support it. at the least, the duty of mutual assistance morally (though not legally) requires a passerby to undertake relatively costless rescues, like calling 911 or throwing a lifejacket to a flailing sw immer. Does it a lso require t hat a v ict im’s compensator y rights be transferred to the state and transformed into a system of deterrent punishment benefitting victims and non-victims alike, as tadros argues? that strikes me as a bridge too far. even if the duty of mutual assistance could justify some loss in benefits, it cannot justif y the loss of the v ictim’s right to the remainder. a lthough Step 10 is framed as a matter of more effective enforcement of the rights and duties of each victim, the state can only enforce them in the aggregate. My right to compensation for theft, and your right to compensation for torture, and all other v ictims’ compensator y rights, become subject to trade offs based on factors such as which punishments of which kinds of crimes will have the “biggest bang for the buck.” rights may be defeasible, but they cannot not be subject to such maximizing cost-benefit calculations and remain rights. Indeterminacy and Arbitrariness a more general substantive problem with the Duty view is the degree of indeterminacy and arbitrariness that comes with the proliferation of a large number of duties and rights, each with uncertain borders and relations to the others. among those that play a role in tadros’ argument are a wrongdoer’s duties to thwart her crime, to prov ide a remedy, to pool her protec t ive dut ies w it h t hose of ot her wrongdoers, and to submit to deterrent punishment; a victim’s duties to punish wrongdoers and transfer his right to punish to the state; and the state’s duties to protect citizens from crime and from unjust punishment. according to tadros, some of these duties may fade over time as the duty- holder becomes less psychologically connected to the person he was when he committed the crime. needless to say, with duties as inherently broad, vague, and temporally unstable as many of these are, problems of interpretation and application are daunting. For example, when is the remedial duty satisfied and the debt paid? how should we measure the state’s duty to punish in proportion to t he good t hat wou ld accr ue -- ca se-by-ca se, or system ica l ly w it h a l l The Limits of Moral Argument 39 LEAP 3 (2015) punishments treated collectively? if the former, how would we isolate the effect of the individual’s punishment? as duties and rights proliferate, and as more than one applies (or is available to be applied) to a particular circumstance, attempts to define, apply and balance them will generate a large margin of error that, with successive iterations, threatens to take over the page. as i shall now argue, we get closer to justice with a discourse that is tied more directly to our moral intuitions and capable of finer distinctions than the abstract discourse of rights and duties that constitutes the Duty view. 2. a MethoDoloGy oF DiMiniShinG returnS l et u s now put a side t hese subst a nt ive c r it iques, a ssu me t hat a l l of tadros’ subsidiar y claims are indiv idually plausible, and consider how they operate collectively in an argumentative chain. i want to examine two inherent limits on the persuasiveness of highly distended moral reasoning of this type. the first problem is that, as a general rule, the more complex and lengthy the argumentative chain, the less confidence we should have in its conclusion. a chain of inductive reasoning is weaker than the sum of its parts. the second problem is comparative. w hen such an extended chain of reasoning is necessary to establish a position as revisionist as the Duty view, we may think that it isn’t enough to justify rejecting much more deep-seated and immediate intuitive beliefs. however strong the argument, it will lack plausibility if it is incompatible with fundamental moral convictions that are too compelling to doubt. (i leave aside a third methodological critique that has been persuasively demonstrated elsewhere: tadros’ reliance on highly idiosyncratic hypotheticals to elicit far broader principles than they can support. See husak 2012: 19) consider first tadros’ argument on its own terms. its initial steps invoke cer t a i n i nt u it ively plau sible pr i nc iples, such a s a mor a l dut y of non- aggression; succeeding steps are mainly established inductively by taking a preceding step’s principle and eliciting responses to hypotheticals testing its extension. this multiple-step moral argument is essential because the ultimate principle it seeks to establish -- that state punishment is permitted only insofar as it may fulfill the wrongdoer’s protective duty -- is not at all intuitive by itself. this kind of moral reasoning suggests the construction of a building, starting with the foundation and progressing upward as each successive f loor is built. it appears to make progress by addition. But addition is a misleading metaphor for viewing this kind of argument. each successive step should reduce our confidence in the conclusion,8 for three reasons: 8 unless, of course, it adds to the plausibility of a prior one. 40 Eric Blumenson LEAP 3 (2015) (i) the longer the chain, the greater the chance for a substantive error to infect it. each additional step brings with it an additional risk of failure. (ii) the second reason applies even if every step is highly likely to be correct. it reflects the mathematical truth that a chain of inductive reasoning is not “as strong as its weakest link” but weaker. the “weakest link” adage does apply to deduct ive reasoning, where t he t r ut h of t he log ica l ly-enta i led conclusion rests entirely on the truth of its premise. But tadros’ argumentative steps are based on inductive inference, analogy, and intuition, none of which can supply the 100% confidence that logical entailment does. in this case, each step can only be judged more or less plausible, and each step makes the chain weaker by compounding the possibility of error, however minimal. a Bayesian calculation would treat each step as probabilistic to the degree of it s plausibility, and the likelihood of the concluding proposition as a product of the multiplication of fractions, just as the chances of tossing two tails in a row are ½ x ½ = ¼. we can illustrate how severely tadros’ methodology undermines his thesis by assuming that each individual step in tadros’ argument is amply persuasive, with all intuitive and inferential claims highly plausible. if we represent this arithmetically by assuming a 90% level of confidence in each of the eleven steps, the likelihood of the conclusion being correct is just 31%. we may wel l have more confidence in the brute conviction that only desert can justify and calibrate punishment. now this 31% figure is illustrative and subject to reasonable disagreement. one might deem some step unnecessary, or deductive, or so self-evident as to be incontrovertible, for example. But at least five of the eleven steps would have to be entirely discounted on such grounds to render tadros’ conclusion even slightly more likely than not. (iii) Some may question whether this mathematical likelihood of error is su f f icient to d iscred it a mora l a rg u ment i n t he absence of speci f ic counterarguments, or whether mathematical probabilities can be attached to moral judgments at all. But a third reason to doubt tadros’ distended argument needs no mathematical proof to warrant acceptance: Occam’s Razor, the principle that the simpler explanation for a proposition is more likely to be true than a complex one, all else equal. Given its fruitfulness in directing scientific investigation over centuries, we need not be able to The Limits of Moral Argument 41 LEAP 3 (2015) explain why this principle is true to be justified in presuming it is.9 By this standard, tadros’ 11-step argument should be rejected as unnecessarily complicated, if only because the same principle tadros uses to justify the v ictim’s right to self-defense – the choice Principle – would justif y state punishment directly if punishment deters crime. if imposing the death penalt y on conv icted killer a w ill deter the unprovoked murder of B, the choice Principle provides a reason to execute a because, as one of the two will die, it is fairer that it be the one who had the opportunity to avoid the risk. in his response to my “diminishing returns” argument, tadros does not contest the math, or the inverse relation between the number of steps he uses and the likelihood his conclusion is correct. he argues instead that all moral claims rely on the truth of many subsidiary claims, so all moral claims are vulnerable on this analysis, including the ones i propound elsewhere in this essay. My “diminishing returns” argument would lead to a general moral skepticism, he claims. (2015b: 58) But that’s the wrong lesson. My argument is not an invitation to moral skept icism, nor a cla im t hat intuit ions a re infa l lible, but a n appea l to consider the relative persuasiveness of different legitimate modes of moral d i scer n ment on t he quest ion at ha nd. a s mor a l a rg u ment becomes increasingly abstract and distended, the intuitive plausibility of its conclusion increases in importance. this creates a burden that highly revisionist moral arguments may not be able to meet. the problem with tadros’ multi-step argument is that it culminates in a rationale that opposes the fundamental intuitive convictions most people have about the morality of punishment, and this forces us to decide which ground of belief is more trustworthy on the issue. t h is is one a nswer to tad ros’ cla i m t hat my a rg u ments a re a s v u l nerable a s h is ow n because t hey a lso i nvolve mu lt iple steps. t he conclusions to those arguments - that it is unjust to inf lict punishment in the absence of desert, and that it is unjust to the v ictim for the state to ignore his victimization – do not require us to choose between an extended chain of reasoning and our considered moral convictions. the bottom line is that tadros’ methodology places his conclusion in a less plausible i n it ia l posit ion before a ny quest ion is ra ised about t he soundness of individual links in the chain. this doesn’t obviate exploring the merits of those links, see Sec. 1(B) above, but it does provide a substantial, independent ground for skepticism. 9 richard Swinburne (1997) claims that “it is an ultimate a priori epistemic principle that simplicity is evidence for truth.” Some argue that this principle is self-evident, constitutive of rationalit y, or another kind of foundational truth that cannot be further justified. others, however, accept occam’s razor is an appropriate methodological ma x im but not by itself indicative of truth. 42 Eric Blumenson LEAP 3 (2015) 3. counter-intuitive SentenceS the last section examined the intricate structure of tadros’ reasoning and whether it can support the principles he derives from it. if we examine how these principles would apply to specific cases, the difficulty multiplies. they produce results so counter-intuitive that something has to give. apparently recognizing this, tadros modifies the Duty view to make it cohere with moral common sense, but to such an extent that it largely disappears; as i shall argue, with tadros’ many work-arounds in place, what remains is something very much resembling negative retributivism. this is not surprising, as so many obv ious sentencing factors are easily understood in terms of retributive desert but invisible to the Duty view in its unvarnished form. 3.1 Losing Proportionality in Punishment consider the case of Dzhokhar tsarnaev, recently convicted for his part in the 2013 Boston Marathon bombings that killed three people and injured hundreds of others. the Duty view would prohibit punishing tsarnaev if he were innocent, but is it capable of generating a proportional sentence to tsarnaev given his conviction? i doubt it, unless we so revise our moral convictions as to make irrelevant numerous factors that anglo-american jurisprudence has consistently viewed as important considerations in sentencing. For ex a mple, i n pla nt i ng t he bombs tsa r naev acted w it h ex t reme premeditation. others may kill on impulse, or after being provoked, or by negligence, or by accident. retributivism can explain the enormously different sentences imposed in killings perpetrated w ith these different levels of culpability: a premeditated killing displays a degree of blameworthiness that doesn’t exist in a negligent one, for example, and therefore deserves far harsher punishment. on the other hand, tsarnaev was a teenager, and we are likely to think he therefore deserves a different, lesser sentence than a fort y year old career criminal who committed the same crime. these factors have been important to sentencing judges because of their obvious relation to desert. retributive sentences are straightforward in that way; most retributivists believe that a punishment should ref lect the gravity of the crime and the blameworthiness of the perpetrator in committing it. if premed itat ion, yout h, a nd pr ior conv ict ions a re releva nt sentenci ng considerations under the Duty view at all, there is nothing straightforward about why this is so. on the Dut y view, we impose sentences based on many factors, but most centrally on the factors that governed the wrongdoer’s liability to be harmed defensively at the time of his crime. the two primary sentencing limitations are that the harm it inf licts on the wrongdoer not exceed that The Limits of Moral Argument 43 LEAP 3 (2015) which (a) he would have been liable to suffer from the victim defending himself (2011: 347), and (B) is warranted for the sake of the net benefit it will produce (333-34). that sets the baseline for the wrongdoer’s liability to su f fer ha r m i n pu n ish ment, wh ich is t hen adjusted by ma ny factors, including inter alia reductions based on repentance (347-48), the passage of time since the crime (347-48), the difference between “eliminative” self- defense and “manipulative” punishment for deterrence (319-320), and the offender’s absence of responsibilit y for the threats his punishment w ill deter (348). as to “a”, note that this proportionality requirement has little to do with t he rect if icator y basis t hat tadros invokes as t he prima r y g round for liability. the sentence is limited not by what would be required to make the victim whole, nor by what would now be required to avert a new but similar crime against him, but by how much harm the v ictim was permitted to i n f l ict defensively at t he t i me of t he cr i me. t h is seems to ma ke t he aggressor’s liability to punishment dependent on the factors that govern t he per m issibi l it y of sel f-defense. Key a mong t hem a re necessit y a nd proportionality: the defender may use only the amount of defensive force that is necessary to repel the crime and proportional to the gravity of the threat it is defending against. there are other factors that may limit defensive force, but none of them are sensitive to the age, record, or culpability of the aggressor because those factors do not change the moral preference afforded the victim given that one of the two must suffer harm. nor do age, record and culpability have much bearing on compensation to someone victimized by a crime; whether the aggressor’s threat is a product of negligence, recklessness, or design is not at issue, only the degree of harm that must be rectified. on the other hand, some factors that are relevant to self-defense have little obvious bearing on punishment. Most inapt is the self-defense element of necessity. a victim defending himself may use only the amount of force necessa r y to repel t he agg ressor, which mea ns t hat dif ferences in t he circumstances – such as the type of weapon the aggressor is using -- will cha nge t he a mou nt of defensive force per m it ted. if one’s l iabi l it y to punishment depends on one’s liability to suffer defensive force, punishment may var y greatly among w rongdoers who are identical in ever y respect except the morally arbitrary circumstances in which they acted. the result will be sentences that, intuitively, seem much too low or much too harsh. consider as examples: - a, a bank teller, embezzles v’s account. B, a purse snatcher, grabs v’s purse. Should a and B’s liability to punishment vary according to the fact that v is entitled to use defensive force against B but not a? 44 Eric Blumenson LEAP 3 (2015) - a shoots v and misses, leaving v unaware of his narrow escape. v has no need to defend himself and no right to compensation. Does this have any bearing on whether a should be liable to punishment for attempted murder? - a threatens v with a knife. v is able to retreat safely and therefore defensive force is unnecessary; but v fails to retreat, parries a’s thrust unsuccessfully, and dies. Does the fact that a was not liable to be ha rmed in self-defense have a ny bea ring on what his liabi lit y to punishment should be? in his response to this last hypothetical, tadros seems to argue that the permissibility of defensive harm does not have bearing in that case, but that seems impossible to reconcile with his fundamental argument against desert.10 3.2 Tadros’ Work-arounds this mismatch between permissible self-defense and proportional punishment should not be surprising. even if we assume the purpose of both is to prevent crime, the factors relevant to averting a wrongdoer’s imminent threat are not the same as those relevant to using a wrongdoer as a means of preventing crimes by other people against other victims at some time in the future. tadros allows that the “transition from self-defence to punishment may not be entirely smooth,” (2011: 348) and develops a number of arguments for departing from the self-defense template he had adopted. the challenge he faces is to cha nge t he scope of pu n ish ment l iabi l it y -- ex pu ng i ng t he irrelevant factors and incorporating the relevant ones -- while somehow maintaining the self-defense rationale for liability. in my judgment it is a challenge that defeats him: the independent proportionality rationales he marshals become so ad hoc, and so divorced from the self-defense and compensatory grounds that preceded them, that we may wonder what the self-defense template for punishment has accomplished. Some illustrations: Punishing environmental crimes - Most criminal codes include environmental crimes that cause harm without harming any particular person – for example, the intentional killing of the last member of a marine species. Duties of victim compensation can’t apply to such a case, so one can’t justify punishment 10 tadros says that v wrongs a because his defensive force was unnecessary, but that “given his wrongful act he is permitted to defend himself. it follows that there is no asymmetry between liabilit y in self-defence and liabilit y in punishment of the kind that Blumenson’s argument relies on.” (2015b: 71). this seems to contradict the central argument tadros used to show t hat l iabi l it y to defensive force is just i f ied by t he choice Pr i nciple, not by t he aggressor’s desert. that principle of distributive justice holds that if harm is inevitable, it is better that it befall someone who was responsible for creating the situation than one who is not. in this case, harm is not inevitable given the victim’s opportunity to retreat; and when he fails to do so, he is the person responsible for making harm to one of the two inevitable. The Limits of Moral Argument 45 LEAP 3 (2015) by extending the compensatory duty. But tadros doesn’t interpret that fact to bar punishment of such crimes. rather, he develops some much more direct grounds for punishing them. on tadros’ alternative rationale, the wrongdoer had a duty to respect the natural environment, and his violation of that duty may give rise to “a duty to protect that aspect of the natural environment from further damage. if the first duty is not owed to anyone, neither is the second…. hence, it may be permissible to punish [him] to deter others from causing further damage to the natural environment.” But the duty not to commit a criminal act applies to all crimes, raising the question of why these grounds don’t obviate his more complex (and therefore, ceteris paribus, less persuasive) primary argument. why isn’t that duty sufficient to ground a protective duty to prevent further such crimes, without relying on a particularized duty to victims at all? richard Burgh (1997: 316) has made an argument along these lines, characterizing a crime as a social harm that requires the offender to compensate society through punishment. Punishing attempts - Similarly, an attempted crime does not harm a particular victim who has no knowledge of it. if the perpetrator of such an attempt is to be punished, it can’t be because of any liability to submit to defensive force or provide compensation to the victim. however, tadros thinks these crimes can be punished because attempted crimes divert police resources and make everyone less safe, thereby establishing the attempter’s dut y to compensate ever yone (2011: 326-27). a lexander (2013) has criticized the factual premise of this claim,11 and Ferzan (2013: 185-86) has criticized its rationale, both because it offers no way to determine what degree of harm a wrongdoer’s diversionary act has caused, and because it holds her strictly liable for it. But even if tadros could answer these critiques, his rationale would still dictate an entirely implausible proportionality calculus. For example, it suggests that attempted drug smuggling should be punished more harshly than attempted murder, given the greater police resources devoted to preventing smuggling. Since publication, tadros has turned to a different argument to justify punishing attempted crimes. he argues that it is implausible that “attempting to harm others makes no difference to a person’s liability to be harmed as a means…i do not see what argument could be provided for it. even if we think that causing a threat is very important to ground a person’s liability to avert the threat, why should we conclude that attempting to cause harm 11 alexander (2013: 172) argues that because many failed attempts would go unnoticed but for their criminality, it is “ludicrous to assert that were they not criminalized, they would be causing us to devote security resources away from averting harmful acts.” 46 Eric Blumenson LEAP 3 (2015) is insufficient on its own to make any difference at all to a person’s liability to be harmed?” (2013: 320). tadros’ intuition is clearly explainable on grounds of desert, but given his rejection of that ground, and the inapplicability of tadros’ compensatory theory, i would argue this gets the burden of persuasion backwards, that the argument missing is his own. Punishment beyond compensation - attempted crimes present one of several difficulties that confront tadros’ effort to justify punishment on the basis of the offender’s residual compensatory obligations. as commentators have noted, this basis also produces the unacceptable corollary that wealthy offenders may be able to buy their way out of punishment (Ferzan 2013: 189-91; walen 2012). Most people would find this unacceptable on grounds of inequa lit y, but because t heir measure of inequa lit y is compa rat ive desert, that can’t be tadros’ worry. his worry is that an offender who does not bear any significant cost in protecting the victim “cannot claim to have fulfilled his rectificator y dut y….[f ]or he would only have done what he would have had a duty to do independently of his wrongdoing” – the duty to rescue each other from harm if it can be done at little cost (2011: 286). So tadros annexes an independent basis of punishment liability to the Duty view. he claims that: our compensatory duties are fulfilled when we have done what is required to rectif y the harm that we have caused. the duties that underpin punishment, in contrast, are not…Because i could have been harmed as a means to avert a threat that i posed as a result of my wrongdoing, i may now be harmed as a means to an equivalent degree to avert other threats, even threats of a greater magnitude than the harm that i caused (288, 291; also see 283-91 discussing punishment beyond rectification). the question is, Why? tadros offers two rather vague answers. the first is the analogical argument that because a guarantee of compensation does not obviate the prohibition on tortious conduct in advance, ex post compensation does not fulfill the offender’s duties either (2015a: 82-83). But this analogy works only if the reason compensation is insufficient ex ante also applies ex post, The Limits of Moral Argument 47 LEAP 3 (2015) and it doesn’t. that reason depends on the act not having occurred: at that point, compensation is second best to preventing the tort to begin with. Ex post no such preference exists. in fact, there can’t be a preference as to type of remedy, because both the compensatory and further duties are paid in the same currency - protection from future crime. the best we get is the discussion of a hypothetical -- Three Threats, described below12 - that suggests that committing a crime subjects the wrongdoer to conscription as a utilitarian means for crime control. tadros’ grounds are that (1) the victim is in serious danger, (2) the offender is harmed to no greater degree than he is liable to be harmed to avert the threat he imposed, and (3) he could have avoided that liability simply by refraining from his wrongful act (2013: 303, enunciating these reasons for the three threats conclusion; 2011: 291). But these grounds prove too much twice over. the first difficulty is that these grounds cannot distinguish bet ween using w rongdoers to prevent crime and using them to supply organs or fulfill other important social needs. in order to avoid making the offender fair game generally, tad ros of fers some except ions to t he above rat iona le ; whet her t hese exceptions are persuasive i leave to the reader to consider.13 12 in three threats, tadros imag ines t hat Bob has propelled a bou lder t hat w ill injure Jane. on the Duty view, Jane would have been permitted to harm Bob to y degree in order to stop the boulder, but the boulder is unstoppable. She can, however, use Bob to divert either Boulder 2 or Boulder 3, each of which have been pushed towards her by others. if she uses Bob to avert Boulder 2, she will avert the same degree of harm that Bob’s boulder will cause, at minimal injury to Bob. if she uses him to avert Boulder 3, she will avert twice the deg ree of injur y t hat Bob’s bou lder w ill cause, but Bob w ill be much more bad ly injured, though in an amount less than y (2011: 289). tadros argues that it is strongly intuitive that Jane may use Bob to avert Boulder 3, even though using him to avert Boulder 2 would fully satisf y Bob’s compensatory obligation with less injury to him (291). 13 tadros says that certain kinds of punishment w ill always exceed the offender’s liability. on his account, even if an offender was subject to lethal defensive force at the time of the crime, capital punishment is impermissible given the passage of time and the difference between eliminative and manipulative harm (2013: 308). w hat about the non-lethal harm of organ removal for transplantation? tadros rules this out as well on the following grounds: (1) “it is wrong to harm a person to tackle a problem that is utterly different from criminal offending.” (2011: 354). w hether a particular punishment is excluded thus depends on what kind of differences matter and why, but we get no more than the conclusory term “different.” without a definition, the criterion cuts both ways: others would find the difference between (a) harming a wrongdoer to defend against his aggression and (b) harming him to deter the aggression of others sometime in the future sufficient to make the latter impermissible. (See Quinn (1985). (2) “it may be t hat t here is somet hing specia l about organ distribution…. Perhaps using a person’s organs is a particularly pernicious way of using a person…” (2013: 309). But again, without specifics we are hard-pressed to explain why incarcerating a person regardless of his desert is not similarly pernicious. (3) institutional reasons to constrain punishments: for example, the likelihood that the institutions administering transplant pu n ish ments w i l l act u n fa i rly, t he ava i labi l it y of less d racon ia n but equa l ly ef fect ive alternatives, and the expansive tendencies of criminal justice systems (2013: 308-09). notably, however, all three grounds may easily apply to exclude prison sentences as well. 48 Eric Blumenson LEAP 3 (2015) the other way that tadros’ reasoning proves too much is that it seems to leave the duty of compensation superfluous. its justification reaches all the punishments that were prev iously grounded in the compensator y dut y. the latter now seems beside the point - as arguably it should be, given that a victim may be fully compensated through the civil system. let us consider a different explanation for the intuition that wrongdoers have an extra-compensatory duty to deter crime by their own punishment. Daniel Farrell (2015) has argued that this putative requirement must be a duty of retributive justice; tadros disputes this on the ground that “retributivist views of punishment are not grounded in duties of offenders, or the relevant duties have nothing to do with protection.” (2015a: 81) i believe tadros is right to deny that this additional duty constitutes the pure form of ret ribut iv ism t hat requires t he inf lict ion of suf fering on offenders, because his theory prohibits doing so solely for that purpose. But i find it difficult to view his claim as plausible except as an implicit if diluted version of the negative retributivist theory i argue for in the following section – the view that desert is a necessary but not sufficient condition for punishment. on the Duty view, the offender has a duty to exceed compensation to the full extent of his liability to be harmed, but this duty should only be enforced if some utilitarian benefit will accrue. and on what basis does that duty exist? not on the basis of either utility or compensation, because the duty exists apart from both. in the absence of some other specification by the author, it seems t hat t he dut y persists beyond f u l l compensat ion because t he offender deser ves to suffer the additional burden. that seems to be the best ex pla nat ion for tad ros’ statement t hat a ssa i la nt Ja ke st i l l owes something after he has fully compensated his victim Sally: “if Jake manages to benefit Sally at little cost to himself, we will have a sense that he has ‘got away’ with his crime.” (2011: 289). 4. the ineXoraBle SiGniFicance oF DeSert i have just argued that the Duty view generates highly counter-intuitive instructions to a sentencing authority unless modified beyond recognition, and that retributivism offers a better account of the factors that must inform the proportionality calculation. this should count heavily against the theory unless its retributivist rival is itself lacking in some greater way. So we must assess the comparative strength of the retributivist alternative and tadros’ arguments against it. tadros argues that retributivism is not an option because it is both false and incoherent, and what intuitions seem to support it can be better explained The Limits of Moral Argument 49 LEAP 3 (2015) in other ways. his central objection, and the one i shall explore here, is that retributiv ism rests on a false premise – the premise that a w rongdoer’s suffering is intrinsically valuable to the degree it is deserved (2011: 26, 45).14 But there are many retributivisms, and only some of them depend on that premise.15 therefore tadros’ critique cannot establish the Dut y view’s comparative advantage over retributivism tout court. More specifically, tadros’ definition does not encompass retributivists who believe that punishing criminals is at least sometimes a duty of justice, a claim i shall argue in part 4(B). nor can it apply to the prominent version known as negative retributivism. negative retributivists do not believe that the state should punish a criminal to the extent she deserves. rather, they believe that the state must not punish the innocent, nor punish the guilty beyond what they deserve. For them, desert is a necessary but not sufficient condition for punishment; therefore punishment is justified only if there is also an additional, non-retributive basis. negative retributivists quite clearly do not believe that the “goodness” of deserved suffering requires the punishment of a criminal, and there is no reason to think they believe such suffering is good at all. But desert is still the central element in their theory: its absence bars punishment, and its presence places a n upper limit on t he permissible sentence. negat ive retributivism illustrates the error in tadros’ argument: one can’t eliminate the importance of desert to sentencing by showing that deserved suffering is, li ke a l l suf fering, bad. we ca n believe t his but a lso believe t hat t he inf liction of suffering in proportion to desert is sometimes justified as a necessary evil. there is a reason tadros dismisses negative retributiv ism, but not, i think, a good one: he believes there can be no such thing. he claims that by its terms, retributivism provides a putative reason to punish the guilty but no reason at all against punishing the innocent, or against punishing the guilty beyond what they deserve. he further argues that if it did protect the innocent, the idea would be incoherent. the next section challenges these t w o c l a i m s. Fol low i ng t h at , s e c t ion 4 ( B ) s how s how a br oader non- consequent ia l ist t heor y of pu n ish ment m ig ht just i f y bot h a l i m it on punishment (through negative retributivism) and an affirmative duty to punish (grounded on other considerations of justice), as one example of a theory incorporating desert that is not subject to tadros’ critiques. i suggest that this theory is more compelling than the Duty view, given its superior ability to account for our considered sentencing judgments and its greater 14 More precisely, tadros believes that only a retributivism built on that premise would be weighty enough to justif y an incarcerative system of punishment. 15 those that do include the theories argued in Moore (1997) and Kirshnar (2000). 50 Eric Blumenson LEAP 3 (2015) coherence as a theory. 4.1 Desert as Prerequisite: Is Negative Retributivism Possible? retributivists disagree about whether their theory commands punishment of the guilty or only permits it, but it seems all retributivists believe that their theory bars punishment of the innocent, and consider this a unique and powerful point in their favor. remarkably, this is precisely the opposite of tadros’ novel rendition of retributivism, which to him constitutes only a sword, not a shield. this fol lows, he says f rom “t he ver y simple t r ut h t hat t he existence of a reason to do something does nothing to exclude the possibility that the thing (and more) could not adequately be justified on other grounds.” (2011: 36; also see 35-7, 312-13). he claims that only the Duty view protects the innocent from punishment. the oddity is that the basis for tadros’ claim that the Duty view bars punishment of the innocent is identical to the reason retributivism purports to do so. that reason is the Means Principle. the claim in both cases is that only the guilty may be punished consistent with the Means Principle - either because only they deserve it (according to retributivists) or because only they have a protective obligation the state may enforce (according to tadros). Given the parallel structure, there are no good grounds to claim, as tadros does, that the Duty view bars punishment of the innocent but retributivism does not. Perhaps tadros believes that the Duty view includes the Means Principle, whi le t he ret ribut ive v iew does not. But why shou ld he t hin k t hat? the retributivist tradition since Kant has most centrally embodied respect for the right of autonomous individuals to choose their ends for themselves, a constraint that restricts punishment to those who will it on themselves by their own blameworthy acts. tadros (2015b: 59) also argues that if negative retributivism did protect the innocent it would be incoherent because desert necessarily cuts both ways: i think that ‘X deserves o’ implies that there is good reason for X to get o irrespective of any further good that will be secured if X gets o. if so, there is no such thing as negative desert in Blumenson’s sense. a negative retributivist may believe it bad (or unjust) for someone to get what he doesn’t deserve without being logically committed to the view that it is necessarily good (or just) for him to get what he does deserve (wasserstrom 1978: 309-10). But let us assume that tadros’ first proposition is correct. his second sentence would not follow from it if any one of the following is true: i. a reason may be overridden. an offender may deserve punishment, and this may entail that punishing him is good in one way, but The Limits of Moral Argument 51 LEAP 3 (2015) the net costs of punishment may be so great as to foreclose it. here’s an analog y: equality is intrinsically good in one way; if achiev ing it wou ld require redist ribut ion t hat lef t ever yone almost as impoverished as the worst off were, doing so may be bad in a greater way; therefore, whether states should aim for equality in any particular case is contingent on the costs and benefits it would produce. ii. a mora l side-const ra int might ba r t he state f rom a iming to cause offender suffering even when deserved. that constraint would not rule out state punishment for other reasons. iii. even if “X deserves o” entails that X should receive o, desert w i l l not require punishment if “o” sig nif ies “for feiture of a libert y right” rather than “punishment.” the question here is whether one can deser ve to lose a right by his blameworthy actions, and surely it is at least coherent to think one can. Some of one’s rights may be contingent on respecting the rights of others. alternatively, blameworthiness may be the fairest criterion for the distribution of individual punishments when a punishment regime w ill produce enough benefit to be justifiable. there is nothing unintelligible or inconsistent in recognizing both a moral prohibition on punishing the blameless and a humane directive to impose punishment on the guilty only when something would be accomplished by doing so. rights-forfeiture theories differ over what rights a criminal forfeits by her conduct. Depending on the theory, she might retain rights against punishments that serve no utilitarian benefit, or inflict pain, or are imposed by vigilantes, for example (see wellman 2012). there are many versions, but to qualify as a form of negative retributivism, the forfeited right against punishment must be limited to punishments proportional to the offender’s desert. 4.2 Beyond Desert: Why Punish? the second and third interpretations conceive negative retributivism as a matter of principle – one that that limits who may be punished and by how much – but by itself provides no reason to punish anyone. if there is to be any punishment at all, negative retributivists must look to some other theory that provides an affirmative reason to impose punishment on an offender. Many negative retributivists find that reason in the utility of punishment as a crime-preventive deterrent. that hybrid view parallels tadros’, except that the permissibility of punishment is grounded in desert rather than a forward-looking remedial duty. 52 Eric Blumenson LEAP 3 (2015) But there is powerful intuitive support for another reason to punish as well: as tadros notes, most people believe that “something is amiss when a serious wrongdoer is not punished,” even in the absence of deterrent value (2011: 276). in this final inquiry, i add this conviction to the mix and ask whether it weighs for or against either theory. if we credit this intuitive conviction as roughly ref lecting some moral truth, we must ask what exactly is amiss. tadros thinks it is the fact that “offenders who are not punished have a duty that is unfulfilled.” (276). the ret ribut iv ists he ta rgets believe it is t he fa i lure to inf lict suf fering on wrongdoers who deserve it. one might argue that a negative retributivist who rejects both views, as i have, can’t explain this intuition and that this should count heavily against his theory. there are two rejoinders. First, even if true, that criticism would not count against the theor y in a pair-w ise comparison with the Duty view, which itself leaves a wrongdoer unpunished when deterrent value is lacking. Second and more importantly, a negative retributivist can answer that challenge because, unlike tadros’ theory, nothing prevents him from combining a desert-based limit on punishment with a non-utilitarian rationale for imposing it. here is a rudimentary sketch of one possibility: a hybrid theory that asserts as state deontological obligations (1) a prohibition on inflicting undeserved punishment, and (2) a responsibility within that limit to impose punishment when required as a matter of justice to the victim. (whether utilitarian benefit is also a reason to impose a permissible punishment is a separate question.) the intuitive appeal of the second element is currently illustrated by the demands for “justice for Michael Brown” by residents of Ferguson, Missouri, following a grand jury’s failure to indict the police officer who killed him, and by the startling number of similar cases since. what is “amiss” in such cases, and in a state’s refusal to sanction any grave crime, is the injustice that inf licts upon the victim: the devaluation for a second time of someone who has a lready been t reated by t he per pet rator as no more t ha n a n instrument to his ends. For George Fletcher, this constitutes state complicity in the crime that leaves “the victim’s blood…on our hands.” (Fletcher 1995: 6, 205; also see hampton 1992: 1684, 1692; Burgh 1987). complicity may be too strong, but at the least, such state inaction betrays the protective role that largely underwrites its own legitimacy, and treats the victim as an outcast. on this account, the state’s obligation to punish crime derives from the injustice it does to victims when nothing is done. But to be clear, this rationale for punishment is a qualified one: punishment is not the obligation, only a means of fulfilling it, and whether other means may also do so is necessarily The Limits of Moral Argument 53 LEAP 3 (2015) dependent, at least in part, on the social meanings that prevail in a culture.16 in ours, many people believe that a long term of imprisonment is the only way of taking victimization seriously. yet it is possible to imagine a cultural shift towards less draconian methods, such as fines, community service, house arrest now enforceable through the use of GPS ankle bracelets -- and even non-criminal restorative justice resolutions, in which case this justification for punishment would dissolve. to be sure, the Duty view is also concerned with justice to the victim -- unlike the prevailing punishment theories, which neglect the victim as an independent subject of justice17 -- but its conception of justice is quite different, and is contingent on its crime-prevention utility. tadros believes that the state’s obligation to repudiate crime and vindicate its victims can’t justify punishment, (2011: 87-8, 91-2, 107, 109; 2013: 255) and argues that because a v ictim’s moral status “is incapable of being eroded through w rongful action….it is difficult to see why the obligation to protect people against lack of respect is very significant in itself” (2011: 108).18 But this misses the real stakes involved in a state’s response to victimization, and leads tadros to severely underestimate its importance. w hat is involved is not merely the wrongdoer’s violation of a victim’s inalienable moral status, but the very existence of the victim’s civil status as a member of the political community. in the united States, it is unconstitutionally cruel and unusual punishment to strip a person of “his individual status in organized society”.19 a state that ignores crimes against its citizens withdraws that status. there are other hybrid theories, of course. h. l. a. hart’s distinction bet ween t he ut i lita ria n “genera l just if y ing a im” of punishment a nd a deser t-based dist ribut iona l const ra int is perhaps t he most inf luent ia l among many (hart, 1968: 8, 10). the only point here is to demonstrate the inexorable signif icance of desert in punishment as a restriction on its permissibilit y, and its compatibility with a range of affirmative rationales 16 a further, necessary question, of course, is whether any particular cultural take on the requirements of justice may be morally unacceptable. w here permissible cultural diversity ends and moral imperatives begin is a vexing problem, and one that increasingly confronts institutions of global justice. For the international criminal court, that issue takes legal form as the question whether non-criminal, transitional justice alternatives are sufficient to bar icc prosecution under its complementarity principle. rome Statute of the icc, art. 17, un Doc. a/conFr. 183/9 (July 17, 1998). over time, icc decisions on the issue will define minimum requirements for criminal justice systems throughout the world. 17 consequentialism is concerned with the collective benefit, presumptively leaving the victim with no greater significance than any other individual; retributivism classically treats justice to the victim as if it were a mere by-product of, or necessary identical to, the punishment that is required to treat the offender as she deserves. 18 See a lso 2013: 277-79, in which tadros rejects adil a hmad haque’s cla im t hat punishment can be justified because we owe it to the victims; see haque 2013. 19 trop v. Dulles, 356 uS 86, 101-102 (1958). 54 Eric Blumenson LEAP 3 (2015) for punishment. w hat’s fatally counter-intuitive in the Dut y view is its exclusion of any direct role for desert as a prerequisite to the permissibility of punishment. concluSion i have argued that the Duty view is unpersuasive as a theory of punishment, and that an alternative theory – one that recognizes both a defendant’s right against undeserved punishment and a victim’s right to vindication – comes closer to a point of reflective equilibrium in which principles, theories, and intuitive judgments cohere and support each other rather than forcing us to choose among them. yet what a fruitful thing it is for the philosophy of punishment that tadros has made his case for the Duty view! there are not many works within the field that cover so much criminal law ground with such originality, and even fewer with the potential to stimulate a new wave of thought on numerous issues in the field. and, it is to be hoped, not just in the realm of philosophy. one of the gifts of a theory of punishment as imaginative and revisionist as the Duty view is that it allows us to v iew our correctional policies through a new lens, rethink old choices, and discover alternative routes to security that don’t always go through a prison gate. That route, which the united States has traveled for the last half century, has left us with over 2.2 million prisoners and the distinction among nations of imprisoning the largest percentage of its population, five times the world’s average (Bureau of Justice Statistics 2012: 3). tadros asks us why, and what we have to show for it. his approach presses us to take the suffering of inmates seriously as a central moral element in punishment, and in so doing, to consider alternatives. For consequentialists, retributiv ists, policy-makers, judges and others who long for a morally defensible criminal justice system, that is the best place to start. BiBlioGraPhy alexander, l., 2013: “can self defense justify punishment?”, Law and Philosophy 32: 159-75. Brun, G., 2014: “reflective equilibrium without intuitions?”, Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 17: 237-52. Bureau of Justice Statistics 2012: “correctional Population in the united States, 2011”, in Bulletin ncJ 239972 : 3.7-52. Bu rg h, r., 1987: “Gu i lt, pu n ish ment, a nd deser t”, in Responsibilit y, character, and the emotions: new essays in moral responsibility, ed. F. Schoeman, 316-37, cambridge: cambridge university Press. The Limits of Moral Argument 55 LEAP 3 (2015) Duff, r a., 2013: “Punishment and the duty of offenders”, Law and Philosophy 32: 109-27. Farrell, D.M., 2015: “using wrongdoers rightly: tadros on the justification of general deterrence”, Criminal Law and Philosophy, 9: 1-20. Ferzan, K.K., 2013: “rethinking the ends of harm”, Law and Philosophy 32: 177-98. Fletcher, G., 1995: With justice for some: victims’ rights in criminal trials, new york: addison-wesley Publishing company. hampton, J., 1992: “correcting harms versus righting wrongs: the goal of retribution”, UCLA Law Review 39: 1659-1702. haque, a.a., “retributivism: the right and the good”, Law and Philosophy 32: 59-82. hart, h.l.a., 1968: “Prolegomenon to the principles of punishment 1”, in Punishment and responsibility, 1-27, oxford: clarendon Press. husak, D., 2012: “retributivism in extremis”, Law and Philosophy 32: 3-31. K irshnar, S., 2000 : “a defense of retributiv ism”, International Journal of Applied Philosophy 14: 97-117. Moore, M.S., 1997: Placing blame: a theory of the criminal law publisher, oxford: oxford university Press. nozick, r., 1974: Anarchy, state and utopia, new york: Basic Books. Quinn, w., 1985: “the right to t hreaten and t he right to punish”, Philosophy & Public Affairs 14: 327-73. rawls, J., 1971: Theory of justice, cambridge, Ma: Belknap Pess of harvard university Press. —1999: “the independence of moral theory”, in rawls, J., Collected papers, ed. Samuel Freeman, 286-302, cambridge, Ma: harvard university Press. Swinburne, r., 1997: Simplicity as evidence for truth, Milwaukee, w i: Marquette university Press. tadros, v., 2011: The ends of harm: the moral foundations of criminal law, oxford: oxford university Press. — 2012: “replies”, Jerusalem Review of Legal Studies 5: 89-109. — 2013: “responses”, Law and Philosophy 32: 241-325. — 2015a: “answers”, Criminal Law and Philosophy 9: 73-102. — 2015b: “response to Blumenson”, Law, Ethics and Philosophy 3: __. tanguay-renaud, F., 2013: “victor’s justice: the next best moral theory of criminal punishment?”, Law and Philosophy 32: 129-57. walen, a., 2012: review of the book The ends of harm by victor tadros, at rutgers university, Criminal Law and Criminal Justice Books, http://clcjbooks.rutgers.edu/ books/ends_of_harm.html wasserst rom, r., 1978 : “Some problems in t he def in it ion a nd just if icat ion of punishment”, in Values and morals, ed. a. i. Goldma n a nd J. K im, 299-315, Dordrecht: D. reidel. wellman, c., 2012: “the rights forfeiture theory of punishment”, Ethics 122: 371-93. http://clcjbooks.rutgers.edu/books/ends_of_harm.html http://clcjbooks.rutgers.edu/books/ends_of_harm.html LEAP 3 (2015) Response to Blumenson v iC TOR TA dROS University of Warwick Abstract this paper defends some of the central claims in The Ends of Harm: The Moral Foundations of Criminal Law against challenges by eric Blumenson. Key Words: Punishment, duties, retributivism, desert, proportionality introDuction i am ver y grateful to eric Blumenson for his thoughtful, insightful and wide-ranging essay engaging with my book The Ends of Harm: The Moral Foundations of Criminal Law (hereafter, Ends). Blumenson makes many points which he thinks count against the Duty view of punishment (Dv) that i defend in Ends which need careful thought. i won’t attempt to address all of his concerns. i will focus on those objections which i think he finds more telling, and where i have said less to defend the view outlined in Ends.1 Before continuing, let me clarif y one feature of the general moral and polit ica l v iew out lined in Ends t hat Blumenson brief ly engages w it h. Blumenson suggests that the account of the means principle in ends is so strict and wide ranging that it implies a form of libertarianism akin to that defended by robert nozick in Anarchy, State, and Utopia (nozick 1974). i would like to clarify the similarities and differences between my approach and nozick’s. i have some sympathy with nozick’s general methodological approach to political theory. like nozick, i think that the duties and constraints on state action are to be defended in the light of a more basic set of moral principles that govern individual interactions with each other. the state, and the principles that govern it are not, i think, sui generis. nozick’s account is more d i rect ly rel ia nt on a set of r ig ht s t ha n t hat defended i n Ends. nevertheless, otherwise there is a broad similarity between us with respect to methodology. 1 i have responded to some points that are similar to those advanced by Blumenson in tadros 2012, 2013 and 2015. Response to Blumenson 57 LEAP 3 (2015) Furthermore, like nozick, i think that there is a constraint on compelling some people to provide for others – the constraint on using some as a means to the good of others. where nozick and i differ, though, is in our understanding of the content of these rights and duties. nozick was much more skeptical than i am about enforceable positive duties, and this feature of his moral theory is central to his defence of libertarianism.2 in contrast, i believe that there are enforceable positive duties. the scope and stringency of these duties may depend on a number of factors, including the extent to which people are mutually engaged in cooperative beneficial activities. i do not provide a full account of the scope and source of positive duties in Ends – i leave that as an open question, even though it has implications for criminal justice. nevertheless, my account of the means principle emphasizes the limits of that principle in a way that nozick’s account does not. this prov ides t he possibilit y of broad ranging socia l prov ision and development aid, depending on the scope of domestic and international mora l obligations. My ow n v iew is t hat positive enforceable duties are quite extensive, and hence i believe that we have powerful obligations of these kinds that can be enforced by the state.3 this also helps to address one of Blumenson’s concerns – he thinks that relying on the ‘duty of easy rescue’ to secure the permission of the state to punish offenders is inadequate because indiv iduals do not have a ver y powerful dut y to transfer their compensatory rights to the state to ensure that other people are protected from offending. i doubt that this is right. this is so in part because victims of crime are provided with substantial benefits from a system of punishment. requiring them to allow the state to have control over their punitive rights is not typically onerous (on the contrary) and any cost that they bear as a result is more than compensated for by the benefits they are provided with. Blumenson also complains that funding health care and occupational safety would, on this view, depend on the existence of duties to provide these things through the state. But it is highly plausible that the provision of these things does depend on such duties – when we fail to provide adequate health care or occupational safety, or for that matter adequate security from crime, we fail to do what justice requires, and hence we fail to satisfy our duties to others. when we provide health care beyond these limits, the appropriate complaint does seem to be that citizens do not owe this level of health care to each other. if the state fails to demonstrate that we owe some level of health care to each other, it has failed to justify that level of health care. 2 nozick 1974, especially 30-3. 3 See, also, tadros 2011b. 58 Victor Tadros LEAP 3 (2015) i think, therefore, that the provision of social justice depends on citizens underlying duties to each other. this is not a libertarian view, at least if libertarians are committed (as nozick was) to the non-existence of general enforceable positive duties. 1. MethoDoloGy Blumenson thinks that the fact that there are many duties, with uncertain scope, involved in Dv provides some reason to reject that view. this is not a reason to reject Dv. if these duties ex ist, we ought to tr y to fulfill them. it may be that we are likely to fulfill them only approximately, but that fact does not free us from these duties. in any individual life, many of us are confronted with a wide range of duties, some of which are in conf lict with others. we have many complex duties as parents, children, professionals, friends, and simply as human beings, and it is often difficult to know whether we have fulfilled these duties. we are likely to do so only approximately at best. this fact hardly frees us of these duties, or makes them irrelevant to the way we live our lives. Blumenson also thinks that the fact that Dv has many steps should incline us against it. the success of the argument for each step, he suggests, is necessary for the success of Dv. even if we have a great deal of confidence in each step in the argument, our confidence in the conclusion should be limited if there are many steps in the argument. unfortunately, Blumenson’s argument would rule out being persuaded by any philosophical argument that relies on many steps, even where we have very powerful reasons to endorse every step in the argument. it is difficult to accept this conclusion. Furthermore, any particular moral claim relies on the truth of many other controversial claims – for example claims about moral claims. Blumenson’s argument would thus lead to more general skepticism about all particular moral claims. Finally, Blumenson’s argument makes philosophical argumentation too easy. consider the truth or falsity of act utilitarianism. act uilitarianism is false if any non-act-utilitarian claim is true. there are many non-act-utilitarian claims. even if we have very low levels of confidence in any particular claim, Blumenson’s view implies that we ought not to endorse act utilitarianism in virtue of the fact that there is some relatively high probability that one of these claims is true. i take it that this argument against act utilitarianism is not valid – to show that we ought not to accept act utilitarianism, we ought to demonstrate that we have confidence in some particular claim that is in conf lict with act utilitarianism. Response to Blumenson 59 LEAP 3 (2015) it is also worth noting that some of the steps in the argument provided in Ends are not necessary to justif y punishment generally – they justif y punishment of particular people for particular purposes. For example, i defend the v iew that it is sometimes permissible to harm a person as a means to avert threats to people other than their immediate victims, even when they are not responsible for posing these threats. if the argument for this claim fails, punishment may still be justified in many cases. it will be justified in cases where offenders, through their offending, create threats to others. this will sometimes be so, because by offending they may undermine the effectiveness of the criminal law. it will also be justified in cases where punishing the offender helps to protect the victim from future offending. i don’t find these limits on punishment plausible, and i argued for a more expansive view. But the question under consideration is not about whether we should accept Dv, but rather about what version of Dv we should accept. 2. BluMenSon’S alternative as punishment is difficult to justif y, we should not be surprised that an argument for punishment has many steps to it. take Blumenson’s justification of punishment. one idea amongst many controversial ideas that Blumenson relies on, in defending his negative retributivism, is that punishment of the innocent is ruled out by something like the following principle: Negative Desert: it is permissible to use D as a means to the good iff D deserves to be used, and in virtue of this fact. Negative Desert is not a very clear principle. we need to know what desert means, and there are many possibilities. we also need to know what it means to deserve something ‘negatively’. i have some doubts that we can make good sense of negative desert in this sense. like many friends of desert, i think that ‘X deserves o’ implies that there is good reason for X to get o irrespective of any further good that will be secured if X gets o. if so, there is no such thing as negative desert in Blumenson’s sense. Negative Desert is not a coherent view, i claim, because it is a fact about desert, as i understand it, that if D deserves o, the value of giving o to D does not depend on any further value that giving o to D will secure instrumentally. Negative Desert is in conf lict w ith this claim about desert. it makes the reason to give D o depend on something external to D getting o – that o is a means to some further good. hence, it is not a v iew about desert, as i understand it. Perhaps Blumenson has a different conception of desert in mind in Negative Desert. without an account of that conception, i continue to find Negative Desert confused. 60 Victor Tadros LEAP 3 (2015) My suspicion that Blumenson’s view is confused was strengthened by his response to the incoherence objection. there Blumenson swithers between two different views. on the one hand, he seems to accept that desert implies that there is a positive reason to give D o, but a reason that can be outweighed. this view accepts that it is intrinsically valuable to give D what he deserves, but that this value can be out weighed. But this v iew is in conf lict w ith Blumenson’s denial that retributivists are committed to the view that it is intrinsically valuable that offenders suffer the burdens of punishment. all sensible retributivists claim that the good of offenders getting what they deserve can be outweighed. So this view is just accepts positive desert, with all of its difficulties. another view is the ‘rights forfeiture’ view. D, this view claims, loses his right against being punished in virtue of having acted wrongly. this view is not best seen as a form of retributivism at all. one reason is that rights forfeiture does not depend on desert.4 a second reason is that it is not clear how desert adds anything to a rights-forfeiture view. rights-forfeiture views of punishment claim that punishment may permissibly be inflicted to serve certain ends on condition that a person has forfeited her right against such treatment. they then argue that a person forfeits her right against such treatment by acting wrongly. it would add nothing to such theories also to claim that wrongdoers deserve to lose these rights. the language of desert adds nothing substantial to rights-forfeiture theory – it is not even clear what it means to deserve to lose a right. Dv is a version of a forfeiture view. So if, by negative desert, Blumenson simply means ‘rights forfeiture’, we are roughly in the same camp. But traditional rights-forfeiture views of punishment are superficial – the idea that wrongdoers lose rights is, of course, true on any justification of punishment. what needs explaining is why offenders lose their rights against being harmed as a means to the ends of punishment. claiming that they have lost their rights to be used in this way is a conclusion that needs defending. the duty view offers a defence of this claim: it suggests that wrongdoers lose their rights against being used for the ends of punishemnt because they incur duties to serve these ends. i also claim that nothing, or almost nothing, else is sufficient – a person loses her right not to be used to serve an end, i claim, only if she has a duty to serve that end, or would have such a duty were she able to pursue it. Blumenson does not show that this view is false. if Blumenson wishes to defend a rights forfeiture view of punishment, he ought not to refer to desert. the idea that D has forfeited her right against being treated in a certain way does not depend on desert. if he rejects the 4 See, for example, McMahan 2009: 8-9. Response to Blumenson 61 LEAP 3 (2015) kind of rights forfeiture view defended in Ends, he should supply an alternative explanation how wrongdoers lose their rights against being punished. Furthermore, any convincing and complete account of rights-forfeiture will be controversial. a rights-forfeiture theorist needs both to provide an account of why people lose rights, and an account of the extent to which they lose rights. one reason why the argument in Ends is complex is that it attempts to make substantial progress with both questions. Simple rights-forfeiture views seem comparatively simple, but that is only because they avoid making progress with the difficult questions about why people lose rights, and the extent of the rights they lose. let’s suppose that there is such a thing as negative desert. let's suppose that there is such a thing as negative desert. like Dv negative Desert relies on very controversial premises if it is to play the role in the justification of punishment that Blumenson wants it to play. Defending some particular account of desert against others will be controversial. this is obviously so as there are many different claims that f riends of deser t ma ke about t he nature of deser t.5 Fur t hermore, a ny interpretation of Negative Desert is extremely controversial. even if there is such a thing as negative desert, it is not uncontroversial that we can deserve to be used. it is not uncontroversial that anything like criminal wrongdoing is the desert basis for being used. and it is not uncontroversial – in fact it is clearly false - that it is only permissible to use a person as a means to the good only in virtue of the fact that the person deserves to be used. that this is clearly false is demonstrated by the fact that we can mount relatively uncontroversial arguments for the permissible using of others without relying on desert. Negative Desert is by no mea ns t he most cont roversia l element of Blumenson’s view, though. it relies on another claim: that the state has an obligation to punish wrongdoers even when this will produce no net social benefit ‘when this is obligatory in order to fulfill the state’s social contract obligations to the victim because no less draconian route is sufficient to do so’. this element of Blumenson’s view also relies on many controversial claims, and so is vulnerable to Blumenson’s own argument. it relies on the success of following argument: the state has social contract obligations to victims. these social contract obligation that the state owes to the victim require the state not to ignore wrongdoing. 5 even within the camp of the intrinsic goodness desert view, there is an enormous range of possibilities, many of which have gone unnoticed. For an exhausting, but perhaps not exhaustive, exploration of many of them, see Kagan 2012. 62 Victor Tadros LEAP 3 (2015) if serious wrongdoing is not punished, the state ignores wrongdoing. therefore the state must punish serious wrongdoing. this argument is even more controversial than Negative Desert. First, the socia l cont ract t radit ion is ex t remely cont roversia l. i doubt t hat state obligations are grounded in social contract obligations. More importantly, it is not clear why the state, in failing to punish, necessarily ignores wrongdoing. there are many different non-punitive responses that the state might make to wrongdoing that would demonstrate that the state takes wrongdoing seriously. Given that punishing offenders is necessarily burdensome to the offender, but not necessarily burdensome to the state, it is also not clear why punishing offenders is sufficient to demonstrate that the state takes wrongdoing seriously. if i want to show that i take something seriously, it is i that should demonstrate a willingness to bear burdens for the sake of that thing. in punishing offenders, the state only demonstrates that it is willing to burden someone else – the offender. this may simply show that the state does not care much about the offender, not that it takes the wrongdoing seriously. Furthermore, it is not clear that by refraining from punishing a person who has committed a serious wrong against the victim the state withdraws the status of citizens as valued members of the political community, as Blumenson cla ims. to demonst rate its commit ment to t he v ict im, t he sensible thing to do is to help the victim. Punishing the offender may be one way to help the victim. the argument in Ends is intended to demonstrate that. But it is not the only way. the victim could be helped by being provided with extra protection by the state, or by being compensated in other ways. and the state could publicly express the importance of the v ictim, and educate its citizens about how terrible it was that the victim suffered in the way that she did. none of this requires punishing the offender. if the state does these things, is it really true that the state devalues the v ictim or denies his civic personhood? So spelling out and defending Negative Retributivism requires an argument with many steps in it. as we have reason to doubt each of these steps (in my view, decisive reasons to reject some steps), Blumenson’s ‘diminishing returns’ argument, if successful, defeats his own view as well as mine. Blumenson responds t hat a n a rg ument w it h mu lt iple steps is more credible if its conclusion is independently intuitively attractive. he thinks that negative retributiv ism is intuitively more attractive than the dut y view. i don’t find retributivism intuitively attractive. Blumenson’s version seems unclear. negative retributivists can simply assert that those who we Response to Blumenson 63 LEAP 3 (2015) intuitively think ought to be punished lack a right against being punished. But then the theory does little more than reporting our considered convictions about punishment rather than explaining them. More standard retributivist views are also unclear, and seem barbaric. Few claims need more careful defence than the claim that it is impersonally valuable that wrongdoers suffer. though some people believe this claim, it is not by itself intuitive – it rests on the idea that suffering and harm are sometimes to be sought for their inherent properties, and many recoil at this thought. Furthermore, i don’t think that the explanation that Dv gives for the permissibilit y of punishment is intuitively unattractive. First, the vast majority of people, when asked why we punish offenders, cite prevention as the aim. Dv offers an argument why it is permissible, subject to certain constraints, to harm offenders to secure this aim. But the aim that Dv advocates is familiar and attractive. Secondly, the idea that offenders may permissibly be used to secure this aim in v irtue of their w rongdoing is attractive. Dv then gives an answer to the familiar objection that offenders may not be used merely as a means to secure this aim – that offenders can be expected to serve the end of protection in virtue of having acted wrongly. this is the most original part of Dv, but i don’t think that the response to the objection is itself unintuitive. 3. other wayS oF FulFillinG the Duty Dv relies on t he idea t hat t he permissibi lit y of punishing of fenders is grounded in the (primarily protective) duties that offenders incur as a result of their wrongdoing. Blumenson, in challenging Step 6 of his summary, argues that it is a weakness of Dv that this would allow uneven punishment of offenders in cases where offenders have discharged the protective duties that they owe to their victims in other ways. i think that this implication of Dv is one of its strengths. 3.1. Who Gets to Decide one question that Blumenson raises, that has also been raised by Kim Ferzan, is why the state should be in a position to decide how the duty that the offender owes to the victim is satisfied. Ferzan raised the following objection to Dv. She argued that if the offender owes a duty to the victim, it is for the victim to determine what the offender does for her. if she wants protection, she can secure protection from him. if she wants her car washed, she can secure that end (Ferzan 2013). in response, i 64 Victor Tadros LEAP 3 (2015) argued that it would be w rong for the v ictim to impose any significant harm on the offender for the sake of her car. the offender can be harmed for the victim’s sake only if any harm imposed on him is proportionate to the end sought (tadros 2013). Blumenson does not think that this obviates the problem that Ferzan raises. i do not see why. the first thing to note is that offenders obviously do owe very stringent duties to the victims of their wrongdoing. Blumenson’s challenge of explaining how these duties can best be fulfilled is thus quite general. if punishment does not vitiate these duties, offenders retain them. if Blumenson thinks that offenders retain these duties, how does he think they ought to be fulfilled? Does he think, for example, that after the offender is punished, the offender may nevertheless be seriously harmed again for the sake of the victim? nevertheless, we should meet the challenge posed by Blumenson. why does Blumenson doubt that Dv can meet it? it is not completely clear, but perhaps Blumenson believes something like this: if D owes a duty to act for the sake of v at some cost n, v may impose n on D for any end whatsoever. this v iew, though, is not credible. it is not generally true of duties. For example, the fact that i have promised to deliver a television to your house implies that i must bear the cost of driv ing to your house. that, though, does not imply that you may impose on me the cost of driv ing to your house for some other end. the most important restriction on the duty imposed on offenders is that any cost that the offender is compelled to bear must be proportionate to the end sought. For example, if D kills one of v’s children, it is plausible that v can kill D as a means to protect another of v’s children if that is the only way to protect the second child. this is so in virtue of the stringent protective duty that D incurs to v, and to v’s child. this does not imply that it would be permissible for v to kill D for fun, or to use D’s skin to make a handbag, for the harm imposed on D would be disproportionate to the good of having fun or getting a handbag. hence, if the victim has a right to decide how the duty that the offender owes to her is satisfied, she has a right to decide only within a certain range of goods that are sufficiently important to justify the harm imposed on the offender. now, there might be some circumstances in which the victim does have a right to decide, and the state would act wrongly in making the decision for her. For example, suppose that both v and X, who is v’s husband, are now threatened with death. D can be used as a means to protect either v or X but not both. it is plausible that v is permitted to determine whether to use D to protect v or to protect X. it follows that it would be wrong for the state to use D to protect v if v would prefer that X be protected. needless to say, Response to Blumenson 65 LEAP 3 (2015) though, the fact that it would be wrong, in these circumstances, for the state to decide for the victim does not militate powerfully against Dv, for these circumstances very rarely arise. it is also worth noting that the state does sometimes give the v ictim cont rol over how t he of fender’s dut ies a re sat isf ied. For exa mple, it is common in restorat ive just ice prog ra ms to prov ide t he v ict im w it h a n opportunity to decide what the offender should do in response to having offended. within some limited range of options, this will sometimes be appropriate. in determining whether the state or the victim ought to decide how D’s duty is satisfied, we must also bear in mind a number of other factors that count against victims making decisions. First, if victims are entitled to make decisions about how the offender’s duty is satisfied, they will be at risk of coercion from offenders.6 Secondly, victims, who will often feel resentment towards offenders, may be inclined to seek retribution by imposing heavier costs on offenders than necessary. thirdly, the victim owes duties to other citizens, including protective duties, and she may be required to select a particular way of satisfying the duty that the offender owes to her because this will best satisfy these protective duties.7 Fourthly, if the state punishes the offender, certain other values, such as communicative values, can be advanced, and this provides some reason for the state uniformly to determine how the offender is punished. if the victim does not have a strong reason to prefer that the duty that is owed to her is satisfied in one way rather than another, it is permissible to ensure that the duty owed to her is satisfied in a particular way to advance other values. overall, the idea that the victim should have complete choice over how the offender’s duty is morally abhorrent, unrealistic and impractical. hence, the fact that victims typically have a right to determine how the duties owed to them are satisfied is not a significant challenge to Dv. 3.2 Duties and the Wealthy the second part of Blumenson’s challenge concerns wealthy offenders. there are three features of this challenge that should be separated. one question is whether it is plausible that w rongdoers who have taken on burdens for the sake of their victims ought nevertheless to be punished. Dv implies that if these burdens are sufficiently large they ought not to be. a second question concerns the relationship between punishment and compensation. 6 See, also, the discussion concerning giv ing the v ictim control over prosecution decisions in tadros 2011a: 296. 7 See tadros 2011a: 297-9. 66 Victor Tadros LEAP 3 (2015) Does Dv deny the victim the right to seek monetary compensation from her offender? a third question is whether Dv has plausible implications for the punishment of the wealthy, who may have the means to provide a great deal of protection to others at little cost to themselves. to assess the first question, suppose that v is attacked by a gang, including D, X, y and Z. D assaults v. let us suppose that it would have been permissible to harm D as a means to avert this threat, harming him to degree x. if the harm that D does to v is large, x will be even larger. this is for the reason that it is generally permissible to harm a person to avert a threat that they culpably pose, even if the harm that is necessary to avert the threat is greater than the harm that the person would do if the threat they pose were realized. D then realizes that what he did was wrong. v still faces a threat from X, y and Z. D, recognizing the duty that he owes to v, now protects v against X, y and Z. he is harmed to degree x in the process. Blumenson implies that the state nevertheless ought to punish D. this seems wrong. D has borne a great cost in order to protect v against X, y and Z. it is wrong to harm D even more for punitive reasons. the idea that we should punish people who have already voluntarily borne great costs for the sake of their victims fails adequately to acknowledge the idea that people can redeem themselves for their wrongdoing through their voluntary actions. in response to Blumenson’s second challenge, there is nothing in Dv that rules out the provision of monetary compensation to victims where monetary compensation is available, and can help to ameliorate the victim’s loss. in evaluating the comparative merits of a compensation scheme against a punitive scheme, we ought not simply to consider what would be beneficial to indiv idual v ictims where most offenders are punished. we ought to consider the circumstances of victims were no one punished. in a system where compensation was the only available remedy for theft, for example, people would be very insecure in their property. in those circumstances, a compensatory scheme would be wholly inadequate to secure property rights. hence, there would be powerful reasons to criminalize theft. nevertheless, even if theft is criminalized, victims may seek monetary compensation from offenders. to explain why this is so, notice the following feature of Dv. obligations to compensate others are subject to two constraints – a constraint on the maximum amount of harm that can be imposed on the wrongdoer (what i have called the maximum harm threshold) and a constraint on the maximum amount of benefit that can be secured from the wrongdoer (the maximum benefit threshold). Dv accepts that there is a maximum harm threshold beyond which the offender may not be harmed, though not a maximum benefit threshold. Below the former threshold, we must consider how the offender Response to Blumenson 67 LEAP 3 (2015) is to be ha rmed, a nd for whose benef it. ha rm may be imposed on t he offender to provide monetary compensation to the victim, to deter, or a combination of the two. this has the attraction that it limits the overall harm that an offender suffers as a result of his wrongdoing. if the offender provides compensation to the victim, and this is very burdensome to him, the amount that he may be punished is reduced. Blumenson’s claim that, according to Dv, offenders who are punished owe no compensation to their victim is thus false. that depends on how much the offender is punished. it is true that if an offender is punished up to the maximum harm threshold, he may not be harmed further to compensate the victim. But this is an attractive implication of Dv. if, though, the offender is punished to some degree less than the maximum harm threshold, compensation may be extracted from him for the victim’s sake. Given that the victim will typically have been rendered much worse off than she would have been by the offenders action, there is good reason to ensure that we should aim to improve the victim’s circumstances. the question is how best to do this. the third feature of Blumenson’s challenge concerns the way in which we should respond to the greater protective resources available to the wealthy. as i have said a great deal about this elsewhere, i will make my comments brief. in compensatory justice, the maximum benefit threshold is normally set at the level of full compensation. it is contested how full compensation should be understood,8 but in standard cases, if the wrongdoer has rendered the victim as well off as she would have been had the wrongdoer not wrongfully harmed her, he has fully compensated her. the maximum harm threshold implies that there is a limit to how much the w rongdoer may be harmed in order to prov ide the v ictim w ith full compensation. if full compensation to the victim would require us to harm the wrongdoer a great deal, it is impermissible to extract full compensation from the wrongdoer. with respect to serious wrongdoing, whilst there is a maximum harm threshold, there is no maximum benefit threshold. wrongdoers cannot satisfy the duties incurred through wrongdoing simply by providing full compensation to victims. if the provision of full compensation is not onerous, they can be expected to do more to protect the victim, and perhaps to protect others. Given this, the fact that the wealthy can provide a great deal of protection to victims at little cost does not imply that they may not be punished to produce further protection if they provide this level of protection.9 8 i discuss this further in tadros 2014a. 9 For further defence of this view, demonstrating how it comes apart from retributivism, see, tadros 2011a: 286-91; 2012: 99-102; 2013: 300-9. 68 Victor Tadros LEAP 3 (2015) Blumenson, i think, agrees w ith this verdict, but thinks that this is tantamount to a form of negative retributivism. this is false. First, the scope and stringency of the duties that we owe in virtue of wrongdoing are not, in general, best explained by desert. when we act wrongly, we incur duties. we do not incur them because we deserve to incur them. of course, we should explain why we have these duties – for example, because we can redeem ourselves by responding appropriately to our wrongdoing, or because we could have avoided having them, or some other explanation. it is difficult to see how desert claims figure in an explanation of the duties that we incur. of course, we could define retributivism in a way that corresponds to the duties that we incur through wrongdoing. we could simply claim that when a person incurs a stringent duty in virtue of having wrongdoing, that just is her getting what she deserves. But if the retributivist claims this, she just accepts Dv, but mangles the terminology. now, Blumenson looks for a n ex pla nat ion why serious w rongdoers cannot satisfy their duties simply by providing full compensation to their victims. he complains that my defence of this is vague. i agree that there is more to say about this issue than i said in Ends. there i noted the fact that it is implausible that the duties of serious wrongdoers are satisfied when full compensation is provided, and gave an explanation for this by considering complaints that wrongdoers and victims could make to the scope of these duties. i also showed that the view that i endorse is intuitive in protection cases such as Three Threats. i have since done more to explain this idea, and i will say no more about it here. But whatever the merits of my explanation, Blumenson’s reference to desert does nothing to help. it is simply a bad redescription of the idea that wrongdoers incur stringent duties that are not satisfied by providing victims with full compensation. it does nothing at all to explain the source of these duties. the explanation that i provided in Ends may have been vague and incomplete. Blumenson offers no explanation at all. 4. eMPirical SuPPort Dv justifies punishment only if punishment is effective in deterring crime. i am poorly placed to do the empirical work to that is necessary to determine whether it is effective, and in which circumstances. this is partly due to my lack of empirical skills. it is also due to the fact that the empirical work could not realistically be done. w hat would be required would be a study that compares reasonably just large-scale liberal societies w ith and w ithout Response to Blumenson 69 LEAP 3 (2015) systems of punishment. But there is no reasonably just large-scale liberal society without a system of punishment. the question is whether dismantling a system of punishment and replacing it w ith some intrinsically better a lternat ive wou ld be det rimenta l to t he crime rate. if it wou ld not be detrimental to the crime rate, our system of punishment is unjustified.10 the fact t hat Dv justif ies punishment only contingent ly on it being effective in deterring crime and on it not having disproportionate bad side effects is no objection to it. Any sensible theory of punishment is contingent in this way. any system of state punishment is enormously costly. it will harm not only offenders, but innocent people as well. these costs need to be justified. the idea that they can be justified by anything other than crime reduction is implausible. even if it is true, as retributiv ists claim, t hat punishment is impersonally valuable, it is very difficult to believe that any impersonal value that it has is sufficiently great fully to justify the costs of any realistic criminal justice system. if state punishment is ineffective in reducing the crime rate, state punishment ought to be abandoned.11 5. ProPortionality Blumenson thinks that Dv cannot explain why some factors that intuitively ought to affect the sentence that we ought to impose on an offender are relevant to punishment. i am not sure why he thinks this. though it is true that i ought to have said more about this issue in Ends, it is highly plausible that both a person’s duties to avert the threats that he poses and the strength of the duties he incurs through his wrongdoing depend on the kinds of factors that Blumenson outlines as relevant to punishment. Furthermore, retributivism seems to me less well placed to explain these factors. Blumenson rightly claim that retributiv ists t y pically think that punishment shou ld ref lect t he g rav it y of t he crime a nd t he of fender’s blameworthiness for it. w hat they lack is an explanation why this is so. there is little reason to think that, on the best view of desert, what we deserve is determined by the properties of our actions. it is more plausible to think that what we deser ve depends on our v irtues and v ices.12 But this more plausible view of desert has troubling implications for a theory of punishment. retributivists typically tailor their theory of desert to provide plausible 10 For further discussion, see tadros 2012: 91-3. 11 For a compelling argument for this view, see husak 2010. 12 See, further, tadros 2011a, ch.4.ii. it is not uncommon for friends of desert in moral philosophy to think that virtue and vice over a whole life is the proper desert basis. See, for example, Kagan 2012: 6-12. ch.4.II Response to Blumenson 70 LEAP 3 (2015) implications for punishment. But if so, their justification of punishment is unsatisfactory. it is no good to begin from a conventional view about what punishment ought to be imposed for which crimes under which circumstances and justify this conventional view simply on the basis that doing what we do is impersonally valuable. what is needed is an independent argument that shows that desert explains why punishment should fit the gravity of crimes and blameworthiness for them. Such arguments are hard to find, and Blumenson offers none. Blumenson is also wrong to think that the necessity constraint on self- defence creates problems for the relationship bet ween self-defence and punishment outlined in Ends. i w ill restrict myself to an evaluation of Blumenson’s first case, as i think this the most interesting: Unnecessary Defence. a threatens v with a knife. v is able to retreat safely and therefore defensive force is unnecessary; but v fails to retreat, parries a’s thrust unsuccessfully, and dies. as harming a was not necessary to avert the threat he poses, it might be argued that a is not liable to defensive harm. Blumenson then concludes that Dv implies that he is also not liable to be punished. this argument is much too quick. First, it is not clear that a is not liable to defensive harm. it is a matter of dispute whether harming a wrongs him where harming him is unnecessary.13 i am inclined to the view that v wrongs a if v unnecessarily harms a. But this does not imply that a incurs no duties as a result of wrongfully killing v. the fact that v wrongly chose to attempt to harm a rather than retreating does not vitiate the duties that a incurs for wrongfully harming v. it is also false that a is not liable to defensive harm to avert the threat that he later poses in Unnecessary Defence.14 to see this, consider a variation on Unnecessar y Defence where X, a t hird pa r t y, cou ld inter vene a f ter v attempts to parry a’s thrust to avert the threat that a poses to v. if X harms a to avert the threat that he poses, X does not wrong a. although v acts wrongly in attempting unnecessarily to harm a, this does not vitiate a’s liability for threat that he later poses.15 Furthermore, whilst it is true that, if v successfully harms a in Unnecessary Defence, v wrongs a, it is false that it is wrong for v to harm a given that V 13 For some discussion, see, for exa mple, McMa ha n 2009 ; Firt h a nd Quong 2012; Frowe 2014. 14 Blumenson also considers the problem of criminal attempts and the significance of intentions to punishment. i say more about these issues in tadros 2013: 313-22, so i leave them aside here. 15 For related discussion, see further tadros 2014b. 71 Victor Tadros LEAP 3 (2015) has decided to stand his ground rather than to retreat. Suppose that v stands his ground. Suppose, also, that by standing his ground he gives up the opportunity that he had to retreat. he must now decide whether to harm a, parrying the blow that a aims at him, or to allow himself to be harmed by a. he may recognize that he was wrong to stand his ground, but this does not vitiate his permission to harm a. he wrongs a in virtue of the fact that he had another option which rendered his defensive force unnecessary. But despite the fact that the existence of this option renders his defensive harm wrongful, given his wrongful act he is permitted to defend himself. it follows that there is no asymmetry between liability in self-defense and liability in punishment of the kind that Blumenson’s argument relies on. concluSion obviously, there is a great deal more that would need to be done fully to meet Blumenson’s interesting and important objections to the arguments in Ends than i have done here. i hope, at least, to have shown that some of Blumenson’s objections can either be met by clarifying Dv, or by showing that the seemingly counterintuitive implications of Dv are more attractive than he thinks. Dv is a new theory of punishment. i do not claim to have worked out all of the details of the theory in Ends. i continue to think that it has a great deal of promise, despite the powerful objections that have been mounted against it. BiBlioGraPhy Ferzan, KK., 2013: "rethinking the ends of harm", Law and Philosophy 32: 177-198. Firth, J. and Quong, J., 2012: “necessity, Moral liability and Defensive harm”, Law and Philosophy 31: 673-701. Frowe, h., 2014: “non-combatant liability in war”, in How We Fight: Ethics in War, ed. h. Frowe and G. lang, oxford: oxford university Press. husak, D. n., 2010: “why Punish the Deserving?”, in The Philosophy of Criminal Law: Selected Essays, oxford: oxford university Press. Kagan, S., 2012: The Geometry of Desert, oxford: oxford university Press. McMahan, J., 2009: Killing in War, oxford: oxford university Press. nozick, r., 1974: Anarchy, State and Utopia, oxford: Blackwell. tadros, v., 2011a: The Ends of Harm: The Moral Foundations of Criminal Law, oxford: oxford university Press. — (2011b) “independence without interests?”, Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 31: 193-213 — (2012) “replies”, Jerusalem Review of Legal Studies 5: 89-109. — (2013) “responses” Law and Philosophy 32: 241-325. Response to Blumenson 72 LEAP 3 (2015) — (2014a) “what Might have Been” in Philosophical Foundations of Tort Law, ed. J. oberdiek, oxford: oxford university Press. — (2014b) “resource wars”, Law and Philosophy 33: 361-389. — (2015) “answers”, Criminal Law and Philosophy 9: 73-102. LEAP 3 (2016) Symposium Philippe van Parijs' Four Puzzles on Gender Equality LEAP 3 (2015) Unjust Gender Inequalities 1 PAU L A C A S A L ICREA & Pompeu Fabra University Many papers on gender inequality focus on one or more respects in which women, as a group, fare worse than men, with some also noting respects in which gender discrimination and oppression is bad not only for women and children but also, as John Stuart Mill recognized, for society as a whole (1869: eg. 471-5, 558, 564). All this is, of course, consistent with men being harmed by patriarchal institutions or worse off than women in some respects either because of those institutions or for independent reasons. In his controversial paper “Four Puzzles on Gender Inequality,” based on a provocative talk presented at a feminist forum, Philippe Van Parijs lists some peculiar gender inequalities. Such inequalities are puzzling not because they indicate dimensions in which women fare better than men but because they show a lack of shared and clear criteria to determine when inequality involves injustice, which is not due to predictable differences between Left and Right. Whether some inequalities require some sort of compensation or institutional reform is unclear even within a single position in distributive justice, including positions as elaborated as that of John Rawls. As readers will notice, the paper is different from the standard scholarly pieces that appear in academic journals like LEAP. However, it still serves a valuable philosophical function because the puzzles it describes raise important questions regarding which statistical differences between two social groups identify an injustice and which merely contain information t hat is eit her irreleva nt or t hat bea rs a more indirect relat ion to socia l justice. The va lue of discussing t hese questions, stressed by Van Parijs’ response “Real Freedom for All Women (and Men),” thus extends well beyond feminism. In addition, each instance of gender inequality Van Parijs describes is a lso intrig uing in its ow n right, and not only as an illustration of t he general problem just described. So, the discussion published here aims to contribute to an exchange that is informative and engaging not only for those interested in gender but also for those working on distributive justice more generally. 1. I thank Philippe Van Parijs and all participants for their cooperation and contributions a nd Serena Olsa retti for usef u l comments on t his introduction. For help w it h t he entire exchange, I thank Andrew Williams for excellent philosophical advice, and Laura Sánchez de la Sierra and Hannah Weber for their conscientious editorial assistance. Unjust Gender Inequalities 75 LEAP 3 (2015) the first potential injustice van Parijs’ paper discusses concerns the fact that women live longer than men. this issue, prev iously discussed not only by conservatives like John Kekes (1997: 100ff ) and men’s rights advocates like David Benatar (2012: 57ff ), but also by luck egalitarians like Shlomi Segall (2010: 105ff ), brings out the controversy over whether there are normative differences bet ween natural and social inequalities. the authors who successively agreed to contribute a piece on this puzzle turned out to be unable to deliver it. and so, despite the fact that leaP editors do not normally contribute to any exchanges, i ended up w riting a (doubly blind refereed) reply to this first puzzle not to delay publication further. the response, “Distributive Justice and longevity,” claims that on plausible liberal egalitarian views men’s lack of female longevity is not an injustice. the second potential injustice concerns women’s greater educational achievements. this new trend is worth attending to inter alia because women’s lower educational achievements used to be deemed an important cause of gender inequality (e.g. okin 1989: ch. 7, esp. 142-7). in “women’s Greater educational efforts as a consequence of inequality,” Jesús Mora denies there is any injustice here because society does not offer men any less educational opportunities. instead, men reject or squander their equal or greater educational opportunities because society already offers them such good opportunities that they do not need qualifications as desperately as women, who, by contrast, in view of their greater likelihood of suffering domestic and workplace exploitation, take up the opportunities they have more conscientiously. a third puzzle highlighted by van Parijs concerns the fact that most voters are women, both because women live longer and because educated individuals tend to vote more. in “Do women enjoy a Political advantage?” Pierre-Étienne vandamme denies this inequality is an injustice or even an advantage because mere membership in a majority group cannot plausibly be judged so. Moreover, i f women a re not vot i ng sel f-ser v i ng ly, it i s i nappropr iate to respond to t hei r d ischa rg i ng t hei r dut y to vote a nd protect public goods or v ulnerable groups, like children or animals, by depriving them of resources we other w ise deem theirs. a fourth and final puzzle arises from three distinct inequalities, which may or may not represent injustices: inequalities in the possession of certain hormones, in incarceration rates, and in sexual desire. in fact, the final puzzle actually contains three distinct puzzles, which is why there are three responses to it. “hormona l inequa lit y” is t he claim t hat men are handicapped by possessing more hormones linked to undesirable behaviors such as those involving imprudence or aggression. in “a Blatant case of over-accommodation,” valeria ottonelli grants that the set of propensities van Parijs describes as 76 Paula Casal LEAP 3 (2015) linked to male hormones could, in some sense, be understood as disabilities. But she argues that the over-accommodation of the unfortunate traits has effectively turned them into advantages. one cannot thus claim hormonal inequality is an injustice that needs to be rectified or that diminishes the inequality between men and women. inequalities in incarceration rates are a ver y different matter. First, incarceration is something only a minority of men experience, rather than part of men’s normal constitution, like male hormones. Second, incarceration is not something that happens “naturally” but is instead a social method to prevent a murderer or rapist from committing further crimes and to deter other individuals from acting likewise. third, unlike hormones, incarceration rates bring back the debate between natural and social inequalities and causation. van Parijs compares the higher incarceration rates suffered by men w ith those suffered by the v ictims of social injustice, povert y and racial discrimination, despite the fact that it is women that are more often the v ictims of social injustice, povert y, and discrimination. however, in “are unequal incarceration rates unjust to Men?” Gina Schouten answers affirmatively, even if men are the beneficiaries of injustice and guilty of the crimes for which they have been imprisoned. a final issue involves the fact that men tend to be more interested in sex than women, and hire prostitutes or act foolishly, harming themselves and others in the pursuit of sexual gratification. in “the rich also cry,” ana de Miguel not only addresses the issue of prostitution and male desire. in addition, she also tries, to some extent like vandamme, to explain why van Parijs’ original audience reacted with hostility to his talk. one reason for the adverse reaction seems to be the way van Parijs’ comments on prostitution sit outside decades of feminist work on the fact that almost all clients of prostitutes– including child prostitutes – are male, and how the sex industry and much of society caters to male desires for sex and domination that men do not regret. 2 van Parijs, of course, does not claim that since men have certain desires women should give in to men’s demands. however, at least part of the hostile reaction appears to have been caused by his unawareness of the way, vividly illustrated by de Miguel, in which portraying male sexual “greediness” as a burden men bear can be used, and has been used, for oppressive purposes. 2. For example, since men want novelt y and ethnic variet y, pimps regularly relocate prostitutes, preventing t hem f rom forming attachments t hat ca n undermine t he pimp`s control (de Miguel 2015:165). in the wider society, too, sexual access to women is maximized by keeping them poor, voiceless, isolated, homebound, or foot-bound, in harems or brothels, and by inventing religions like that of trokosi, deukis, and devadasi that sanctify sexual slavery, or by brainwashing girls into “wifely duties” and obedience because “men can’t help it.” Unjust Gender Inequalities 77 LEAP 3 (2015) van Parijs was moved by the desire to understand distributive justice better and was not thinking about possible misuses of his questions nor about t he ex istence of a men’s right movement, w it h which he has no connection. however, as women’s position slowly improves in developed societies, and men’s rights groups grow and become more vocal academically, legally, and politically, these sorts of misencounters and heated reactions are only likely to multiply and escalate. it is, therefore, preferable to examine calmly and separately each claim about a potential injustice to men. Some disputes may be solved by mere exposure to the relevant empirical research and by clarifying misunderstandings or faulty patterns of reasoning, whilst others may involve reasonable disagreements, or refer to an important unfairness to men that needs to be institutionally addressed. in all cases, however, it seems preferable to discuss such matters amicably when one has well-disposed interlocutors eager to do so, than to ignore potentially reasonable considerations. Failing to discuss such concerns is likely to fuel the growing resentment that is already brewing in the men’s rights movement. Some general recommendations one can extract from the exchange between van Parijs and the other six political philosophers who respond to him are also likely to prevent other inequalities from being misconstrued as injustices. the first is that we should not zoom in and focus on an isolated inequality, for example, on education or longevity, without also zooming out to take a wider picture that may change the significance of the observed inequalities. the second is that we should not assume all statistical regularities indicate the existence of constraints reducing individuals’ options, responsibility, or liabilities. For example, the fact that there is a strong statistical correlation between excessive power and corruption does not mean that power reduces people’s options and should be seen as an attenuating circumstance making the powerful less liable to punishment for corruption. Finally, we cannot assume inequalities are reduced whenever the better-off engage in unadvisable behavior. For example, we may have reasons not to count the badness of being corrupt as something that diminishes the inequalit y bet ween the very powerful and the powerless. 3 3. one example can illustrate all three points. it was statistically very normal for slave- owners to pick a slave and force her to satisfy whatever sexual whim they had. the way the slave’s family looked at the slave-owner doing so or perhaps the expression of the slave-owners’ wife or daughter if they saw him may have caused him a temporary discomfort. however, it would seem odd to focus on that discomfort as an inequality justice requires amending, once we zoom out and take into account the circumstances that surround the discomfort and explain it. Second, the fact that it was common for slave-owners to exploit slaves sexually does not automatically mean slave-owners were constrained or lacked sufficient opportunity to act differently. Finally, it would be strange to deem the slave-driver’s greater tendency towards additional wrong doing as something that reduced the inequality between masters and slaves. 78 Paula Casal LEAP 3 (2015) the following exchange discusses several inequalities seen both from a narrower and a wider focus by van Parijs and his commentators, ref lecting on relevant factors that surround each of them. after all, it is by placing all the pieces together rather than by staring at each one in isolation that puzzles are usually solved. BiBlioGraPhy Benatar, D. 2012: The Second Sexism - Discrimination Against Men and Boys. oxford: wiley-Blackwell De Miguel, a. 2015: Neoliberalismo Sexual. El mito de la libre elección. valencia: cátedra. Kekes, J. 1997: Against Liberalism. ithaca: cornell university Press. Mill, J.S. [1869] 1998: “the Subjection of women”, in On Liberty and other Essays. oxford: oxford university Press. okin, S. 1989: Justice, Gender and the Family. ny: Basic Books. Segall, S. 2010: Health, Luck and Justice. nJ: Princeton university Press. LEAP 3 (2015) Four Puzzles on Gender Equality PHiLiPPE vA n PA R ijS Université Catholique de Louvain Abstract there are dimensions a long which men seem to be disadvantaged, on average, relative to women. For example, they can expect to live less years; in a growing number of countries they are, on average, less educated than women; they form an electoral minority; and their greater propensity to misbehave means that the overwhelming majority of the prison population is drawn from their ranks. these disadvantages, if they are real, all derive from an unchosen feature shared by one category of human beings: being a male. Does it follow that these advantages are unjust? Key words : gender equa lit y, socia l just ice, polit ica l power, crimina lit y, phi losophy PreaMBle Part of my job consists in giving talks. Many of them leave hardly any trace in my memory, but some of them i shall remember forever. one of these is the short speech i agreed to give in Brussels on the 25t h of april, 2013 at the 2013 JuMP forum, a big annual event “for advancing women in the workplace.” what happened? over a year prior to the event, i had been asked by JuMP’s wonderfully dy namic director, my ex-student isabella lenarduzzi, whether i would agree to take part in a débat des philosophes on gender equality before an audience of hundreds of bright and active women. Despite my lacking any specific expertise on the subject, i accepted her kind invitation to open that debate, on the assumption that it would provide an opportunity for a common ref lection on real and difficult issues, rather than for a rambling rehearsal of well-meaning platitudes. Given the time limit (ten minutes for the initial input), i asked whether i could be gently provocative. “excellent,” isabella said. Because of unexpected technical difficulties, the debate had to take place without simultaneous translation, and hence in english rather than 80 Philippe Van Parijs LEAP 3 (2015) in Dutch and French, as initially announced. For this reason, i probably skipped some qualifications. i did warn my audience that some of what i was going to say would be said ‘tongue-in-cheek’ but did not realize that this opaque metaphor meant nothing to many of them. yet, as at least part of the audience laughed when i expected them to laugh, i felt confident that i was being understood. i started realizing that something had gone wrong when booing joined t he clappi ng a f ter i f i n i shed. t h i s w a s soon con f i r med by t he f i r st com mentator: my speech, t he ma n sa id, had been a n i nsu lt to bot h women and philosophy. after several other reactions in a milder tone but a similar vein, i was given a couple of interrupted minutes to start clarifying what badly needed clarifying – obviously not enough to convince the lady in charge of the conclusion that, behind the appearance of some of the worst bullshit she had ever heard, something was hiding that even she might have found palatable. t he r e s u lt , i c on fe s s, w a s s ome pr e d ic t a ble f r u st r at ion . Fac i ng a disapproving, even indignant, audience is part of the price we have to accept paying occasionally for playing our role as academics – i.e., people whose fate is not dependent on their popularity and who therefore have the freedom and responsibility to say what they believe is right even if their audience does not like to hear it. But the source of my frustration, in this case, was different. the part of the audience i had unintentionally upset, i felt, was not indignant because of what i said and thought, but because of what they had some reason to believe i said and thought, though never said or thought. and the fault, i realized, was mine. w hat follows is a w ritten version of what i did say on that occasion, without any significant alteration in substance or form. however, after the introduction and each of the four puzzles i presented, i have added (in italics) a slightly longer comment. these comments are meant to spell out more clearly what my ten-minute speech tried to say. i conclude with a brief epilogue on the connection between the philosophical questions i wanted to raise and the struggle for greater gender justice. 1. BacKGrounD: Multi-DiMenSional inJuStice towarDS woMen i was invited to introduce a philosophical debate on equality between men and women. i want to do so in a way that befits a philosopher, that is, by questioning assumptions that are too easily taken for granted, by asking questions that may sound incongruous or that one would prefer not to ask Four Puzzles on Gender Equality 81 LEAP 3 (2015) oneself. in particular, as i am addressing an audience with an overwhelming majority of women, i want to draw attention to four dimensions along which gender inequality does exist, but in women’s favor. i am not claiming that they are all of the same importance, nor that they can, without qualification, be regarded as dimensions of gender injustice. i am claiming even less that the disadvantages incurred by men along these four dimensions currently offset the disadvantages incurred by women along many others. [T hese other dimensions do not only include those most commonly mentioned, such as the income gap on both an annual and hourly basis, the extent to which women and men occupy positions of political or economic power, or the extent to which men and women perpetrate violence on members of the other gender. They also include, for example, the fact that, on average, women (have to) spend more time and money on their external appearance, wear more uncomfortable shoes, cover or uncover parts of their body, or are de facto denied access to public spaces or means of public transport at certain times. This last aspect is of particular and growing importance, as highlighted, for example, by the conjunction of the motivation behind last year’s “Picnic the Streets” action on Brussels’ central lanes and of Sofie Peeters’ superb documentary “Femme de la rue.”1 Sustainability will require us to live more and more packed together in cities, with urban housing becoming ever more expensive and hence private space ever smaller. This makes the quality and safet y of public spaces ever more important for the well-being of all, and freedom from threats and harassment in those places increasingly crucial for a fair distribution of access to such well-being between women and men.] nothing in what i am going to say amounts to belittling the importance of these various dimensions or to denying that the disadvantages incurred by women along these dimensions far exceed the advantages i am about to sketch. But i do want to question the view that the latter is true as a matter of necessity or that it will be true forever. 2. liFe eXPectancy life expectancy at birth is currently 82.5 years for european women and 76 for european men. one might be tempted to regard this as a minor advantage: an additional six years of life would be of greater value if they could be squeezed i n at age 30 or 40 rat her t ha n added at age 80. But t h is is a 1 “Picnic the Streets” is a movement that started with a massive unauthorized sit-in triggered by the opinion piece i published under that title in the Belgian press in May 2012 and that led to the city’s decision to pedestrianize Brussels’ central lanes. “Femme de la rue” is a short film first broadcast in July 2012 that documented how women were being harassed in some streets of central Brussels. 82 Philippe Van Parijs LEAP 3 (2015) confusion. w hat hides behind the gap bet ween the average lengths of women’s and men’s lives is a greater probability for a woman to reach and enjoy her forties, her fifties, her sixties, and so on, not only her nineties. one necessar y consequence is that the gap bet ween men’s and women’s incomes is smaller on a lifelong basis than on an annual basis: on average, men get a significantly higher income than women in every year they live, but they live less years. My point, however, is more fundamental. as regards inequalities in life, there is something that is presumably even more valuable than income: life itself. [Perhaps a better way of conveying my point is as follows. Imagine a society in which one gender dies on average at age 50, the other at age 55, but the former has an average annual income 10 % higher than the latter (with everyone guaranteed a decent minimum income). If this is all you know, which gender would you prefer to belong to? My guess is that many of us would go for the longer life. If instead, you would prefer to belong to the gender with the higher annual income, reiterate the thought experiment with a 5% , a 1% or even a 0.1% income gap, while leaving the respective life expectancies unchanged. I doubt that anyone would need to go to such a low income differential before indicating a preference for the gender with a longer life expectancy. As long as most people would be willing to give up some income in order to live longer, women’s higher life expectancy reduces the inequality between men and women. This claim is not self-evident, as shown by two interesting objections. Firstly, whereas the socially produced income inequality between the two genders is an injustice, should we not say that the inequalit y in life expectancies is not, because it derives either from a biological difference or a difference in lifestyles (or a combination of both)? In the former case, it is a natural fact, not a social injustice. In the latter case, it is a matter of choice for which people need to be held responsible, not of social circumstances which social justice requires us, as far as possible, to neutralize. But are just institutions not also required to reduce natural inequalities, say, between the more talented and the less talented, between the able-bodied and the handicapped? And are gender-specific lifestyles not a matter of social norms at least as much as of individual choice? Secondly, doesn’t the alleged advantage of women in terms of life expectancy overlook the inequality in the distribution of care work generated by this very advantage? Women do not only live five or six years longer than men, they are also on average two or three years younger than their male partner. This means that far more women than men are likely to still be around when their ageing partner is becoming frail and dependent. As long as much of the elderly care required in these circumstances is performed within the household, the necessar y consequence is a ver y significant inequalit y in the amount of Four Puzzles on Gender Equality 83 LEAP 3 (2015) domestic elderly care work performed by the two genders, which — as lives get longer and children fewer — may approximate or even exceed the size of the inequality in the respective amounts of domestic child care. Note that this holds even under the unrealistic assumption that both the will and capacity to care for their partner are the same for men and women. In this light, men’s lower life expectancy might be interpreted as a trick to extract more care work out of women. Its impact could only be neutralized if elderly care work were 100% outsourced — which hardly seems desirable, even if it were affordable — or if women had male partners on average 5 or 6 years younger than them — which, for whatever reason, does not seem on the horizon.] 3. eDucational achieveMent ever since the invention of school, men have long enjoyed a huge educational advantage over women. in most, if not all, developed countries, this has ceased to be the case for some years. in the european union, for example, the percentage of women with a higher education degree is 25%, compared to 22% for men. and in Sweden, often regarded as the forerunner in matters of gender equality, the corresponding figures are 35% for women and 25% for men. isn’t the concern to reduce this inequality overshooting? [One may reply that some overshooting would do no harm. After centuries of massive inequalit y favoring men, a few decennia of some inequalit y favoring women would be welcome. However, even if today’s men were the descendants of yesterday’s men only and today’s women of yesterday’s women only, thereby forming two separate lineages, this sort of intergenerational revenge would have a hard time passing as justice between members of the current generation. If only because today’s men are just as much as today’s women the descendants of the female victims of yesterday’s injustice, I doubt anyone will, on reflection, take this objection seriously. Far more serious is the objection that even though women are, on average, more highly educated than men, they still earn lower incomes. This would seem to make the injustice even worse: not only do women get paid less than men, but they do so despite studying harder. No doubt this paradoxical situation is due in part to the time it takes for differences in educational accomplishment to be reflected in differences in professional success, but also and probably to a larger extent to the fact that women choose studies that lead to less lucrative careers. If this is the main factor, can the paradox still be viewed as amplifying the injustice? Whatever the verdict on the previous two issues, there is a third consideration worth pondering. Irrespective of its specific content, the level of education 84 Philippe Van Parijs LEAP 3 (2015) matters for reasons irreducible to earning power: it has a significant impact on health, for example, or on empowerment as citizens and household members. This is arguably why it features as an important separate variable in indexes of a countr y’s human development proposed as alternatives to GDP per capita. If we accept this proposition, we seem led again to the same sort of trade- off as in the case of life expectancy: women’s emerging educational advantage should then be regarded as offsetting (albeit in small part) men’s economic advantage. Or can this only be said if the educational advantage is due to a difference in innate ability rather than to a difference in effort?] 4. Political Power if you combine the first two inequalities, you are in a position to predict the growth of a third one. From women’s longer life expectancy, it necessarily follows, with universal suffrage, that they form a majority in the electorate. Moreover, in countries in which voting is not compulsory, there tends to be a significant statistical correlation between level of education and actually using the right to vote. even in Belgium, where the vote is supposed to be obligatory, the less educated, i gather, are over represented in the growing percentage of non-voters. consequently, the growing educational gap between women and men can be expected to express itself in a continuous strengthening of women’s electoral majority.2 if as a result of these trends women regularly cast over 60% of the votes, can it not be said that there is a political inequality in their favor, no doubt less outrageous as regards both size and source than the one that long prevailed in our so-called democratic past, but nonetheless real? Moreover, this inequality would hold even if the people elected into power by t his predomina nt ly fema le electorate kept being most ly men. on t he assumption that the electorate is not stupid or blind, these people, whether women or men, w ill only be elected and re-elected if the policies they propose or adopt match the preferences of the female majority. [again, a simple thought experiment may make the point more vividly. Suppose you can choose between two electoral systems: one in which only women can vote and only men can be elected, and one in which only men can vote and only women can be elected. which would you prefer? isn’t it obvious that those concerned with the fate of all women, rather than the career prospects of a few, should prefer the former to the latter? if this is the case, shouldn’t the fact that women form a growing proportion of the voters (if it is a fact) count as a significant political inequality in their favor? 2 this must be asserted with some caution, as one would need to verif y that, for any given level of education, men do not vote more than women and that the overall positive correlation between education and voting holds for both genders taken separately. Four Puzzles on Gender Equality 85 LEAP 3 (2015) Moreover, this inequality in electoral power is one which, if they so wished (and contrary to the institutional assumption in the thought experiment of the previous paragraph), women could convert into an even greater inequality in their favor among those who hold political responsibilities. this would be the case, for example, if our electoral system were organized so as to aggregate the votes of women and men in a way essentially analogous to the way in which Belgium’s electoral system aggregates the votes of Flemings and walloons in Belgium’s federal elections or the votes of (supposedly) French and Dutch speakers in Brussels’s regional elections: women would be required to vote for women only and men for men only.3 the seats in Parliament would then be automatically distributed in proportion to the number of men and women in the electorate. if all the government needed were support of a majorit y in t he Pa rlia ment (w it hout a f ur t her inst itut iona l const ra int analogous to the parity rules in the Belgian and Brussels governments), an all-female government supported by the female majority could rule the country in impeccably “democratic” fashion. there a re of course good reasons to avoid ex tending to t he gender divide the electoral pathology of Belgium’s language community divide. it is important that those who want to govern a country should be electorally accountable to its whole population. But even w ith a strict analogue of Belgium’s current electoral system, and hence in the absence of a guaranteed proportional representation of men and women in the elected assemblies, it is within the power of the electoral (and even greater voting) majority of women to vote into office a corresponding majority of women. indeed, under the French or British system of single-member constituencies, and on the reasonable assumption that women form the majority of the voting public in every one of them, women have the power to make sure that only women get into the parliamentary assembly. however, the point to which i want to draw attention holds irrespective of whether women use their power in this way. it holds even if they elected into office only male candidates, those ambitious enough to fancy exercising the increasingly unattractive job of politician, but driven by their very ambition to advocate and implement policies favored by the female majority.] 3 For its federal elections, Belgium has a list-proportional system w ith prov incial constituencies. in Flemish prov inces, there are only Flemish candidates. a nd in walloon prov inces, there are only walloon candidates. For the regional elections in the officially bilingual region of Brussels capital, there are two electoral colleges, with only Dutch-speaking parties standing in one, and only French-speaking parties in the other. Brussels voters can choose in which of these two colleges they wish to vote and are assumed to do so according to their own native language — an increasingly problematic assumption in a region with hundreds of distinct native languages. 86 Philippe Van Parijs LEAP 3 (2015) 5. horMonal ineQuality the fourth inequality to which i want to draw attention is more delicate. a lthough part of what i am going to say w ill be said, as i hope you w ill notice, tongue-in-cheek, it is meant to draw attention to another important and difficult issue relating to the connection between gender injustice and gender inequality. as a point of departure, take the rather unsurprising fact i recently heard that over 95% of the consumers of prostitution services are men. why is this? this might have something to do with the fact that men’s annual incomes exceed women’s by a significant amount and that men therefore have more pocket money to spend on this expensive form of leisure. though pretty ignorant on these matters, i suspect that the cause is more basic and has something to do with the difference between male and female libido, their respective hormonal endowments, or some other physiological difference. no doubt this difference can be said to generate some of the most despicable cases of domination of women by men (whether clients or pimps). But does it not also reflect a gender-based inequality of needs, i.e., a form of handicap? Men’s greedier libido turns them into handicapped individuals, sometimes even super-handicapped à la Dominique Strauss-Kahn. whether the price to be paid for this handicap takes the form of expenditure on sexual services or of a fall into a reputational precipice, isn’t there here something to pity as well as to be indignant about? [Attributing the frequency of some form of misdemeanor to the fact that the perpetrators are men rather than women does not disculpate them: an explanation is not an excuse, let alone a justification. Most men, after all, are not prostitution clients, and however plausible the claim that the strong statistical correlation with maleness ref lects a genuine causal link, the role played by free will in the causal process is by no means irrelevant. This is arguably one key reason why we believe that prostitution services should not be subsidized in the way we believe psychiatric services and other forms of medical care should be. All of this hardly needs saying, I thought, but some of the reactions to the rather abrupt punch line of my speech suggest that stating the (fairly) obvious is not always a waste of time. There is, however, a deeper challenge here. Consider the fact that young men are massively over represented among perpetrators of violent crimes (partly against women, but to a large extent against other men), and hence (luckily) Four Puzzles on Gender Equality 87 LEAP 3 (2015) also among prison inmates. Here again, the hormonal story is not implausible.4 But the argument need not be fundamentally different if men and women had equally aggressive dispositions but men gave way to them more often simply because their genetic endowment makes them physically stronger. Under modern conditions, it is fortunately less easy to get away with violence than in the era of Genghis Khan. Has an advantage not thereby be turned into a disadvantage? Can it not be said that men are handicapped relative to women because of their greater propensity to end up in jail as a result of acts they would not have committed had they been women? Here again, it may be prudent to add that this is no excuse, nor justification, for their behavior. After all, there are men who have not spent one minute in prison any more than one cent on prostitution. However, think about the way we react to similar figures displaying strong correlations between social background and smoking, or between social background and criminality. People who grew up in poor families tend to smoke far more than people from rich families (which makes the tobacco tax one of the most regressive taxes ever implemented), and they are disproportionately in prision (in part, no doubt, but not only, because they tend to be sentenced more severely for the same crimes). Is it not plausible to regard this as an aspect of the injustice they suffer? They did not choose to be poor, and had they been rich rather than poor they would not (probabilistically speaking) be wasting their money on cigarettes or their time behind prison bars. This should not prevent us from taxing the smokers or punishing the offenders, but should it not temper our indignation – especially if we happen to enjoy a more privileged background? Indeed, should we not view such facts as one of the expressions of the injustice inflicted on the poor? In this light, let us return to those men who waste their money on prostitutes or misbehave in a way that gets them into trouble (whether incarceration or reputational precipice). They did not choose to be men any more than those born poor chose to be born poor, and had they been women rather than men, they would not (probabilistically speaking) have to bear these burdens. Is the analogy between the two cases not so strong that it would be inconsistent to regard the inequalities mentioned as an aspect of an injustice suffered by the poor, but not as an injustice suffered by men? (Note that the analog y holds irrespective of the validity of the hormonal diagnosis. If the difference between the behavior patterns of men and women has nothing to do with testosterone or any other physiological difference, but rather with the way in which boys 4 See Paula casal’s striking piece, which helped inspire the formulation of this fourth puzzle: “love not war. on the chemistry of good and evil,” in arguing about Justice, louvain-la- neuve: Presses universitaires de louvain, 2011, 145-156. Freely downloadable at www.academia. edu/2396206/arguing_about_Justice_essays_for_Philippe_van_Parijs_Pul_2011_free_PDF www.academia.edu/2396206/Arguing_about_Justice_Essays_for_Philippe_Van_Parijs_PUL_2011_free_PDF www.academia.edu/2396206/Arguing_about_Justice_Essays_for_Philippe_Van_Parijs_PUL_2011_free_PDF 88 Philippe Van Parijs LEAP 3 (2015) are socialized – say, being encouraged to play with guns rather than dolls –, the analogy would arguably be even closer). This brings us to my philosophical question. Why is it that my intuition – and presumably yours – is different in the two cases? Is it simply because of the contingent fact that these handicaps suffered by men can hardly be said to offset the many unjust inequalities that favor them, whereas in the case of the poor they are added to a whole series of other clearly unjust inequalities in the same direction? Or is there a deeper, less contingent difference between the two cases? Is the key difference, for example, that it is hardly controversial that a world without poverty would be a better world, whereas some doubt (perhaps wrongly) that a mankind without males would be a better mankind? If this is not the key difference, what is?] ePiloGue: a PhiloSoPher’S JoB As mentioned at the start, part of the job of a philosopher is to question assumptions, and one effective way of doing so is by formulating puzzles by asking, for example, (1) If society gives group B more money per unit of time while nature gives group A more units of time, can it always be said that there is an unjust inequality at the expense of group A? (2) If society gives group B more money and group A better education, can it always be said that there is an unjust inequality at the expense of group A? (3) If group B enjoys a majorit y among power holders and group A a majority among those who choose the power holders, can it always be said that there is an unjust inequality at the expense of group A? (4) If group B’s genetic endowment makes its members more likely to end up in prison, can this ever be counted as an injustice suffered by its members, none of whom chose not to be born a member of the less incarceration-prone group A? Are these questions outlandish, far-fetched, deprived of any relevance to the most pressing issues and most urgent struggles for the sake of greater justice between men and women? At first sight, several of them certainly are. Yet they are worth asking. For each of them is meant to invite further thinking on the ideal of equality of opportunity that underlies much of the struggle for greater gender justice. The equalization of opportunities requires that one should neutralize the impact on our life prospects of circumstances beyond our control – including our being born women or men –, while making us bear the consequences of the choices we make – including those made by virtue of preferences that may happen to differ markedly between women and men. Four Puzzles on Gender Equality 89 LEAP 3 (2015) Taking seriously the questions raised above and addressing the difficulties they reveal is essential to clarify, refine, and sharpen this ideal, and thereby to strengthen the struggles they inspire. Dismissing them, by contrast, deprives us of an opportunity to give a sounder basis to the struggle for greater justice along the gender dimension, as along any other. In particular, articulating the ideal in response to puzzling challenges is essential to put any particular struggle in a broader context: the concern for opportunities, the real freedom of those with least real freedom, irrespective of their gender, but among whom women are massively overrepresented. LEAP 3 (2016) Distributive Justice and Female Longevity1 PAUL A C ASA L ICREA & Pompeu Fabra University Abstract This paper discusses Philippe Van Parijs’ claim that men’s lack of female longevity constitutes an injustice, whether this is caused by asocial factors or by gendered lifestyles. This response argues that, like others, such as John Kekes and Shlomi Segall, Van Parijs underestimates the resources of egalitarian liberalism to avoid this implication. One explanation treats individuals as liable for gendered life-shortening behavior, for example, when they value either life-shortening lifestyles or the choice between lifestyles, and one cannot say society has not “done enough” for them. A second explanation claims a trait is not a relative advantage when it is systematically part of a package of traits that do not constitute a relative advantage. A third explanation claims a trait is not an advantage when its value to the trait bearer is conditional, and the relevant conditions are unlikely to be fulfilled. Keywords: R. M. Dworkin, hypothetical insurance, John Kekes, gender, natural and social inequality, T. M. Scanlon, Shlomi Segall INTRODUCTION In “Four Puzzles on Gender inequality” (2015), Philippe Van Parijs presents his first puzzle thus: “As long as most people would be willing to give up some income in order to live longer, women’s higher life expectancy reduces the inequality between men and women” (2015: 82). This first puzzle is probably the most familiar of the four Van Parijs addresses. For example, when John Kekes (1997) sets out to discredit egalitarian liberalism, he uses the idea of women having to compensate men for lacking female longevity as a reductio 1 I thank Aurora Pujol, José Luis Martí, and particularly Andrew Williams for helpful comments on an earlier draft. I also thank two ver y thorough anonymous referees. I also t h a n k Je s ú s Mor a , L au r a S á nc he z de l a Sier r a , a nd Ha n n a h Web er for t hei r e x c el lent editorial assistance. Distributive Justice and Female Longevity 91 LEAP 3 (2015) of t he ta rgeted v iew.2 rat her t ha n f inding it absurd to t reat women as relatively advantaged by their greater longevity, van Parijs cannot think of a way to avoid the conclusion. he envisions only two ways to challenge it. one is to cla im t hat g reater fema le longev it y is eit her (i) due to men’s lifestyle and, therefore, something men are liable for, or (ii) biologically- based and, thus, something justice does not require society to amend. he states that (i) is not available to those who hold that social norms shape gender-specific lifestyles, and (ii) is not an option for those who believe just institutions should also reduce inequalities derived from natural talents or disabilities (82). a final option he considers involves deny ing female longevity is a significant benefit, given the way those final years are spent. i shall follow this useful map to describe in more detail the territory it charts, and draw some routes he does not consider. like van Parijs, i shall not establish the facts, but focus on the normative implications of different factual assumptions. Kekes finds the idea of compensating men for their lower longev it y particularly ridiculous because he regards the variation as a product of biology rather than of unjust social practices (1997: 104). however, i agree with van Parijs that it is not plausible to regard greater female longevity as an entirely asocial phenomenon and then argue that only inequalities that are socially generated can be unjust (nagel 1997; Daniels 2007; Pogge 1989: secs. 15-16, 1995 and 2000). along with Kekes, and others such as Shlomi Segall (2010: 105-10), van Parijs gives the impression that liberal egalitarianism lacks the resources to deny plausibly that it is unjust that men lack female longevity. in contrast, i shall argue that there are plausible liberal egalitarian views that hold individuals l iable for t he ha r m f u l consequences of their gendered lifestyles, and that deny that individuals lacking a certain trait are owed compensation when they identif y w ith t hei r t ra it-dest roy i ng lifestyles or when they value having the choice between different lifestyles. Furthermore, even if we assume the variation in longevity between men and women depends entirely on asocial factors, plausible liberal egalitarian responses are still available. one such response claims a trait is not a relative advantage when it is systematically part of a package of traits that do not constitute a relative advantage. a final option, which van Parijs also considers, is to deny a trait has value to the trait bearer if its value is conditional, and the relevant conditions are unlikely to be fulfilled. i shall proceed to examine the options just noted, referring both to mainstream normative theories and to scientific explanations. My main hope 2 For convenience, like van Parijs, i shall compare men and women; and like Kekes, i shall refer to “compensations.” the relevant measure, however, is not how far individuals or groups are from one another but how far they are from what they would have in a just society. 92 Paula Casal LEAP 3 (2015) is to show the complexity of van Parijs’ first puzzle. Some deem compensating men for their lesser longevity obviously absurd whilst others find it just as obv ious that liberal equalit y rightly mandates such compensations. in contrast, i think that both reactions are mistaken, and that the puzzle is not only very difficult but also an interesting litmus test to sort important variants of plausible forms of egalitarian liberalism. i am also sure that if a random mutation resulted in women starting to die far ahead of men many of those who currently find van Parijs’ suggestion absurd would start listing lesser longevity as one of the disadvantages women suffer. But i shall leave the defense of his position to van Parijs, and focus on some plausible responses liberal egalitarians could give, and which he has so far neglected. 2. the Social hyPotheSiS: liFe-ShorteninG GenDereD Behaviour a lthough women live longer on average than men, there are remarkable differences in the variation among different societies. this suggests that social factors play some important role in explaining gender-based variations in longevity. For example, in 2013 women outlived men by twelve years in Belarus, but only by one year in San Marino, and men outlived women by four years in tonga (who 2015). in europe, women outlive men by eleven years in lit hua nia, whi le in more gender ega lita ria n societ ies li ke Sweden, netherlands, and the united Kingdom, the gender gap is just around three years (eurostat 2015). Further evidence of the importance of social factors refers to changes in the gender gap within one society across time. For ex a mple, a s gender equa l it y i ncrea ses i n eu rope, t he longev it y gap is shrinking (eurostat 2015). in china, the projection of current trends shows that as more people survive their 80th birthday, women become more prevalent in the last age group (Fig. 1). Fig 1. chinese life expectancy pyramids in 2000 and 2050. Source: world Population Prospects, 2004 revision (2005)3. 3 http://www.prb.org/Publications/articles/2006/chinasconcernoverPopulationagingandhealth.aspx Percentage Percentage Male MaleFemale Female http://www.prb.org/Publications/Articles/2006/ChinasConcernOverPopulationAgingandHealth.aspx Distributive Justice and Female Longevity 93 LEAP 3 (2015) now, longevity may depend on social factors without also depending on gender-specific lifestyles. For social factors could include, for example, a reform in the publicly-funded health service or the adoption of a certain tradition or sport w ith an unexpected differential impact on male and female life expectancy. improved hygiene and obstetric care, for example, reduced women’s death in childbirth, creating a longevity gap which was not so noticeable before. longevity varies from one society or one period to another for social, but not always gendered, reasons. let us assume, however, as van Parijs does, that if the causes are social, they involve gender-based variations in lifestyle (see also Segall 2010: 108). the causes generally listed involve different factors. Some are unhealthy habits such as some pleasurable forms of consumption like drinking alcohol, smoking, taking drugs, or eating without measure whatever one fancies. others involve risky activities such as speeding, drunk driving, dangerous sports, and the sort of behav ior displayed in internet v ideos w ith labels such as “extreme idiots.”4 a third factor involves occupational hazards, and a fourth, violence or a greater tendency to commit suicide or homicide, or to be killed or injured in fights (see fig. 2). White, Non-Hispanic Black, Non-Hispanic Hispanic Men Women Men Women Men Women Injuries 70.8 22.3 49.0 14.8 55.7 13.0 Homicide 6.4 2.6 102.2 11.3 28.0 4.0 Suicide* 24.6 5.0 14.5 2.4 12.8 2.9 Cancer 6.0 4.5 6.7 6.3 5.7 5.4 Heart Disease 5.0 3.0 13.8 7.4 4.6 2.0 HIV** — — — 5.7 — — Fig. 2: leading causes of death for men and women aged 20-29 in the uS in 2007, deaths per 100,000 (PrB 2010). Most feminists, and perhaps most liberal egalitarians, tend to hold social rather than biological explanations of gendered behavior, and so they may find the lifest yle explanation of longev it y plausible. this, however, does not commit them to the view that if a man’s behavior is gendered, he is not liable to bear the burdens arising from it. there are different explanations of why inferring a lack of liability is a non sequitur. i cannot rev iew them all but several are not hard to guess. First, denying liability for the bad consequences of gendered behavior would 4 See, for example, https://w w w.youtube.com/watch?v=Px a xbZeGtua https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=PxAxbZeGtUA 94 Paula Casal LEAP 3 (2015) have undesirable consequences as it would leave us w ithout important incentives to avoid behavior that is both undesirable and gendered. leaving consequences aside, one may argue that it is not fair that, while men can indulge in drinking and eating without gaining weight or being so strongly penalized by society, women must exercise self-restraint and then compensate men for not having exercised it. this is unfair because if a already had all the fun of a carpe diem lifestyle, B should be allowed to keep the benefits of the self-restraint exercised. otherwise it would be like making women who diet pay for the slimming treatment of those who overeat. Second, since male violence and risk-taking are already among the main causes of death for young women, one cou ld a rg ue t hat women have a lready pa id w it h a significant reduction in their own longevity and shared in the costs of male behavior. regarding occupational hazards, some would argue that if both a and B want jobs, and jobs that involve (on-balance advantageous) combinations of benefits and drawbacks, it will be unfair to give a the job, and make B compensate a for the job ś drawbacks (including possible longevity losses). assuming it is not the dead but living people to whom compensation is or is not owed raises further problems. it would not make sense to compensate men who avoid all life-shortening behavior and are thus likely to live long. For then there will be nothing they have to be compensated for, and they will be unfairly enjoying both the extra years and the compensation for lacking them. But it would make even less sense to compensate individuals who, despite engaging in all the life-shortening gendered behavior, still escape the fate for which they are supposed to be compensated. we would be giving extra resources to people who remain alive despite their eating without self- restraint or their indulging in other imprudent activities. this seems just as implausible, if not more. it may seem more plausible if, instead of granting monetary compensations to the men who stay alive, we invested more on men’s health and spent less on pregnancy or cervical cancer, as Shlomi Segall at one point suggests to illustrate the case (2010 : 108). But if pecuniar y compensations are not justified, neither are these in-kind compensations. if there is nothing to compensate men for, they will be enjoying both the extra years and the compensation, and this would be unfair. (Both pregnancy and cervical cancer, moreover, come about because of sperm, which arguably makes it even more unfair). another possibility would be to force men to adopt female lifestyles. But men may resist this option. this could be because they prefer life-shortening lifestyles or because they value having the choice, the mere opportunity of engaging in activities with some risk of self-harm. adapting an example proposed by Scanlon to explain the value of choice, let us imagine that there is an area with extremely nasty nettles in bloom Distributive Justice and Female Longevity 95 LEAP 3 (2015) that cause a terrible rash (Scanlon 1998: 256).5 the authorities mark the area and warn people about the consequences of wandering through the flowering nettles. Scanlon argues that even if it is difficult to see any value in getting a nasty rash, there is generic value in being able to choose rather than be forced to do the right thing all the time. thus, having fenced off the area and issued all the warnings, we could say that society had done enough to protect individuals from the danger (see Scanlon 1998: 249-294; voorhoeve 2008; williams 2006). Scanlon then asks us to imagine there is a curious woman who really wants to see what is happening in the fenced area, and so decides to go in to check it out (Scanlon 1998: 257). he denies she will then have a claim on society for help or compensation, since she had an adequate opportunity to avoid the harm. there could be exceptions to this conclusion that Scanlon would accept. For example, if we can stop her rash by showering her with the public park’s watering hose, it would be such an easy rescue that she could have a complaint if she were not showered. in other cases, perhaps during a drought, she could not make such demands. another plausible exception would be that of individuals or groups who are already victims of injustice or live below a minimum threshold and take some risks to escape their dire condition. Since such exceptions do not apply to the case of men indulging in unhealthy habits, let us add to the picture some gender stereot y pes and claim that the woman was a victim of female curiosity or love for f lowers, and so was engaging in self-harming gendered behavior. or suppose a man wants to enter the fenced area to show off how tough he is or because of a gendered sensat ion-seek i ng desi re, or a gendered aut hor it y-def y i ng attitude. would this change anything? it is implausible to assume that the mere fact that such behavior can be associated with gender stereotypes makes a difference. it would make a difference if the signs were unclear or if the individuals were children. But adults who chose to ignore the clear sig ns do not have a leg it imate compla int if t hey come out w it h a rash, regardless of whether theirs was a case of typically male, female, sport-fan, or ideological foolishness. in t he ca se of l i fe-shor ten i ng gendered behav ior, t he ca se aga i nst compensation is even stronger that in the example of the nettles because incursion into the fenced area is a one-off event rather than recurrent behavior, like eating and drinking excessively, driving recklessly, picking fights, and general carelessness. if the behavior that causes a man to have 5 i have modified Scanlon’s original example because it involved hazardous waste, which may suggest corporate responsibilit y for extremely nast y and premature deaths in deprived areas. 96 Paula Casal LEAP 3 (2015) a shorter life span is traceable to choices that men pursue repeatedly, and even identify with, the case for compensation is even less plausible. Given that we cannot plausible claim society has not done enough for men, or compare the case to that of an easy rescue, liberal egalitarians who believe in accommodating t he va lue of choice would not compensate men for undesirable, gendered behavior. needless to say, for desert theorists, making the prudent, non-violent, law-abiding poor reward the imprudent, violent, careless rich is exactly the opposite of justice (see, for example, arneson 2007). But let us now examine what follows if sex variations in longevity do not depend on behavior but respond to some other explanations scientists have proposed, and which i sum up below. 3. the aSocial hyPotheSiS: the evolutionary eXPlanationS on average, women live longer than men. it would be puzzling for scientists if they did not, as this is normal for females in other species. a traditional explanation in the case of humans is that estrogen protects women from cardiovascular disease. another explanation is that having only one copy of the X chromosome makes males more vulnerable to harmful recessive mutations (Pan 2012).6 the latter explanation could also account for the alleged female tendency to form a tighter cluster near the mean while more males are outliers, occupying more extreme (desirable and undesirable) positions (cronin 2008). Sexual differences in longevity, however, are greater in species with a history of polygyny (i.e., of males mating with several females) and tend to be g reater t he la rger t he si ze of t he ha rems. thus, in ver y polyg y nous mammals, like elephant seals, males are almost twice as large as females and females almost twice as long-lived as males.7 in contrast, in less polygynous species, sex differences in either size or longevity may be much smaller. the massive bowhead whales can sur v ive t wo centuries, whi le small insects may survive only two weeks because, across species, a large size correlates with longevity. By contrast, between the sexes of the same species, the reverse obtains: if the females of a species are much smaller than the males of the same species, they tend to live much longer. 6 a recent ly proposed ex pla nat ion is t hat t he qua l it y-screen i ng process of ou r mitochondrial genes only happens through females, and so mitochondrial mutations may be weeded out when t hey a re ha rmf u l to fema les but not when t hey a re ha rmf u l to ma les (camus 2012). 7 Male southern elephant seals weigh 11,000 pounds and live around 15 years, whilst female southern elephant seals weigh 2,000 pounds and live around 24 years. See, for example, http://www.marinebio.net/marinescience/05nekton/esbody.htm. http://www.marinebio.net/marinescience/05nekton/esbody.htm Distributive Justice and Female Longevity 97 LEAP 3 (2015) in species with a polygynous history, when compared to females, males are: (i) larger and better armed or ornamented; (ii) more aggressive; (iii) more drawn to competitive interaction and aggressive play; (iv) more likely to engage in escalating violence, leading to injury or death; (v) more eager to mate; (vi) less discriminating about mates; (vii) more prone to high-risk behav ior, particularly when pursuing females (Dar w in 1872; thornhill and Palmer 2000 : 37); (v iii) more likely to die prematurely in accidents, combat, or f rom d isea se (Da ly a nd w i lson 1983); (i x) less long-l ived through physiological malfunction (hamilton 1966); and (x) conceived and born in larger numbers, roughly balancing their dying prematurely in larger numbers from violence, disease, malfunction, or imprudence (alexander et al. 1979). these characteristics could cause men to lack some of the self- repair mechanisms that women have because there would not be much point in nature investing in self-repair systems for those likely to die of other causes any way (Diamond 1993: 110). other explanations refer to the social usefulness of females for youngsters of eit her sex. in polyg y nous species, ma les a re more ex pendable t ha n females not only because fewer males are needed for reproduction, but because offspring benefit more from females. one example is the grandmother effect, observable in matriarchal societies like those of orcas, where older females guide and protect the young, surviving menopause and outliving males by several decades (Brault and caswell 1993). think too about how male lions wait for the females to bring home the bacon, and having killed all the cubs they did not sire, leave only scraps for their own offspring to eat. youngsters sometimes do so much better without their large, sexually aggressive male parent around that the best such males can do for their offspring is what some actually do: go away and die to avoid competing with their own kin. longevity is known to correlate not only with size in the two ways explained above but also with cultural transmission. elephants, great apes, and other highly intelligent, self-aware, cultural creatures, like orcas, lactate for many years. they do so not because they need the milk, but because they need to intersperse the pregnancies to allow mothers enough time to provide their offspring with an education. lactation, however, is also connected to the high incidence of polygyny in mammals, since such devoted mothers are very easy to exploit: they will not abandon the offspring in which they have invested so greatly, even if they are abandoned or exploited themselves. the large investment per infant typical of these species is adaptive because its members are long-lived, so education and cultural transmission tends to pay off. in the case of humans, the large human brain required for extensive learning involves large additional costs for child-bearing women, and this 98 Paula Casal LEAP 3 (2015) may have also resulted in their greater longevity: a very large brain for babies, combined with a pelvis not initially designed for bipedal walking, makes human births exceptionally dangerous even for young and healthy mothers. Given these facts, if women died younger and were fertile until they were about to die, both mothers and their infants would die in even larger numbers. Female longevity might then be a consequence of how much more costly it is to have offspring for female humans compared to other female primates (Diamond 1993: 117). and since mothers pass their genes to their sons, men could have then benefited from an increase in their longevity (relative to that of all other apes) without having to pay the costs. appealing to these considerations, some may respond to van Parijs in at least four ways. First, one may respond by arguing that the main beneficiaries of female longevity are actually men. Female longevity is not a trait that is explained by its benefits for females but by its benefits to offspring of both sexes. Moreover, possessing this trait comes at a high price for women since it is connected to the extraordinary danger and difficulty involved in giving birth, as well as to smaller size in females, and inequality and reproductive exploitation. without pay ing these costs, men also benefit from female longevity since they benefit when they are young males, they benefit from their own offspring being safe, and it is likely that they have also benefited with increases in their own longevity. on this view, then, one could argue that is not males, but rather females that ought to be compensated for the costs of securing collective longevity. a second reply would involve arguing that the inequality in longevity is not unjust because its removal would make humans worse off. if so, rawlsians, for example, would deny such beneficial inequalities are unjust. if these explanations are correct, van Parijs’ assumption that, if longevity has a biological explanation, then men’s lack of female longevity is unjust, would be a non sequitur. a third answer to van Parijs would be to argue that if males die younger because of their propensity to attack others in order to monopolize more females, while females live longer because of their useful caring services, in a way we are back to the explanation of longevity in terms of “gendered” lifestyles discussed earlier. van Parijs, however, may argue that evidence of gendered lifestyles having evolutionary roots only reduces men’s liability. But this is too rushed. First, everything has evolutionary roots, and we do not generally deny all liability. Second, for some theories of liability, the fact that humans have an evolutionary past is taken for granted and makes no difference at all. third, we are sufficiently monogamous and sufficiently unlike seals, orcas, and lions that although some may be tempted to behave like such animals, we are not hardwired to do so, and most of us do not. Distributive Justice and Female Longevity 99 LEAP 3 (2015) a fourth and final answer to van Parijs is to deny compensation on the ground that a trait cannot be considered an advantage when it is inextricably linked to other traits that cannot, on the whole, be considered an advantage, which is precisely what scientists are telling us with these explanations. ronald Dworkin and other advocates of equality of resources (Dworkin 2000), for example, would deny that individuals have any claim simultaneously to enjoy the advantages of a condition and the advantages of lacking the condition. take a case (suggested to me by andrew williams) involving a basketball player whose exceptional success depends on unusual height that is also correlated with premature death and terrible backaches. Dworkin would deny another shorter player is relatively disadvantaged in a compensation- supporting sense when he prefers only the taller player’s success, and does not regret lacking the package of traits on which it depends. on this view, men have no legitimate complaint regarding female longevity because, as the biological explanations suggest, giving birth and living a few more years are tightly linked and part of the same package, like the height and the backache, the suffering and the medals. and people are not entitled to have their cake and eat it too, enjoy an able body and yet insist in competing in the Paralympics, or be compensated for not being able to do so. there are, moreover, further arguments against compensating men inspired by Dworkin’s work on equality. as many readers probably know, for Dworkin a fair distribution of external resources is one which could have emerged from a hypothetical auction where individuals enjoy equal bidding power (2002: 67). when the process is complete nobody envies the bundle of resources others have ended up with, since they could have also bid for those resources themselves. against this background of equality of resources, equally situated individuals then purchase insurance against what they by their own lights consider a relative misfortune (clayton 2000; williams 2002, 2004). now, since men do not normally regard being male as such a misfortune, they are not entitled to compensation for lacking female longevity, or female hormones, or female breasts. By contrast, some transgender persons who very much want to have female bodies, and even give birth and breastfeed, w ith or w ithout the extra longev it y, but have a male anatomy, should be compensated. Dworkin’s view supports assisting these individuals with their sex-reassignment needs through a publicly-funded health ser v ice because people would have insured against being born with a body which does not match their self-identified sex when others possess such a body. Some may worry that this Dworkinian criterion for justifying or denying compensations depending on whether individuals identify with their condition may not always favor feminist demands. in response to this worry, one may 100 Paula Casal LEAP 3 (2015) a rg ue t hat t he D work i n ia n cr iter ion ca n not be used aga i nst fem i n ist demands because what women want (equal pay, respect, political representation, and so on) has nothing to do with being male or female. Few expressions in the history of thought are as unfortunate as the Freudian and lacanian “penis env y,” when what women want and demand does not depend on maleness or anatomy. thus, if men do not suffer from the reverse condition (say “womb env y”) but are perfectly happy to be men, and identif y with being men and do not consider being male a misfortune, they have no claim to compensation because in their own opinion they are not the victims of bad luck. they would have insured against illness or disability but not against being male. the same will apply to a religious believer who ends up not only with a lower life expectancy but lower welfare throughout his life because of the constant fasting that his religion demands. if this person identifies with his faith and does not regard it as a craving or disability, he does not have a complaint. he cannot both pity the atheist’s lack of faith and think of his own faith as a blessing whilst still plausibly claim to suffer from relatively bad luck. Similarly, there is no injustice if this believer dies younger purely as a result of a faith he welcomes and the corresponding religious activity he willingly pursues (Dworkin 2002: 119, 138; williams 2002: 378). Dworkin’s account, thus, is an example of a view that does not claim that justice concerns exclusively that which has a social origin, and still denies that men’s lack of female longevity constitutes an injustice. van Parijs may want to reject Dworkin’s account and all forms of egalitarian liberalism that conclude men’s lack of female longevity is not unjust, and he may be able to offer good reasons for doing so. My main point, however, is that his road map is not exhaustive: there are more exit routes on offer than he allows. in fact, van Parijs even omits to mention his own proposal regarding how to evaluate variations in internal assets, namely undominated diversity, according to which targeted transfers and other measures must make sure that no person’s lifetime internal endowments are regarded by all as inferior to that of someone else (van Parijs 1997, ch. 3). on this view, men are owed no compensation because there is no agreement on their endowment being inferior – there may even be a consensus on the denial of this claim. So it seems that not only Scanlonians and Dworkinians but even van Parijsians may deny it is unjust that men lack female longevity. regarding rawls, his theory of justice has been widely interpreted as denying that it is unjust that men lack female longevity (Barclay 1999; Segall 2010, 99ff and clayton 2001). the first statement of his view was understood as claiming that justice requires equalizing individuals’ natural primary Distributive Justice and Female Longevity 101 LEAP 3 (2015) goods when a deficit in those goods resulted in an unequal access to social primary goods, namely income, wealth, the basic liberties, and the social bases of self-respect. Since men are not disadvantaged in their access to social primary goods, however, there is no injustice that needs to be corrected. rawls’ later Justice as Fairness. A Restatement (2001), however, contains a section on Sen’s capability approach (rawls 2001: 168-176), which suggests that the widely held interpretation may not be the only position a rawlsian may take in this debate. instead, some rawlsians may argue that longevity is a capability and that enjoying greater capabilities matters even if it does not alter an individual’s access to primary goods. So rawlsians may accept that differences in longevity can have independent relevance for justice. Since most people disregard this aspect of rawls’ restatement of his theory, we can safely conclude that most liberal egalitarians deny that men’s lack of female longevity is unjust. let us now turn to the final question van Parijs raises which concerns the value rather than origins of greater female longevity. 4. iS FeMale lonGevity a SiGniFicant BeneFit? van Parijs begins by granting that hav ing some extra years may not be significantly valuable, and that concession seem plausible. women’s extra years may come when they are too old, weak, disabled, or dependent to achieve anything very valuable with the extra time. they may spend most of the time asleep, ill, in and out of hospital, and with their mind and energy focused on coping with the problems of female old-age: frequent falls and fractures, arthritis, incontinence, deafness (cutting people off socially, which affects women more), stress, insomnia, depression, and dementia, which claim more female than male victims. longevity, then, is only conditionally valuable, and the last few years of one’s life are the ones more likely to detract from the total value of one’s overall existence. as van Parijs notes, it would be great to have some extra years if they could be “squeezed in at age 30 or 40” (2015: 82) rather than prolonging the worst bit of one’s life. i agree again. van Parijs, however, goes on to add: “But this is a confusion. what hides behind the gap between the average lengths of women’s and men’s lives is a greater probability for a woman to reach and enjoy her forties, her fifties, her sixties, etc., not only her nineties” (82). van Parijs does not indicate the extent to which men’s prospects of reaching middle age are smaller than women’s, and if that gap is not itself significant, he has not made any progress in showing that women enjoy a significant benefit here. Moreover, van Parijs does not cite any data supporting his claim, and population pyramids like those indicated earlier (Fig. 1) suggest that the number of males and females at ages 30 and 40 remain largely the 102 Paula Casal LEAP 3 (2015) same until we reach the very last, and least desirable, stage of life. thus, even if his qualification is relevant, the differences in probabilities may not be sufficiently large as to constitute a significant advantage. there are also likely to be regional variations, and so depending on your birthplace you may be a victim of female infanticide or die in childhood from “the pattern of neglect” (the systematic dismissal of a daughter’s nutritional or medical needs), you may be killed by your rapist, stoned by religious fanatics, burned for witchcraft, killed for dowry, or die in childbirth or from domestic violence. as different factors combine, over a hundred million women are missing (Sen 1990). of course, things are different in developed societies. But there, if you are prudent and look after yourself, the chances of dy ing young are so small for both women and men that some small difference in what is already a remote chance may not be very significant. in addition, as van Parijs notes, women are not only poorer but also need to stretch their scarcer resources over more years, which makes them in one respect poorer still. having said this, however, he adds that there is an income difference (and he mentions income differences of 5%, 1% and 0.01%) that individuals would accept in exchange for increased longevity. three observations are needed here. First, women do not only have to stretch the fewer resources they have over a few more (equally costly) years. in fact, it is in those final years that the costs of surviving often skyrocket. Second, women are not only poorer but much poorer than men and much worse paid. and so that the reader is not left with the wrong impression, it is worth noting that income differences are much larger than those van Parijs suggests in his thought experiment. in Spain, for instance, the gender income difference is 33.7% (eurostat 2015b), so that if a man makes 1,000€€ a month, the woman would only make 666€, receiving just 2€€ for every 3€€ a man secures. third, just as we cannot imagine that the extra years are additional years in our 30’s or 40’s, we cannot imagine these are additional years of a typical male life, with all the drinking or speeding included. For the alleged advantage consists mainly in the final years of a female life, with its poverty, illness, stress, and subordination to men. it is unlikely, then, that men would prefer these female ‘advantages’, and if they are tempted to do so they should consider van Parijs’ final, and most original, observation regarding longevity. he notes that besides living longer, women are also on average two or three years younger than their male partner. This means that far more women than men are likely to still be around when their ageing partner is becoming frail and dependent. As long as much of the elderly care required in these circumstances is performed Distributive Justice and Female Longevity 103 LEAP 3 (2015) within the household, the necessary consequence is a very significant inequality in the amount of domestic elderly care work performed by the two genders, which — as lives get longer and children fewer — may approximate or even exceed the size of the inequality in the respective amounts of domestic child care. Note that this holds even under the unrealistic assumption that both the will and capacity to care for their partner are the same for men and women. In this light, men’s lower life expectancy might be interpreted as a trick to extract more care work out of women (2015: 82). what this means is that women’s somewhat longer lives are not really theirs: whatever their vocation, they are effectively conscripted as nurses, cooks, and cleaners. not long after they finish cleaning and feeding their children, they may end up stuck with the far less pleasant chore of cleaning a nd feeding old men, of ten f irst t heir ow n fat her a nd t hen t heir elderly spouse. hav ing looked after their partner day and night, they then see them die, and go on to age and die alone themselves. van Parijs sees no way out of this. Since deterring men from marr y ing younger women seems difficult, if not impossible, and getting them to outsource their elderly care seems to him not only costly but undesirable, he thinks we face here a blind alley. if we accept this pessimistic conclusion, it becomes easier to deny men are missing out on any significant benefit. But perhaps we should explore ways to change women’s situation in those final years. let us consider the age gap first. the age between spouses correlates with higher divorce rates (Francis-tan and Mialon 2015), and so we may have additional reasons to nudge people into reconsidering divorcing to marry somebody much younger. van Parijs himself once proposed a tax on the age difference between partners to reduce the chances of the wife leaving a less senior job than her husband’s in order to care for their children (van Parijs 2001). Such a tax could serve other functions too, and it could even be progressive: the rate could be adjusted so an elderly millionaire starting his fourth marriage to a barely adult beauty queen would pay a higher tax than a less wealthy man whose marriage involves a smaller age gap. and since the gap correlates with income inequality and other aspects of the social structure (casterline 1986), it may also spontaneously shrink as society becomes more just. regarding elderly care, i favor more outsourcing. Some countries out- source care by combining the elderly individual’s savings with state aid, for exa mple, by adva ncing f unds t hat t he state ca n t hen recover once t he deceased’s home is sold. Most developed countries outsource childcare despite the fact that it is important for the development of the child (but often not for the elderly) to be cared for by a specific person, and despite 104 Paula Casal LEAP 3 (2015) the fact that it is far more delightful for a person to wash and feed her own child than an old man. one may prefer to see and talk to one’s spouse or female relative rather than a paid carer, but then one can always invite them to visit rather than force them to be there performing all sorts of tasks, such as treating bedsores, that not everybody is cut out for. caring for an elderly person often requires the ability not to feel faint or nauseous when confronted with certain sights and smells, the ability not to take criticisms personally, and the strength not to drop a man’s body when moving it. if a young male professional is much better than an aging wife at all of this, it is not desirable to rely on her performing such tasks. Moreover, it is unfair that after a lifetime of being paid so much more, men cou ld go on to ex pec t women to c a re for t hem g rat is. i n stead, ever y body should feel under a duty to save to avoid becoming, in effect, slave-drivers in their old age. i certainly do not see how one could have a right to turn a rare and modest advantage for women into yet more unpaid and unchosen female labor. as Dworkin would say, we may disagree about to what extent we should compensate people for a certain disability, but we should agree that a just society will not turn individuals’ natural advantages into a liability by engaging in some sort of slavery for either the talented or the long-lived. concluSion van Parijs claims that lacking female longevity is an injustice against men, if it is caused by a gendered lifestyle. i have argued that on some plausible views, such as thomas Scanlon’s, at least under some circumstances in which society can be said to have "done enough" for some individuals, they can be expected to bear the consequences of their life-shortening behavior, whether or not it is influenced by gender stereotypes. van Parijs also argues that if men’s lack of female longevity is due to asocial factors, then it is an injustice against men. i have argued that on some plausible views, such as ronald Dworkin’s, it is not an injustice if, as scientists suggest, having female longevity is inextricably linked to being female, and men identify with their condition and do not consider it bad brute luck. Finally, van Parijs notes various reasons to deny female longevity is a significant benefit. one of them concerns the informal conscription of unpaid female labor for elderly care. i have argued such conscription should end. until it does, however, i agree with van Parijs that it greatly diminishes the value of what was already at most a very modest benefit. Distributive Justice and Female Longevity 105 LEAP 3 (2015) BiBlioGraPhy alexander, r. et al., 1979: “Sexual Dimorphism and Breeding Systems of Pinnipeds, ung ulates, Primates and humans,” Evolutionary Biolog y and Human Social Behaviour, ed. n. chagnon and w. irons. north Scituate: Duxbury. arneson, r., 2007: “Desert and equality”, Egalitarianism. New Essays on the Nature and Value of Equality, ed. n. holtug and K. lippert-rasmussen. oxford: oxford university Press. Barclay, l., 1999: “the answer to Kekes’ Question,” Ethics 110: 84-92. Brault S. & h. caswell, 1993: “Pod-specific Demography of Killer whales,” Ecology 74: 1444-54. camus, M. F., D. J. clancy and D. K. Dowling, 2012: “Mitochondria l, Materna l inheritance and Male aging,” Current Biology 22: 1717-21. casterline, J., l. williams and P. McDonald, 1986: “the age Difference between Spouses,” Population Studies 40: 353. clayton, M., 2000: “the resources of liberal equality,” Imprints 5: 63-84. — 2001: “rawls and natural aristocracy,” Croatian Journal of Philosophy 1: 239-259. cronin, h., 2008: “More Dumbbells but More nobels,” Edge http://edge.org/annual-question/2008/response/10670 Daniels, n., 2007: Just Health, cambridge: cambridge university Press. Darwin, c., 1872: The Origin of the Species, london: Penguin. Daly, M. and M. wilson, 1983: Sex, Evolution and Behaviour, north Scituate: Duxbury. Dworkin, r., 2000: Sovereign Virtue, cambridge Ma: harvard university Press. 2002: “Sovereign virtue revisited,” Ethics 113:106-143. eurostat, 2015a: Mortality and life expectancy Statistics, http://ec.europa.eu/eurostat/ statistics-explained/index.php/Mortality_and_life_expectancy_statistics. eurostat, 2015b: Gender Pay Gap Statistics http://ec.europa.eu/eurostat/statistics- explained/index.php/Gender_pay_gap_statistics. Francis-tan, a. and h. Mialon, 2015: “a Diamond is Forever and other Fairy tales,” Economic Inquiry 53:1919-30. hamilton, w. “the Moulding of Senescence by natural Selection,” Journal of Theoretical Biology 12: 12-45. Kekes, J., 1997: Against Liberalism, ithaca: cornell university Press. nagel, t., 1997: “Justice and nature,” Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 17: 303-321. Pan Z, c. c., 2012: “Gender and the regulation of longevity,” Autoimmun Review 11: a393-403. Population reference Bureau 2010: young uS adults vulnerable to injuries and violence, http://w w w.prb.org/Publications/articles/2010/usyoungadultinjury aspx (12.12.2015). Pog ge, t., 1995 : “t h ree P roblems w it h cont racta r ia n-consequent ia l ist way s of assessing Social institutions,” Social Philosophy and Policy 12: 241–266 and in the Just Society, ed. e. F. Paul et al. cambridge: cambridge university Press [1995]: 247-250. — 20 0 0 : “Ju st ic e for Pe ople w it h Di s a bi l it ie s — t he S em i-c on se quent ia l i st approach,” Americans with Disabilities: Exploring Implications of the Law for Individuals and Institutions, ed. l. Francis, and a. Silvers. new york: routledge: 34–53. http://edge.org/annual-question/2008/response/10670 http://ec.europa.eu/eurostat/statistics-explained/index.php/Mortality_and_life_expectancy_statistics http://ec.europa.eu/eurostat/statistics-explained/index.php/Mortality_and_life_expectancy_statistics http://ec.europa.eu/eurostat/statistics-explained/index.php/Gender_pay_gap_statistics http://ec.europa.eu/eurostat/statistics-explained/index.php/Gender_pay_gap_statistics http://www.prb.org/Publications/Articles/2010/usyoungadultinjury.aspx http://www.prb.org/Publications/Articles/2010/usyoungadultinjury.aspx 106 Paula Casal LEAP 3 (2015) Scanlon, t., 1998: What We Owe to Each Other, cambridge Ma: harvard university Press. Segall, S.: 2015: Health, Luck and Justice, nJ: Princeton university Press. Sen, a., 1990: “More than one hundred women are Missing,” New York Review of Books, December 20. thornhill, r. and c. Palmer, 2000: A Natural History of Rape, cambridge Mass: Mit Press. van Parijs, P., 1997: Real Freedom for All, oxford: oxford university Press. — 2001: “real Freedom, the Market and the Family,” Analyse und Kritik 23:106-31. — 2015: “Four Puzzles on Gender inequality,” Law, Ethics and Philosophy 3. voorhoeve, a., 2008: “Scanlon on Substantive responsibility,” Journal of Political Philosophy 16:184-200. w ho, 2015: “life expectancy Data by countr y” http://apps.who.int/gho/data/ node.main.688?lang= en. williams, a., 2002: “equality for the ambitious,” Philosophical Quarterly 52: 377-389. — 2004: “equality, ambition and insurance,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary volume lX Xviii: 131-150. — 2006: “liberty, liability, and contractualism,” Egalitarianism ed. n. holtug and K. lippert-rasmussen. oxford: clarendon Press: 241-61. http://apps.who.int/gho/data/node.main.688?lang=en. http://apps.who.int/gho/data/node.main.688?lang=en. LEAP 3 (2015) Women’s Greater Educational Efforts as a Consequence of Inequality1 JESÚS MOR A Carlos III University of Madrid Abstract Contrary to Philippe Van Parijs’ assumptions, women’s greater educational achievements do not indicate that gender inequalities are smaller than assumed or that the efforts to achieve gender equality are overshooting. Being more qualified may be women’s best hope to escape poverty, unemployment, or single-parenting, as well as domestic and workplace exploitation. They a re t hus sy mptoms of gender inequalit y, not signs of its disappearance. In addition, they do not translate into greater access to income and wealth, positions of power and authority, social standing, or the chance to have several children, in the same way as they do in the case of men. Having to work so much harder to be rewarded so much less is, as Van Parijs at one point suspects, one of the forms of compound injustice that women face. Keywords: gender inequality, education, poverty, traditional gender roles, leadership positions INTRODUCTION In his second puzzle on gender equality, Philippe Van Parijs draws attention to the fact that, in some places, women are now more successful than men in securing degrees in higher education. This is not true everywhere, but I shall not dispute the trend in some countries and instead note that this already happened in the United States in the mid-1980s (Schwartz and Han 2014: 605). This paper disputes some of the lessons Van Parijs draws from these events. Van Parijs points out that higher education “has a significant impact (...) on empowerment as citizens and household members” (2015: 84), and so wonders whether “women’s emerging educational advantage should then 1 Special thanks to Paula Casal for her thoughtful suggestions, and multiple revisions and corrections. I also thank two anonymous referees 108 Jesús Mora LEAP 3 (2015) be regarded as offsetting (albeit in small part) men’s economic advantage” (84). My v iew is that it is true that education could potentially, in some possible world, offset men’s economic advantage. In ours, however, it does not. Income and employ ment gender differentials persist, as Van Parijs admits (84 ). A nd, in fact, such inequa lit ies compel women much more than men to achieve higher education. Women’s income and employment are much more dependent than men’s on qualifications and so, rather than indicating the end of inequality, women’s greater educational efforts appear to be just one of the many consequences of the pervasive inequality favoring men. Women’s greater dependence on extra educational effort is one of the many disadvantages women suffer. It is well known that women, whether they are secretaries or MPs, also have to make a greater effort than men to look good and dress well to avoid mockery. The fact that they try so much harder and sometimes succeed and do look better than men is not a sign of the end of injustice, but just one of the respects in which, as it is often said, women have to “try twice as hard, to be granted half as much.” And this makes men like myself wonder why they do persist in trying rather than give up in the face of such obstacles. 1. PROTECTION FROM POVERTY, SINGLE PARENTING AND DOMESTIC EXPLOITATION One of the most relevant disparities between men and women is what we may call “the poverty risk,” which refers to the chances of ending up liv ing in poverty. While in the past there were a variety of reasons why somebody could end up liv ing in povert y and the ranks of the poor were made up to a greater extent of people from a variet y of groups, povert y statistics and projections clearly show single (especially, never-married) mothers and their children as making up a large and growing2 percentage of people living below the poverty line in developed societies (see Bianchi 1999: 313; Targosz et al. 2003: 716). Women’s poverty risk is higher than men’s. In addition, poverty (income inequality) involves additional harms for women because of how deeply and irreversibly it can affect their children and because it correlates with increased risks of violence, harassment, and rape (W haley 2001: 550), as well as depression and other t y pes of mental disorder (Targosz 2003: 721). In the United States, the poverty risk increased for women relative to 2 In the words of Bianchi, “since the mid-1980s, the percentage of mother-child families in poverty has fluctuated, and the ratio of their poverty rate to that of married-couple families has been higher than in 1984.” She also notes that the relative poverty ratio between mother- ch i ld fa m i l ies a nd t wo-pa rent fa m i l ies, f luc t uated bet ween t he 1970s a nd t he 1980s. Never t heless, i n 198 4 mot her-ch i ld fa m i l ies' pover t y rat io w a s st i l l f ive t i mes t hat of t wo parent-families. Women’s Greater Educational Efforts as a Consequence of Inequality 109 LEAP 3 (2015) men in the period from 1950 to 1980 (Bianchi 1999: 310), precisely the period in which women applied themselves enough to catch up with men educationally. Despite such a great educational effort, however, women’s poverty rates still remained higher than men’s during the 1990s (Bianchi 1999). Recent data shows that the efforts of European women have also failed to liberate them from a higher poverty risk (see Van Lancker et al. 2015: 45-54). Given this explanation of women’s educational efforts, the prediction can only be that the trend will remain while sexism remains. A f unda menta l factor in ex pla ining women’s g reater pover t y risk is single-parenting, which is strongly connected to their education. Since the chances of finding a co-parent increase for women as they obtain diplomas and degrees, women with higher education reduce their poverty risk, for even if their educational efforts do not secure them permanent employment, they reduce their risk of single-parenting in poverty (Diprete and Buchmann 2006: 4). This offers an excellent deterrence against dropping out of school. Since men do not face the same risk, they do not have the same deterrent. Education diminishes women’s chances of being abandoned while pregnant and giving birth alone, and when the relationship continues, education remains one of the few protections (and perhaps the only protection) women can secure against the man then insisting that since he earns more, she should stay home, cook ing a nd ra ising t he chi ldren. This is a risk y opt ion for women, as with every pregnancy and every year into the marriage, women become less desirable both in the love and the labor markets, becoming less employable and attractive, not only because of the physical deterioration usually caused by motherhood, but because when children come with the package, women become less attractive both to other men and employers. Meanwhile, the man is promoted, takes senior positions and his stocks in both markets go up. With very poor exit options, the woman then tends to lose her voice and have to accept any deal she is dealt (Okin 1989: 137-8), including affairs or sexual activities she does not want, while living with the fear of being abandoned for another woman, or seeing this happening and becoming poor. Even renouncing motherhood and staying in paid employment is no guarantee against being expected to do most of the household chores after work (Hochschild 1989: 4). Men need not fear such exploitation, and do not need a degree to gain protection against such fate. 110 Jesús Mora LEAP 3 (2015) 2. PROTECTION FROM UNEMPLOYMENT AND EXPLOITATIVE WAGES Out side t he home, women a re a l so at g reater r i sk of u nemploy ment, underemploy ment, a nd unfa irly low wages a nd so need to have more qualifications for these purposes than men. In addition, in the 1980s and 1990s, the value of higher education has been grow ing faster for women than for men, not only regarding family returns but also the labor market (Diprete and Buchmann 2006). The gap in income bet ween college and high-school educated women increased enormously after the 1980s and remained always larger than that of men (13 and 20). This shows that women’s income is more dependent on higher education than men’s, for whom high school is often enough to provide adequate earnings. Similar trends appear in relation with access to employment. In the European Union, men’s rates of employ ment are superior to women’s in all levels, with the exception of tertiary education (Eurostat 2014). Only at that level are female rates able to achieve men’s possibilities to find a job. This provides an additional good reason for women to accomplish higher education: it constitutes an irreplaceable tool for them to achieve levels of employability similar to men’s. Becoming well qualified may also be the only way in which women can reduce (rather than eliminate) the rate of patronizing comments, demeaning and intimidating attitudes, and bullying. It seems, then, that educated women are penalized for being women less than less educated women are by all those who select them as either employees or as co-parents or partners. If so, even if female higher educational efforts do not make women wealthier, they are worth pursuing, for it is their protection, and perhaps the only one, against being short-changed at work and at home. Thus, female educational efforts, far from signaling the arrival of equality, are the knotted rope women use to escape the f lames of discrimination, domestic and workplace exploitation, and poverty. Van Parijs doubts there is any inequality “if society gives group B more money and group A better education” (2015: 88). This is misleading because societies do not reserve school places for women or otherwise offer women something it denies to men. To understand something complex we may need to take its simpler constitutive pieces apart and place them together again. But we may mislead rather than contribute to a better understanding if we greatly simplify something and just leave it at that. Women’s Greater Educational Efforts as a Consequence of Inequality 111 LEAP 3 (2015) 3. WOMEN’S LOWLY OCCUPATIONS Van Parijs admits that “not only do women get paid less than men, but they do so despite studying harder” (2015: 83). He then suggests, however, that t his may be because “women choose studies t hat lead to less lucrat ive careers” (83). If that is the case, he doubts whether their studying more and earning less could “still be viewed as amplif ying the injustice” (83). This speculative monistic explanation, again, stops the inquiry short. We need to ask why women pursue badly paid careers. There are several w idely discussed explanations of this phenomenon in the literature. One well-known explanation refers to social conditioning, stereotypes, and the systematic undermining, from a young age, of women’s confidence in their being able to per for m wel l i n cer ta i n occupat ions. A not her t heor y is t hat some occupations have low status and are badly paid because so many women work in them. We know, for example, that when women started to occupy the respectable positions of “clerk” and “administrator,” though the tasks remained the same, the position was demoted to that of “secretary” and the salary lowered (see Reskin and Hartmann 1986: 31). A third, extensively documented explanation of why women take such occupations is that other occupations are less compatible w ith women hav ing to do most of the housework and childcare. It seems that the three best known accounts do not imply that there is no injustice to worry about, but on the contrary direct us to the existence of ot her injust ices ex pla ining women’s actua l occupat ions. Va n Pa rijs would have to show that none of these explanations or any other alternatives referring to some background of unfairness is even partially correct. He would then have to prov ide a more conv incing account which does not u lt i mately refer to u n fa i r phenomena. It is u n l i kely, however, t hat a complete description would not involve elements from all three explanations. A starting point to analyze the traditional attribution of certain professional pathways to each of the sexes can be the common association between women and childrearing. Regardless of whether women decide or not to have children, most gender differences in employment and economic opportunities are parasitic on the sexual division of labor (Nagel 1997: 318). The assumption of the interconnection between womanhood and childrearing has had the widespread effect of denying women the ability to specialize. The interruption that the need to care for children necessarily generates makes women engage in a whole set of different tasks that involve lower cognitive, emotional, and aesthetic demands, without fully concentrating on any of them (Wilson 2004: 261, 272). Women’s work should not be too absorbing or dangerous, as it must always allow them to maintain their socially assumed maternity function (261, 272). Statistical ev idence shows that the presence of women in full 112 Jesús Mora LEAP 3 (2015) time work decreases enormously after the birth of the first child (Paull 2008: F18) and small children at home increase the likelihood that a woman is employed part time (Rosenfeld 1996: 209). The different expectations generally attributed to men’s a nd women’s work ma ke it necessa r y for t he latter to choose careers that allow little specialization and great ability to combine childrearing w ith work outside the household. As a consequence of the assumption that it is them who will have to take care of children, women accommodate their fertility to their labor force participation and vice versa (Brewster and Rindfuss 2000: 289-290). Consequently, women tend to be overrepresented in fields characterized by their functional or symbolic proximity to the traditional female domestic role, which cover health related careers (nursing), education, and humanities (Charles and Bradley 2002: 581, 590). These occupations provide more poorly paid jobs than those that require specialization, like Math, Science, and Engineering (MSE), which are characterized by the abundance of men (580). The traditional absence of women from MSE domains has also had effects on men’s and women’s self-perception of their skills. As a result of common stereot y pes, women w it h equa l scores in Mat h tests to men tend to rate their own mathematic skills much lower (Fine 2010: 48). Differences in rating of one’s own skills derive also in a different disposition to choose one or another professional path (48), so that, even though women are not necessarily less competent than men for MSE, they will be more reluctant to lead their careers in this direction. These stereotypes, though, do not only work against women’s fitting in particular domains, they also affect their position within different occupations. Both in traditionally male and female spaces, the disproportionate upholding of leadership spots by men hinders women’s upwa rds ca reer mobi lit y (Maume 1999: 1436, 1452). Managers often associate positions of power with the exercise of abilities like aggressiveness and ambition (1436, 1452), which are more commonly coupled with men. There are, however, other abilities, like social and psychological skills or ability to negotiate, which can be more useful in some managerial positions. In contrast, managers’ preconceptions about women tend to describe them as ‘gentle’ or lacking a mbit ion, wh ich creates problems for t hose who t r y to cl i mb up t he leadership ladder (Fine 2010: 52). The exercise of leadership is simply not seen as feminine, and when women manage to achieve positions of power they are commonly regarded as ‘competent but cold’ (52). Therefore, the situation of women in access to leadership is hindered by the interplay of first, the assumption of their lack of competence to exercise power and, second, t he negat ive percept ion of t hose women who at tempt to put leadership-associated abilities into practice. Women’s Greater Educational Efforts as a Consequence of Inequality 113 LEAP 3 (2015) The traditional exclusion of women both from MSE domains and leadership positions makes it harder for them to fit into those spaces still nowadays. As Radcliffe-Richards (1980: 113) points out, if a group is kept out of a particular area long enough, it is overwhelmingly likely that activities will develop in a way unsuited to the excluded group. MSE careers and the achievement of leadership (both in traditional male and female domains) are currently linked to capacities which are uncommonly associated with women. Men’s socially- designed biographies define workplace expectations and successful career patterns (MacKinnon 1987: 36). These long-lasting stereotypes are hard to break for women who, as we have seen, are at the same time regarded as incompetent for leadership and valued negatively when they try to exercise power in ‘masculine’ ways. Even if women were truly less attracted than men by MSE careers, that interest is clearly not impervious to outside influence (Fine 2010: 50), so that social stereotypes condition enormously women’s predisposition to enter such domains. In addition, the assumption of their lack of competence for leadership blocks women’s career mobility both in traditional male and female domains, in which men are commonly ‘kicked upstairs’ on the belief that they are too competent for low-rank posts (50) or that leading is a special talent men have. Randall Filer offered an alternative explanation of women’s lower income. He argued that women are badly paid because they care more about the non- pecu n ia r y a spects of a job a nd so systemat ica l ly pick bad ly pa id but otherwise attractive positions (see Filer 1985: 426-37). This did not sound prima facie implausible and points to a potential, exonerating explanation which probably helped those who already wanted to do nothing about existing inequalities. However, as J. S. Mill had already argued against Adam Smith, and as contemporary social scientists confirm, the worst paid jobs have a systematic tendency to be the worst jobs in all the non- pecuniary dimensions of job desirability as well. Moreover, women’s jobs in particular are worse t ha n men’s in t welve of t he four teen non-moneta r y measures used by Christopher Jencks and his co-authors (Jencks et al. 1988: 1352). Thus, “if it is true that women value non-monetary factors more than men, what this shows is that women fair worse than men even in what matters to women most” (Casal 2016: sec. V.b). Therefore, the fact that women are badly paid, far from being explicable by some exonerating factor, constitutes a clear case of compound injustice. So, the answer to Van Parijs’ question regarding whether the fact that women today are both more qualified and worse paid should be seen as “amplifying injustice” (2015: 83) is “yes,” because women are worse paid within the same occupat ion, a nd t he most li kely ex pla nat ions of t heir being in cer ta in occupations refers to further injustice. 114 Jesús Mora LEAP 3 (2015) It is also important to note that having an education which those in the opposite sex lack has ver y different consequences for men and women, regarding non-pecuniary or promotional aspects of their lives. Men with very successful careers in the hard sciences often have several children, while successful female scientists often have no families at all, as they have to compete with men who have housewives that do everything for them whilst lacking one of their ow n. So a group of well qualified women are childless or even entirely alone. For another group, their qualifications have just brought them additional sadness and frustration in realizing that the price of having children was having to leave their PhD on the shelf and put on their cleaning gloves, while their less qualified husbands pursue their careers. A third group of women lives with extraordinarily high levels of stress as breadwinners who still make sure their children keep medical and social appointments, do their homework, have all they need for school, and either do all the housework or have to chase the man so that things get done to what they consider an acceptable level. For, while getting married does not affect male careers negatively – rather the opposite – (see Wolfinger et al. 2008: 394), the weight of housework forces women either to delay their decision to form a family or to forsake it if they want to succeed in the professional world (390-1, 398-402). Having an education, thus, does not bring women the benefits it brings men. CONCLUSION Women’s educational achievements do not show that the efforts to achieve gender equality are overshooting. Being more qualified may be women’s best (or sometimes only) hope to escape poverty, unemployment, or single- parenting, as well as domestic and workplace exploitation. It is thus a symptom of gender inequality, not a sign of its disappearance. In addition, it does not translate, in the same way as it does with men, into greater access to income and wealth, positions of power and authority, social standing, or the chance to have several children. Having to work so much harder to be rewarded so much less is, as Van Parijs at one point suspects, one of the forms of compound injustice that women face. Women’s Greater Educational Efforts as a Consequence of Inequality 115 LEAP 3 (2015) BIBLIOGRAPHY Hochschild, A., 1989: The Second Shift, New York: Penguin Books. Bianchi, S., 1999: “Feminization and Juvenilization of Poverty: Trends, Relative Risks, Causes and Consequences,” Annual Review of Sociology 25: 307-33. Brewster, K. and Rindfuss, R., 2000: “Fertility and Women’s Employment in Industrialised Nations,” Annual Review of Sociology 26: 271-96. Casal, P., 2016: “Mill, Rawls and Cohen on Incentives and Occupational Freedom,” Utilitas: forthcoming sec. V. Charles, M. and Bradley, K., 2002: “Equal but Separate? A Cross-National Study of Sex Segregation in Higher Education,” American Sociological Review 67: 573-99. Diprete, T. and Buchmann, C., 2006: “Gender-Specific Trends in the Value of Education and the Emerging Gender Gap in College Completion,” Demography 43: 1-24.Eurostat, http://appsso.eurostat.ec.europa.eu/nui/show.do?dataset=lfsa_egaed&lang=en Filer, R., 1985: “Male-Female Wage Differences: the Importance of Compensatory Differentials,” Industrial and Labour Relations Review 38: 426-37. Fine, C., 2010: Delusions of Gender, London: Icon Books. Jencks, C. et al., 1988: “What is a Good Job? A New Measure of Labor-Market Success,” American Journal of Sociology 93: 1322-57. MacKinnon, C., 1987: Feminism Unmodified: Discourses on Life and Law, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Maume, D., 1999 : “Occupationa l Segregation and t he Career Mobilit y of W hite Men and Women,” Social Forces 77: 1433-59. Nagel, T., 1997: “Justice and Nature,” Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 17: 303-21. Okin, S., 1989: Justice, Gender and the Family, New York: Basic Books. Paull, G., 2008: “Children and Women’s Hours of Work,” The Economic Journal 118: F8-F27. Radcliffe-Richards, J., 1980: The Skeptical Feminist: A Philosophical Enquiry, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul. Reskin, B. and Hartmann, H., 1986: Women’s Work, Men’s Work: Sex Segregation on the Job, Washington: National Academy Press. Rosenfeld, RA, 1996: “Women’s Work Histories,” Population and Development Review 22: 199-222. Scwartz, R. and Han, H., 2014: “The Reversal of the Gender Gap in Education and Trends in Marital Dissolution,” American Sociological Review 79: 605-29. Ta r gosz , S., et a l. 20 03 : “L one Mot her s, Soc ia l E xclu sion a nd Depre s sion,” Psychological Medicine 33: 715-22. Van Lancker, W., et al. 2015: Workshop on Main Causes of Female Poverty, Brussels: Policy Department C, Citizens Rights and Constitutional Affairs. Van Parijs, P., 2015: “Four Puzzles on Gender Equality,” Law, Ethics and Philosophy 3. Whaley, RB, 2001: “The Paradoxical Relationship between Gender Inequality and Rape: Toward a Refined Theory,” Gender and Society 15: 531-55. Wilson, C., 2004: Moral Animals: Ideals and Constraints in Moral Theory, Oxford: Clarendon Press. Wolfinger, N. et al., 2008 “Problems in the Pipeline: Gender, Marriage and Fertility in the Ivory Tower,” The Journal of Higher Education 79: 388-405. http://appsso.eurostat.ec.europa.eu/nui/show.do?dataset=lfsa_egaed&lang=en LEAP 3 (2015) Do Women Enjoy a Political Advantage? Majority Position and Democratic Justice1 Pi E R R E -É T i E n n E vA n dA M M E Université Catholique de Louvain ABSTRACT Philippe van Parijs suggests that there might be a political inequality in favor of women, taken as a group, stemming both from their life expectancy and their supposed higher participation in elections due to their higher level of educat ion. he a lso wonders about t he status of t his inequa lit y. is it advantageous? is it unjust? Does it partially counterbalance other disadvantages or injustices? this papers starts by assessing and qualif ying the alleged inequalit y from an empirical perspective. it then considers van Parijs’ normative questions and argues that we should not consider the inequality as an advantage, nor an injustice, because mere membership in a majority group cannot plausibly be judged so. where women have strong common interests, they have no power; where they have electoral power, they have no overarching common interests. Key words: Political equality, gender equality, life expectancy, education, democratic justice introDuction in his provocative and stimulating paper on gender inequalities, Philippe van Parijs discusses four puzzles. i focus on the third, which concerns an alleged political inequality in favor of women, taken as a group, stemming both from their life expectancy and their supposed higher participation in elections due to their higher level of education. van Parijs recognizes that, all things considered, women suffer many more disadvantages than men, but wonders about the status of this inequality: is it advantageous? is it 1 i am very grateful to Paula casal for her numerous useful comments on earlier drafts of this paper and linguistic advice. i also thank Siba harb and leaP’s anonymous reviewers for various excellent suggestions. 117 Pierre-Étienne Vandamme LEAP 3 (2015) unjust? Does it partially counterbalance other disadvantages or injustices? i argue that we should not consider this inequality as an advantage, nor an injustice, because mere membership in a majority group cannot plausibly be judged so. 1. a General PuZZle aBout theSe PuZZleS Before considering van Parijs’ puzzle, i feel i should say a more general word about the questioned appropriateness of his paper, if only because it has engendered offended reactions. i have found around me that most men considered the puzzles amusing and stimulating, whereas most women found them inappropriate, if not stupid. it is certainly easier to discourse with lightness over the possible advantages of being a woman when you do not experience everyday domination nor bear the symbolic weight of an enduring oppression. therefore, even though i agree with van Parijs that the questions he raises are “worth asking” (van Parijs 2015: 88) and take this puzzle as an invitation to ref lect upon the interesting issue of democratic justice, i also agree with several of his critics that the puzzles are of little practical relevance and therefore somewhat odd in the writings of such a philosophe engagé. 2. the eXtent oF GenDer Political ineQuality van Parijs ma kes t wo empirica l hy pot heses. First, t hat women form a potential majority in all constituencies with universal suffrage where they enjoy longer life expectancy. although men are more numerous at birth almost every where in the world, it is true that women outnumber them in the population of most advanced democracies, such as western europe and north america. By contrast, the sex ratio tends to be reversed in africa and asia.2 Second, he suggests that this unequal balance of electoral power might be increased by a larger participation of women in elections, thanks to their higher level of education in several countries. this is more controversial. it has generally proven true in the history of democracy that the level of education increases electoral turnout (norris 2004: 175). the correlation between education and women’s turnout is expressed by the fact that in developed countries, where they are likely to have a more equal access to education, the gender gap has disappeared: women participate in elections 2 See the cia’s “world Factbook” https://www.cia.gov/library/publications/the-world- factbook/fields/2018.html https://www.cia.gov/library/publications/the-world-factbook/fields/2018.html https://www.cia.gov/library/publications/the-world-factbook/fields/2018.html Do Women Enjoy a Political Advantage? 118 LEAP 3 (2015) at least as much as men (norris 2002).3 in contrast, in newer democracies, where unexamined religious norms and/or sexist social norms reducing women’s educational opportunities tend to be more pervasive, women’s turnout to elections is lower. in recent history, though, there seems to be a clear secular trend, expressed in the generational variations in women’s turnout (norris 2002) and political orientation (Stevens 2007: 52-58). is it then the case that, in contexts where women are on average more highly educated, the inequality in electoral turnout is reinforced? not really. in advanced democracies, w it h t he exceptions of t he united States and Sw it zerla nd – which somet imes a lter t he genera l picture –, educat ion seems to have almost no effect anymore on turnout (Przeworski 2010: 94). the impact of education on electoral participation is generally higher in less aff luent countries, which usually show less gender equality and less female participation in elections.4 therefore, where the impact of education on turnout is high, women might not otherwise enjoy high turnout or a higher level of education. what is more, even where higher education does increase turnout, a reversed tendency might counterbalance it, as a low education profile seems to affect women’s (lower) turnout much more than men’s (norris 2002). in sum, the accumulation of the t wo advantages env isioned by van Parijs – participation and education – is plausible in the u.S., and possibly Switzerland, yet much less elsewhere. this does not affect his hypothesis that longer life expectancy might constitute a political advantage, but it restricts the extent of the supposed inequality of political power. now, what could somewhat increase the plausibility of van Parijs’ claim is the amusing fact that “sur veys find more people say ing that they have voted than the actual polling figures confirm” (Stevens 2007: 49) and “men are slightly more likely than women to misrepresent having gone to the polls” (verba et al. 1997: 1054). this, however, is unlikely to increase significantly women’s actual electoral power. a more promising path for van Parijs could be to consider the effects of age on turnout, which used to worry him (van Parijs 2011). as he knows, older people tend to vote more than younger people (norris 2004: 125; van Parijs 2011: 35). and contrary to what he seems to assume (van Parijs 2015), the ratio of elderly women to elderly men is higher than the ratio of women to men at younger ages (cia 2014; casal 2015). in light of developed democracy’s 3 they often have more or less equal rates of turnout, and as they often outnumber men in those societies, they often (yet not always) outnumber them in elections. 4 this with reservations, as little information is available about turnout rates broken down by sex. See norris 2002. 119 Pierre-Étienne Vandamme LEAP 3 (2015) tendency to face an ageing population, one might thus think that the imbalance of electoral power is increasing in the west. however, the sex differential in life expectancy is now narrowing with the years in developed countries after having peaked between 1970 and 1980 (Glei and horiuchi 2007). So, while differences in turnout according to age may slightly increase the imbalance of electoral power, ageing will probably not. Political action, however, is not reducible to participation in elections.5 this brings in another reason for tempering van Parijs’ hypothesis that women could enjoy some political advantage. it seems that “[w]ith respect to most forms of political activity other than voting, women are slightly less active than men” (verba et al. 1997: 1053).6 this comes from the fact that they generally have less resources to spend on political activity than men, but also that they have on average less interest in – and knowledge about – politics. this difference, it appears, “persist[s] at each educational level” (1060), and can be explained both by their perception of politics as a man’s game – their interest and knowledge increase in constituencies with female (potential) representatives – and a gender differentiated political education. in addition to this, their lower participation in the workforce also negatively affects women’s engagement with politics in the broader sense (et al. 2001: 198-218). Finally, the potential electoral advantage cannot be taken in isolation from the rest of the process characterized by a marked underrepresentation of women in parliaments, local government, media, or lobbying. elections constitute only a part of politics and turnout does not amount to political engagement. rather than a political inequality in favor of women, it would thus be more appropriate to talk about a potential electoral inequality in their favor or, more precisely, a potential inequalit y in active suffrage, dwarfed by an unfavorable inequalit y along most other dimensions of inf luential political action. 5 this is not denied by van Parijs, but somewhat obscured by his tendency to use a Schumpeterian model of democracy. See van Parijs 2011. 6 Marien et al. (2010) recently arrived to the opposite conclusion, using a broader data set t ha n Burns, Sch lozma n a nd verba, who ma in ly focused on t he uS. More cross- countr y investigation wou ld be necessa r y. yet what seems to account for t he dif ference is mainly a different understanding of political participation. Marien, hooghe and Quintelier conclude that women are more active in non-electoral politics because they consider charity donations and products boycotting – both performed more often by women than men – as i mpor ta nt “pa r t icipat ion acts.” yet it seems to be i n act iv it ies produci ng i n f luence on institutionalized politics (party membership, party meetings, direct contacts with politicians) that women are generally less active than men – except for signing petitions (Marien et al. 2010). Furthermore, if you consider the money invested in political action beside the time dedicated to it, the imbalance of influence in favor of men becomes more apparent (Burns et al. 2001: 68). Do Women Enjoy a Political Advantage? 120 LEAP 3 (2015) 3. iS thiS ineQuality unJuSt? iS it even an aDvantaGe? having a qualified picture of the extent of the (potential) inequality in active suffrage in favor of women, we can consider its normative implications. if the inequality in active suffrage is only caused by an unequal use of an equal opportunity to vote, one might argue that there is no injustice. For there being procedural injustice, one needs to trace back the unequal turnout to unequal opportunities. w hen men’s turnout is lower than women’s, it might be because they are on average younger and less educated. life expectancy does not affect men’s opportunities to vote, since at each age, all other things being equal, they have equal opportunities to do so. what about their lower educational achievements? they cannot plausibly stem from unequal educational opportunities, but they might result from unequal educational abilities. if this were the case, one may argue that this involves some procedural injustice in countries where education has an impact on turnout. this small disadvantage, however, would be cancelled by all the other advantages politically enjoyed by men, which provide them many more opportunities of political influence than women. Moreover, if women’s higher educational achievements are due to unequal opportunities in the job market (Mora 2015), men suffer neither unequal educational opportunities nor unequal voting opportunities, and there is no procedural injustice. van Parijs seems nevertheless more concerned w ith people’s use of their votes than with procedural justice. what he invites us to consider are the implications of being in a majority or minority position in a constituency. here the problem is not procedural. that women have more power because t hey a re more numerous is procedura l ly irreproachable : it is t he ver y implication of the basic principle of political equality – one person, one vote. the worry is that they could turn this numerical advantage into a substantial injustice. van Parijs’ approach is radically consequentialist, as illustrated by his past discussion of the disenfranchisement of the elderly (van Parijs 2011: 31-66). to be member of a minority group cannot by itself be considered as an injustice, but a minority position makes groups more vulnerable to injustices. as people differ along many lines in characteristics, we are all potentially members of a minority group. what can be considered as democratically unjust – or can lead to substantive injustices – is to have political institutions 121 Pierre-Étienne Vandamme LEAP 3 (2015) arranged in such a way that majority groups are allowed to exert domination over minorities.7 But domination should not be understood here as Philip Pettit (2012) does. according to him, it is sufficient for there being domination that one agent has the possibility or power to arbitrarily interfere with the choices and actions of another. yet such understanding of domination is of little use for exploring democratic justice in group relationships because virtually all potential majorities dominate potential minorities. ian Shapiro, for example, defends a conception of domination that is more useful for our purpose. he suggests that having the capacity to interfere with people’s basic interests “does not itself constitute domination; rather it creates the potential for domination” (Shapiro 2012: 324).8 what matters for democratic justice is therefore to assess the plausibility of the threat that one group will take advantage of a favorable balance of power to actually dominate another by systematically favoring its ow n interests at the expense of the other’s. it is the case, for example, when an ethnic group outnumbers another one towards which it is hostile, or because the employed largely outnumber the unemployed. there you find ground for justifying constitutionally protected rights for minorities, in order to avoid this specific kind of domination. to the contrary, we do not consider people with blue eyes as disadvantaged because in a minority, as it is unlikely that they are going to suffer a political disadvantage because of this imbalance of power. they can take part in multiple more plausible majority coalitions, as does the minority sometimes formed by men. i mean by this that it will prove easy for men, as for the blue-eyed, to build a coalition of interests or convictions cross-cutting sexes and eye color. now, it seems quite implausible to consider the fact that women generally outnumber men as an advantage, because where they could take advantage of their number, they lack the interest in doing so. the only common interest of women which could bring them together despite the diversity of their socio-economic interests and their diverging values is the avoidance of male domination. this explains general progresses towards more gender equality since the advent of universal suffrage. yet, in the countries where they are the most oppressed – say, Saudi arabia –, women are not allowed to vote. in oppressive democracies, where they are entitled to vote but lack education 7 i say “democratically unjust” because social injustices are not reducible to domination. nevertheless, contrary to a just society, a just democracy cannot eliminate all kinds of unfair advantages. Politically relevant majorities will always enjoy an advantage – stemming from the inescapable use of majority rule –, which it should be the aim to minimize, at least in such a way as to reduce political domination. 8 as Shapiro suggests, Pettit’s understanding of domination “partly accounts for [his] schizoid attitude toward the state” (Shapiro 2012: 321), as it pushes him to defend multiple veto players that can lead to a political stand still. Do Women Enjoy a Political Advantage? 122 LEAP 3 (2015) and freedom of conscience, they can vote but either do it less than men – see india –, or do it against their common interest – be it under the pressure of their male relatives or because they have internalized some oppressive ideology. only in countries where they have equal access to education and are freed from ideological domination could they use their number as an advantage and “convert [it] into an even greater inequality in their favor” (van Parijs 2015: 85). But in those contexts, their common interest – reducing male domination – does not seem strong enough to offset their divergent interests and values.9 take the u.S. as an example. Since the 80s, contrary to their previous tendency, women have tended to support Democrats more than men at every election (Stevens 2007: 55-56). Moreover, since 1964, women systematically outnumber men in presidential elections, with a difference reaching 7.2 million votes in 1996 (norris 2002).10 one could then wonder why republicans do not adapt t heir prog ra ms – on reproduct ive issues for ex a mple – to catch more fema le votes. Such a n i nt u it ion seems to be endorsed by van Parijs when he says that “on the assumption that the electorate is not stupid or blind, [the representatives], whether women or men, w ill only be elected a nd re-elected if t he policies t hey propose or adopt match t he preferences of the female majorit y” ( van Parijs 2015: 84). yet the latter preferences vary along many dimensions and are not sufficiently tied together to ma ke women’s votes a n at t ract ive speci f ic ta rget for republicans. conflicts of economic interests and (religious) values largely dominate the competition for votes. targeting one gender group at the expense of consistency regarding those more sensible issues is risky for both parties. women, as everyone, assign priorities to some political goals over others, and seldom are their special interests – those they share only w ith women – on top of the list. this probably explains why historical attempts to create women’s parties “have generally proved short-lived” (Stevens 2007: 100). For all these reasons, it seems implausible to characterize the larger number of women among voters as an actual advantage, and even more as an injustice. it could be advantageous for them in a hy pothetical world with full consciousness of their common interests and no division along other lines. then, only, would we have to take it seriously and possibly design institutions in such a way as to reduce their possibilities of turning this 9 w hat is more, these countries have generally adopted strong anti-discrimination laws which undermine the possibility of a domination of men by women. these laws do not make male domination disappear, as it is rooted in pervasive social norms, but they would most probably impede new forms of domination. Political power is not unchecked. 10 this could be due both to demography and education, as the latter does have an effect on turnout in the uS. 123 Pierre-Étienne Vandamme LEAP 3 (2015) advantage into an injustice.11 in the meantime, men can sleep soundly. concluSion i have argued that the electoral power imbalance between men and women is a fact in advanced democracies, yet not very significant – contrary to van Parijs’ hy pot hesis –, a nd to be considered a longside a reversed power imbalance along other dimensions of political action neglected by his a rg u ment. t hen i have cla i med t hat for a major it y to exer t pol it ica l domination, and thus turn a numerical advantage into an unjust democratic advantage, it needs power and overarching common interests. where women have strong common interests, they have no power; where they have electoral power, they no longer have overarching common interests. the fact that they constitute a potential electoral majority is thus unlikely to constitute an injustice someday nor to counterbalance (even modestly) other political disadvantages – such as the fact that women are underrepresented, less politically stimulated, and have fewer resources for political engagement. BiBlioGraPhy Burns, n., Schlozman, K. and verba, S., 2001: The Private Roots of Public Action: Gender, Equality, and Political Participation, cambridge: harvard university Press. casal, P., 2011: “love not war. on the chemistry of Good and evil,” in Arguing About Justice: Essays for Philippe Van Parijs, ed. a. Gosseries and y. vanderborght, 145- 155, louvain-la-neuve: Presses universitaires de louvain. — 2015: “Distributive Justice and Female longevity,” Law, Ethics and Philosophy 3: 90 - 106. cia, 2014: “the world Factbook,” https://w w w.cia.gov/librar y/publications/the- world-factbook Glei, D., and horiuchi, S., 2007: “the narrowing Sex Differential in life expectancy in high-income Populations: effects of Differences in the age Pattern of Mortality,” Population Studies 61: 141-159. Marien, S., hooghe, M. and Quintelier, e., 2010: “inequalities in non-institutionalized Forms of Political Participation: a Multi-level analysis of 25 countries,” Political Studies 58: 187-213. Mora, J., 2015: “women’s Greater educational efforts as a consequence of inequality,” Law, Ethics and Philosophy 3: 107-115. norris, P., 2002: “women’s Power at the Ballot Box,” voter turnout Since 1945: a Global report, international institute for Democracy and electoral assistance: 95-102, 11 note that this hypothetical power imbalance might bring, overall, more justice, as it seems that most crimes and injustices are committed by men (casal 2011; Pinker 2011), and van Parijs argued elsewhere (van Parijs 2011) that we should opt for the democratic arrangement most favorable to justice, even at the cost of political equality. https://www.cia.gov/library/publications/the-world-factbook/ https://www.cia.gov/library/publications/the-world-factbook/ Do Women Enjoy a Political Advantage? 124 LEAP 3 (2015) http://w w w.idea.int/publications/v t/upload/v t_screenopt _ 2002.pdf 2004: Electoral Engineering: Voting Rules and Political Behavior, cambridge: cambridge university Press. Pettit, P., 2012: On the People’s Terms: A Republican Theory and Model of Democracy, cambridge: cambridge university Press. Pinker, S., 2011: The Better Angels of Our Nature: The Decline of Violence in History and Its Causes, london: Penguin Books. Przeworsk i, a., 2010 : Democracy and the Limits of Self-Government, new york: cambridge university Press. Shapiro, i., 2012: “on non-Domination,” University of Toronto Law Journal 62: 293-335. Stevens, a., 2007: Women, Power and Politics, new york: Palgrave McMillan. van Parijs, P., 2011: Just Democracy. The Rawls-Machiavelli Programme, colchester: ecPr Press. — 2015: “Four Puzzles on Gender equality,” Law, Ethics and Philosophy 3: 79-89. verba, S., Burns, n., and Schlozman, K., 1997: “Knowing and caring about Politics: Gender and Political engagement,” The Journal of Politics 59: 1051-72. http://www.idea.int/publications/vt/upload/VT_screenopt_2002.pdf LEAP 3 (2015) A Blatant Case of Over-Accommodation1 vA L E R i A OT TOn E L L i Genova University Abstract van Parijs asks whether the fact that men engage in regrettable behavior at much higher rates than women could be seen as a “handicap” due to their hormonal set-up, and therefore as a dimension of gender inequality to men’s disadvantage. i argue that this suggestion rests on unwarranted assumptions about the meaning of gender equality and the causes of men’s behavior. Moreover, even if for the argument’s sake we grant these unwarranted assumpt ions, it is easy to show t hat no unfa irness is suf fered by men because of their (supposedly) unbalanced hormonal constitution. indeed, if any injustice is done by our current social arrangements, it is injustice to those who suffer from the over-accommodation of this highly dangerous and destructive trait of men’s character. Keywords: gender equality, hormones, disabilities, violence introDuction it is a known fact that men get themselves into trouble much more often than women do. they commit 95% of murders worldwide (unoDc 2013), over 95% of recorded rapes in europe (heuni 2014), and every where have a greater tendency to engage in inappropriate or wrongful sexual behavior. the vast majority of serial killers, prostitute killers, serial rapists, and sociopaths in general are also male. as a result, men are more likely than women to spend long terms in jail and suffer from social disgrace. in his piece on gender equality, van Parijs suggests that this phenomenon can be traced to hormonal causes. he does not produce any account of how this may be so, but refers to an intriguing article by Paula casal (2011) in which scientific evidence on the correlation between high testosterone levels, typical of males, and aggressive, unempathetic, careless, and anti-social 1 For helpful suggestions, i thank Paula casal and three anonymous referees. 126 Valeria Ottonelli LEAP 3 (2015) behavior is discussed. van Parijs asks whether the fact that men engage in regrettable behavior at much higher rates than women could be seen as a “handicap” and therefore as a dimension of gender inequalit y to men’s disadvantage. van Parijs’ puzzle about hormonal inequalit y relies on a biased and incomplete description of the facts at hand. once the facts are reassessed a nd more accurately described, it becomes clea r t hat no unfa irness is suffered by men because of their (supposedly) testosterone-driven behavior. indeed, if any injustice is done by our current social arrangement, it is injustice to those who suffer from the over-accommodation of this highly dangerous and destructive trait of men’s character. Moreover, van Parijs’ argument not only assumes a description of our social world that is deeply misleading and inaccurate, but also rests on factual and normative assumptions that are highly controversial. i intend to accept such assumptions for the sake of my argument. however, it will be worth making them explicit and show how disputable and unwarranted they are. this is where my discussion will start. 1. two unwarranteD aSSuMPtionS BehinD the Fourth PuZZle van Parijs’ arguments rest on two main premises. the first concerns t he meaning of gender inequality; the second concerns the hormonal bases of men’s behavior. let’s start with his notion of gender inequality. From the way in which van Parijs frames the puzzle on hormonal inequality and the other puzzles he considers, it looks as if what he has in mind by gender inequalit y are differences in opportunities for welfare or resources bet ween men and women. this is not a n obv ious presupposit ion. in t he rich a nd high ly sophisticated literature on gender inequality (for some useful surveys, see Squires 2000, ch. 4; walby 2004; verloo and lombardo 2007), indeed, such a metric of equality is far from central. even when comparisons between levels of achievement in terms of resources or welfare are made (see for example young 2001; Phillips 2003), in most cases they are not taken as releva nt per se, but as indicators of ot her dimensions of injust ice a nd gender inequa lit y. For exa mple, women’s higher unemploy ment rates, lower income, a nd g reater ha rdship resu lt ing f rom divorce a re ta ken as signs of the domination, oppression, and exploitation that women suffer in our societ y. considering the intricate and fascinating philosophical questions that are involved in these debates, it is puzzling that van Parijs A Blatant Case of Over-Accommodation 127 LEAP 3 (2015) assumes as unproblematic that the relevant notion of equalit y at stake must be some version of equality of opportunity for welfare or resources. w hat is even more disconcerting is that this unwarranted assumption evidently leads van Parijs to believe that the only alternative to posing the unorthodox questions he asks is to restate mere “well-meaning platitudes” (van Parijs 2015: 79). once we assume a different notion of gender equalit y than the one chosen by van Parijs, such as equality as non-domination or democratic equality as the equal access to full citizenship, it becomes evident that his remarks are in need of much further analysis. Merely pointing at a highly circumscribed welfare loss or an unsatisfied preference will not do. the second highly controversial assumption that van Parijs makes is that men’s criminal and sexually inappropriate behavior is explained by hormones. this cannot be the full story. if violent behavior were simply driven by male hormones, we would not be able to explain why, for example, in 2012 in South africa there were 31 homicides per 100,000 people (and 64.5 in 1995), 39.3 in Jamaica, 90.4 in honduras, 7 in Moldova, 7 in west Bank and Gaza, and just 1 in the netherlands, italy and Spain (unoDc 2013). of course, in all these countries most killers are men, but such huge variations in homicide rates suggest that the reason cannot be an evenly spread feature like testosterone. the same should be noted about sexual behavior. rape, sexual harassment, or paid sex cannot be interpreted as the mere satisfaction of an impellent physiological urge (Pateman 1988: 198). in truth, at a point in his discussion, van Parijs considers the possibility that the bases of men’s behavior are not hormonal, but rather social and environmental. he suggests, however, that his analysis of the disadvantage suffered by men “holds irrespective of the validity of the hormonal diagnosis” (van Parijs 2015: 87). in the following discussion, i will treat van Parijs’ puzzle in its straightforward, unqualified version based on the hypothesis that men suffer from a “handicap” caused by their hormonal constitution. in fact, as i will note at the end, van Parijs is right that the conclusions we may reach on this puzzle can easily be extended to the case in which men’s behavior is determined by environmental factors rather than hormones. 2. why iS Men’S “hanDicaP” not treateD? i interpret the hormonal puzzle as a matter of justice. i do so not only because this is how van Parijs formulates it when summing up the four puzzles at the end of his discussion (2015: 88), but also because the debate about gender equality he contributes to is in fact a debate about justice. Discussing gender inequality is not making humorous lists of relative pros and cons of being 128 Valeria Ottonelli LEAP 3 (2015) a woman or a man, or asking ourselves which gender we should “pity” the most. we ask about inequalities between men and women because we worry that they are a matter of social injustice. i therefore assume that van Parijs points to hormonal inequality because he thinks that there is something wrong with the fact that, in our society, a biological feature leading to dysfunctional behavior, which therefore can be described as an unchosen “handicap,” determines the fate and opportunity for welfare and resources of those affected. in order to assess whether men’s levels of testosterone can be treated as a handicap that raises issues of justice, we may compare it to standard cases of disabilities, for example someone who has lost her capacity to walk. Given the conception of equality that we are assuming here, she suffers injustice to the extent that her unchosen handicap affects her prospects of success in terms of welfa re or resources. in order to redress t hat injust ice, if her disability is due to a reversible medical condition, she should have access to adequate healthcare. when this is not possible, society should accommodate her needs and abilities, by removing all the architectural barriers, social rules and practices that cause her physical constitution to be a disadvantage. to the extent that this is unfeasible, she must be compensated. now, consider van Parijs’ worry about men’s hormonal constitution. what is the nature of this alleged genetic handicap? van Parijs admits that high levels of testosterone do not imply that men can never manage to repress their instincts in order to avoid their worst expressions, but believes that high levels of testosterone induce a tendency to lose control and engage in various forms of anti-social behavior (yildirim and Derksen 2011). in fact, mu rders a nd rapes a re on ly t he most d ra mat ic ex pressions of such a biological disposition. in the literature van Parijs indirectly refers to, high levels of testosterone are associated with aggressive (Montoya et al. 2012), uncaring, unempathetic (Zilioli et al. 2014), and risk-taking (Stanton et al. 2011) behav ior; t his not on ly ma kes men prone to v iolent crimes, but a f fe c t s a l l t hei r i nter ac t ion s w it h ot her p e ople a nd t hei r e v er yd ay activ ities (legato 2006). if we assume that it is something built into men’s constitution, then this actually looks like a ver y unfortunate condition, w h ich shou ld be recog n i z ed a s a ha nd ic ap. i f we a re wor r ied about injustice, then we should ask whether our society is doing enough to treat, accommodate, or compensate men for such an impairing disability. if not, men could legitimately complain about our current social arrangement. as a matter of fact, in our societies we witness no attempt to treat male’s hormonal handicap. however, once we start inquiring about this lack of treatment, we realize that the analogy with other central cases of disability breaks down. the reason why men are not treated, in fact, is not because A Blatant Case of Over-Accommodation 129 LEAP 3 (2015) males are carelessly left to themselves with their impairing handicap, as is the case with other conditions that could be treated but are not. rather, the reason why men are not treated is that male aggressive, unempathetic, careless, and risky behavior is taken, and has been taken for centuries, as the norm rather than a handicap. our whole social world has been organized around the notion that male behavior, as sociopathic as it may look to an enlightened mind, is just normal – if not the model to emulate. of course, the norm is not described as being aggressive, unempathetic, and prone to risk-taking; the use of these disapproving descriptions is ruled out exactly because male behavioral predispositions have always been and still are very much taken as the golden standard. rather, those attitudes, typically feminine, that depart from the male constitution taken as the norm are described as feeble, overly risk-adverse, and women are taken to be exceedingly prone to swooning, fainting, and crying. in this respect, like in others, women are conceived as men “minus certain attributes whose paradigm is morphological” (irigaray 1985: 27); women’s feeble character is traced to their ill-developed biological constitution. in fact, the proposal that men’s disposition to v iolent and aggressive behav ior could be treated as a handicap and changed through a direct i nter vent ion on t hei r hor mona l con st it ut ion wou ld be perceived a s horrif y ing. a lthough the alteration of female hormonal constitution is of ten read i ly accepted, be t hat for bi r t h cont rol or ach ievement s i n competitive sports, any curtailment of male hormonal constitution tends to be perceived as an unbearable form of violence. this is exactly because those hormonal traits that make males so unfit for healthy social interactions are, in fact, cherished by our culture. 3. how Men’S hanDicaP iS over-accoMMoDateD with other disabilities, it is often the case that when they fail to be recognized as unchosen handicaps, they fail to be accommodated by social institutions as well. this is the case, for example, with many conditions that received scientific and social recognition only recently, such as fibromyalgia, seasonal affective disorder, or genetic proneness to obesity. here is another point at which the parallel between men’s handicapping hormonal constitution and other central cases of disability breaks down. in fact, the failure to recognize men’s “handicap” as such does not result in a lack of accommodation by social institutions, since it is, indeed, seen as perfectly normal and even valuable. as a consequence, the tastes, values, and needs of men, and especially of the most aggressive among them, have shaped our entire social and political system, reaching an almost perfect level of accommodation. 130 Valeria Ottonelli LEAP 3 (2015) van Parijs seems to suggest that this was true once, in the remote times of Genghis Khan, but it is no longer the case in our highly civilized society in which physical violence no longer provides a social advantage. however, the genetic trait we are considering here is not violent behavior per se, but the high levels of testosterone that make males aggressive, competitive, ca reless, a nd prone to risk. those t ra its, in fact, st i l l const itute a ver y valuable factor of social advancement and prestige, and are still associated w it h h ig her probabi l it ies to occupy top-ra n k posit ions i n econom ic orga ni zat ions a nd polit ica l inst itut ions. the capacit y for “leadership” continues to be celebrated in our society and its major economic and social domains; empirical studies show that such capacity is consistently associated with aggressive, competitive, and careless behavior (alimo-Metcalfe 2010). not surprisingly, a strong association has been found between possessing high testosterone levels and being rewarded as a “leader” in firms and social h iera rch ies i n genera l (Sher ma n et a l. 2015). l ack of “r isk-aversion” a nd “compet it ive agg ressiveness” a re considered const itut ive of good entrepreneurship (rauch et al. 2009), and this is seen as giv ing men a comparative advantage (Sapienza et al. 2006; lim and envick 2013). even in the apparently peaceful, enlightened, and highly civ ilized academic world, being competitive, aggressive, and not “too nice” is rewarded in terms of career and prestige ( van den Brink and Benschop 2012: 515-16; Bell and King 2010). there’s more. in fact, if we look at how our major institutions and social pract ices a re bu i lt a nd work, we rea l i ze t hat ou r t reat ment of ma les’ unfortunate hormonal constitution represents indeed a rare case of over- accommodation of an impairing disabilit y. to see how this may be so, consider that wherever a public policy for the accommodation of people with disabilities exists, an important condition is included, which we might call a “safety proviso”2: the accommodation and inclusion in social, political, and economic institutions of people with disabilities should not cause grave risks to the safety and health of third parties. For example, in many western countries, as people get older they have to pass physical examinations at increasing ly shor ter inter va ls in order to renew t heir driver’s license. Someone who suffers from narcolepsy cannot be hired as an air-traffic controller or as a school bus driver. of course, this does not mean that their disabi lit ies shou ld not be addressed or t hat t he cost of ca rr y ing t hem should fall only on those affected. People who cannot drive should have access to cheap and easily available public transportation; those who, for medical reasons, cannot be hired in certain jobs must have an adequate choice of alternative careers. however, no wrong is done to them if they are 2 a much discussed example is Section 504 of the Americans with Disabilities Act of 1990 A Blatant Case of Over-Accommodation 131 LEAP 3 (2015) prevented from engaging in those activ ities which would result in very h ig h r i s k s for ot her p e ople. i nde e d, t he s a fet y pr ov i s o i s si mpl y a requ i rement of justice; it rightly protects the welfare and opportunities of those who might be affected by risky or dangerous activities. if we take seriously the idea that due to their high testosterone levels men tend to engage in agg ressive, risk y, ca reless, or even sociopat hic behavior, then we immediately see that not only the hormonal disability that affects men is largely accommodated in our society, but, in fact, it is unduly over-accommodated, since in t heir case t he sa fet y prov iso is massively violated. unlike poor-sighted people wanting to f ly planes, men are not prevented from engaging in activities and taking up roles that are likely to put other people at risk if carried out by someone with such an unbalanced constitution. in fact, men represent the vast majority in those jobs in which testosterone-driven aggressive, risky, and careless behavior is most likely to cause serious damages. in western countries, 75% to 90% of those who work in law enforcement a re men; women a re on ly 10 % of t he police workforce in Portugal,3 13% in Spain,4 13% in italy and the u.S.,5 15% in France, 22% in the netherlands and 28.2% in the u.K.6 Men still occupy the vast majority of public offices and are still dominating politics, especially in those executive roles that require making life-and-death decisions on the fate of millions of people. Men represent 93% of political leaders (heads of state or heads of government) in the world;7 88% of u.S. State Governors are men; 88% of mayors of u.S. major cities are male; 8 in europe, 66% of members of national Supreme courts are men;9 they make up 82% of those sitting in decision-making bodies of central Banks;10 they are 73% of senior ministers in national cabinets; and 89% of leaders of major political parties 3 http://w w w.theportugalnews.com/news/only-one-in-10-psp-officers-is-a- woman/6061 [last accessed 12 February 2016]. 4 http://w w w.elnortedecastilla.es/salamanca/201510/17/mujeres-ganan-poder- representan-20151017123638.html [last accessed 12 February 2016]. 5 http://w w w.criminaljusticeschoolinfo.com/women-law-enforcement.html [last accessed 12 Februar y 2016]. 6 http://sputniknews.com/europe/20151202/1031099667/uk-women-police. html[last accessed 12 February 2016]. 7 http://w w w.unwomen.org/en/what-we-do/leadership-and-political- participation/facts-and-figures [last accessed 12 February 2016]. 8 http://w w w.fairvote.org/election-of-women-in-our-100-largest-cities- disadvantaged-by-districts [last accessed 12 February 2016]. 9 http://ec.europa.eu/justice/gender-equality/gender-decision-making/database/ judiciary/supreme-courts/index _en.htm [last accessed 12 February 2016]. 10 http://ec.europa.eu/justice/gender-equality/gender-decision-making/database/ business-finance/central-banks/index _en.htm [last accessed 12 February 2016]. http://www.theportugalnews.com/news/only-one-in-10-psp-officers-is-a-woman/6061 http://www.theportugalnews.com/news/only-one-in-10-psp-officers-is-a-woman/6061 http://www.elnortedecastilla.es/salamanca/201510/17/mujeres-ganan-poder-representan-20151017123638.html http://www.elnortedecastilla.es/salamanca/201510/17/mujeres-ganan-poder-representan-20151017123638.html http://www.criminaljusticeschoolinfo.com/women-law-enforcement.html http://sputniknews.com/europe/20151202/1031099667/uk-women-police.html http://sputniknews.com/europe/20151202/1031099667/uk-women-police.html http://www.unwomen.org/en/what-we-do/leadership-and-political-participation/facts http://www.unwomen.org/en/what-we-do/leadership-and-political-participation/facts http://www.fairvote.org/election http://ec.europa.eu/justice/gender-equality/gender-decision-making/database/judiciary/supreme-courts/index_en.htm http://ec.europa.eu/justice/gender-equality/gender-decision-making/database/judiciary/supreme-courts/index_en.htm http://ec.europa.eu/justice/gender-equality/gender-decision-making/database/business-finance/central-banks/index_en.htm http://ec.europa.eu/justice/gender-equality/gender-decision-making/database/business-finance/central-banks/index_en.htm 132 Valeria Ottonelli LEAP 3 (2015) are men.11 although in europe women are the majority of physicians under 35, men still dominate the higher ranks of the medical profession12 (they occupy 86% of top posit ions in ita ly;13 89% of leadership posit ions in Germany;14 and they represent 72% of consultants in the u.K.)15. 83,7% of the u.S. active army,16 almost 90% of the u.K. army,17 85% of the French army,18 and 93% of the italian army19 are still composed by men. Such an over whelming presence of men in dangerous, difficult, and ha zardous jobs presumably causes countless episodes of killings, torture, physical aggression, humiliation, maltreatment, medical malpractice,20 physical injuries, and deaths by negligence each year.21 Moreover, we should also be aware that the breach of the safety proviso in the case of men would produce even more victims if the non-hormonally- handicapped half of humanity, i.e. women, did not put in practice a whole array of everyday techniques in order to avoid or untrigger men’s violence and aggression. these span from coping strategies in abusive relationships (waldrop and resick 2004), to self-imposed curfews at night (Bondi and Metha 1999), to the simple act of switching to the opposite sidewalk when a group of men approaches. the non-hormona lly-handicapped ha lf of humanity constantly works at reducing the toll that the over-accommodation of men’s disability would otherwise exact. But this of course has enormous socia l costs in terms of oppor tunit ies for resources or welfa re, which disproportionately affect women. 11 http://w w w.unwomen.org/en/what-we-do/leadership-and-political- participation/facts-and-figures [last accessed 12 February 2016]. 12 http://w w w.healthcare-in-europe.com/en/article/11487-male-female-doktors. html [last accessed 12 February 2016]. 13 http://w w w.quotidianosanita.it/lavoro-e-professioni/articolo.php?articolo_ id=12545 [last accessed 12 February 2016]. 14 http://w w w.healthcare-in-europe.com/en/article/11487-male-female-doktors. html [last accessed 12 February 2016]. 15 http://w w w.theguardian.com/society/2010/aug/22/women-doctors-top-nhs- jobs [last accessed 12 February 2016]. 16 http://w w w.army.mil/women/today.html [last accessed 12 February 2016]. 17 http://w w w.huffingtonpost.co.uk/2015/03/27/women-britsh-armed-forces- sexism_n_6940538.html [last accessed 12 February 2016]. 18 http://w w w.lemonde.fr/societe/article/2014/04/15/l-armee-sous-pression-pour- conforter-la-place-des-femmes_4401356_3224.html [last accessed 12 February 2016]. 19 http://w w w.esercitoitalianoblog.it/donne-nellesercito-italiano-nemici-dentro- e-fuori/ [last accessed 12 February 2016]. 20 throughout the world men in the medical profession are consistently much more likely than women to be sued for malpractice and this can be traced to differences in their personality traits (Firth-cozens 2008). 21 compare for example the striking data on deadly road accidents caused by men’s reckless behaviour (al-Balbissi 2003). http://www.unwomen.org/en/what-we-do/leadership-and-political-participation/facts http://www.unwomen.org/en/what-we-do/leadership-and-political-participation/facts http://www.healthcare-in-europe.com/en/article/11487-male-female-doktors.html http://www.healthcare-in-europe.com/en/article/11487-male-female-doktors.html http://www.quotidianosanita.it/lavoro-e-professioni/articolo.php?articolo_id=12545 http://www.quotidianosanita.it/lavoro-e-professioni/articolo.php?articolo_id=12545 http://www.healthcare-in-europe.com/en/article/11487-male-female-doktors.html http://www.healthcare-in-europe.com/en/article/11487-male-female-doktors.html http://www.theguardian.com/society/2010/aug/22/women http://www.army.mil/women/today.html http://www.huffingtonpost.co.uk/2015/03/27/women-britsh-armed-forces-sexism_n_6940538.html http://www.huffingtonpost.co.uk/2015/03/27/women-britsh-armed-forces-sexism_n_6940538.html http://www.lemonde.fr/societe/article/2014/04/15/l-armee-sous-pression-pour-conforter-la-place-des-femmes_4401356_3224.html http://www.lemonde.fr/societe/article/2014/04/15/l-armee-sous-pression-pour-conforter-la-place-des-femmes_4401356_3224.html http://www.esercitoitalianoblog.it/donne A Blatant Case of Over-Accommodation 133 LEAP 3 (2015) in our society, the only measure that is taken to prevent the disastrous effects of men’s high testosterone levels are criminal laws against violent offences. these are a very poor way to address the risks posed by men’s handicap. they only offer an ex post response when the damage has already been done, are highly ineffective even as a deterrent to prevent future damages, a nd dispropor t ionately a f fect people f rom poor socia l backg rounds or members of stigmatized ethnic groups. the real target of these measures is not men’s per vasive and highly damaging aggressive, careless, and risk- taking behavior, but the kind of violent personal aggressions that are likely to occur and be persecuted in deprived social contexts. these considerations should also help us see why – as van Parijs remarks (2015: 87) – we pity members of racial minorities and other disadvantaged groups for the high rates of incarceration they suffer, while we do not tend to do the same with men. a short answer is that it is mainly male members of t hose d isadva ntaged g roups, rat her t ha n men i n genera l, who a re incarcerated and therefore should complain about the unfairness of our social arrangements.22 this is a case of intersectionality in which race and cla ss play a f u nda menta l role. Moreover, i f we t r y to d isenta ng le t he various determinants of high incarceration rates, we see that race and class on one hand, and gender on the other, play a completely different role. to the extent that incarceration can be traced to poverty, racism, lack of education, a dysfunctional family env ironment, or inadequate legal defense, it strikes us as an odious side effect of more fundamental forms of d i sadv a nt age c reated by ou r soc ia l i n st it ut ion s. to t he ex tent t hat incarceration can be traced to men’s proneness to aggressive, careless, and risky behavior, it strikes us as a poor and ineffective attempt to mitigate the most atrocious effects of the over-accommodation of such a dysfunctional behavioral trait. concluSion i have mainly focused here on the over-accommodation of men’s proneness to risky, aggressive, and careless behavior. however, it should be clear that parallel considerations could easily be extended to men’s exasperated libido. our society provides for all sorts of accommodations and over-accommodations of men’s sexual appetites, and prostitution is just one of the most evident expressions of such a bias towards men’s constitution and the fundamental friendliness to men’s sexuality that is a constant of most human societies. 22 western and Pettit (2010), for example, report that 68% of african american men born after 1970 who have dropped out of high school have prison records, vs. only1.2% of white males with college education. 134 Valeria Ottonelli LEAP 3 (2015) it should also be clear that our response to van Parijs’ puzzle on hormonal inequality would be the same even if we assumed that men’s behavior has social, rather than hormonal causes. Stressing the importance of socialization in the formation of men’s character would only make the central point of our response more evident: men’s aggressive, risk-taking, and careless behavior, far from being a disadvantage, is indeed cherished and accommodated in our society, and those traits of character are actively encouraged and rewarded since early infancy. what would be different, if we dismiss the hypothesis that men’s behavior is determined by hormones, is our picture of what it would take for our society to achieve justice, by redressing and preventing all the wrongs, dangers, and harms coming from the over-accommodation of men’s behavior. if we took the hormonal hypothesis seriously, then ideally, a just society would consider the dismal (and very costly) prospect of massively medicating males or excluding them from those jobs and roles in which their high testosterone levels create unbearable risks for other people. if we instead see men’s dysfunctional behav ior as ma in ly determined by env ironmenta l causes, just ice w i l l be achieved through a different and much more appealing path: by pursuing more en lightened met hods of ma le socia li zat ion, a nd a col lect ive re- evaluation of which character traits should count as good and valuable among human beings. BiBlioGraPhy al-Balbissi, a.h., 2003: “role of Gender in road accidents,” Traffic Injuries Prevention, 4: 64–73. alimo-Metcalfe, B., 2010: “an investigation of Female and Male constructs of leadership and empowerment,” Gender in Management: An International Journal, 25: 640-48. Bell, e. and King, D., 2010: “the elephant in the room: critical Management Studies conferences as a Site of Body Pedagogics,” Management Learning 41: 429–442. Bondi, l. and Mehta, a., 1999: “embodied Discourse: on Gender and Fear of violence,” Gender, Place and Culture, 6: 67-84. casal, P., 2011: “love not war. on the chemistry of Good and evil,” in Arguing About Justice. Essays for Philippe van Parijs, ed. a. Gosseries and y. vanderborght, 145- 157, louvain: louvain university Press. Firth-cozens, J., 2008: “Doctors with Difficulties: why So Few women?,” Postgraduate Medical Journal, 84: 318–20. heuni, 2014: European Sourcebook of Crime and Criminal Justice Statistics 2014, helsinki, european institute for crime Prevention and control. irigaray, l., 1985: Speculum of the Other Woman, ithaca: cornell university Press. lim, S. and envick B.r., 2013: “Gender and entrepreneurial orientation: a Multi-country Study,” International Entrepreneurship and Management Journal 9: 465-482. legato, M.J., 2006: Why Men Die First, new york: Palgrave. A Blatant Case of Over-Accommodation 135 LEAP 3 (2015) Montoya, e.r. et al., 2012: “testosterone, cortisol, and Serotonin as Key regulators of Socia l aggression: a rev iew and theoretica l Perspective,” Motivation and Emotion, 36: 65-73. Pateman, c., 1988: The Sexual Contract, Stanford: Stanford university Press. Phillips, a., 2003: “Defending equality of outcome,” Journal of Political Philosophy, 12: 1-19. rauch, a. et al., 2009: “entrepreneurial orientation and Business Performance: an assessment of Past research and Suggestions for the Future,” Entrepreneurship Theory and Practice, 33: 1042-2587. Sapienza, P., Zingales, l., Maestripieri D., 2009: “Gender Differences in Financial risk aversion and career choices are affected by testosterone,” PnaS 106: 15268– 15273. Sherman, G.D. et al., forthcoming: “the interaction of testosterone and cortisol is associated with attained Status in Male executives,” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology. Squires, J., 2000: Gender in Political Theory, cambridge: Polity Press. Stanton, J.S., liening, S.h. and Schultheiss, o.c., 2011: “testosterone is Positively associated with risk taking in the iowa Gambling task,” Hormones and Behavior, 59: 252–256. unoDc, 2013: Global Study on Homicide 2013, new york, united nations Publications. van den Brink, M. and Benschop, y., 2012: “Gender Practices in the construction of academic excellence: Sheep with Five legs,” Organization 19: 507-24. verloo, M. and lombardo, e., 2007: “contested Gender equality and Policy variety in europe,” in Multiple Meanings of Gender Equality, ed. M. verloo, 21-50, Budapest: ceu Press. walby, S., 2004: “the european union and Gender equality: emergent varieties of Gender regime,” Social Politics, 11: 4-29. waldrop, a.e. and resick, P.a., 2004: “coping among adult Female victims of Domestic violence,” Journal of Family Violence, 19: 291–302. western, B. and Pettit, B., 2010: “incarceration and Social inequality”, Daedalus, 139: 8-19. yildirim, B.o. and Derksen, J.J.l., 2011: “a rev iew on t he relationship bet ween testosterone and life-course Persistent antisocial Behavior,” Psychiatry Research 200: 984–1010. young, i.M., 2001: “equality of whom?,” Journal of Political Philosophy, 9:1-18. Zilioli, S. et al., 2015: “testosterone, cortisol and empathy: evidence for the Dual- hormone hypothesis,” Adaptive Human Behavior and Physiology, 1: 421-433. LEAP 3 (2015) Are Unequal Incarceration Rates Unjust to Men?1 Gi n A SCHOu T E n Harvard University Abstract the genetic endowment of males makes them likelier than females to be perpetrators of violent crime and thus to end up in prison. Philippe van Parijs notes this and raises a startling question: is it not an injustice to males that their unchosen genetic endow ment renders them likelier to suffer the harms of incarceration? in this brief response, i canvass some tempting avenues by which we might think we can dispel the puzzle, and argue that each is unsuccessful. this will disappoint those hoping for a refutation of the claim lurking behind van Parijs’ question: that even as their criminal behavior is so profoundly harmful to so many innocent victims, male violent offenders are themselves somehow victims of injustice. i hope to show that this indignation-provoking claim is far more difficult to refute than we would have hoped, but also to suggest that it is far less threatening— and less bizarre—than we might have feared. Keywords: crime, gender, incarceration, justice, sex, testosterone introDuction in his fourth puzzle on gender equality, Philippe van Parijs notes that the genet ic endow ment of ma les ma kes t hem l i kel ier t ha n fema les to be perpetrators of v iolent crime and thus to end up in prison.2 he raises a startling question: if the unchosen genetic endow ment of males renders them likelier than females to suffer the harms of incarceration, could this be an injustice ( van Parijs 2015: 88) Plausibly, it adds to the injustice of poverty that those who grow up in poor families are likelier to be incarcerated 1 i am grateful to Paula casal, Jeff Behrends, harry Brighouse, and three anonymous reviewers at Law, Ethics, and Philosophy for asking challenging questions and making valuable suggestions on previous drafts of this response. 2 For more on biological contributions to male crime, see thornhill and Palmer 2000, casal 2011, and rainer 2013. For data on men’s greater criminality, see Greenfeld and Snell 2000. 137 Gina Schouten LEAP 3 (2015) than their more privileged counterparts.3 why, asks van Parijs, do we have the intuition that the elevated risk to those born with these disadvantages is different than the elevated risk to those born with male genetic endowments? those who are concerned about ongoing injustices against women are likely, at first, to find these puzzles irritating. we might lament the opportunity costs of theorizing alleged injustices against men when women continue to be victimized by pervasive structural injustices, and worry that such t heor i z i ng w i l l slow prog ress towa rd women’s equa l it y. i sha re t hese worries. Still, hormonal inequalities may generate injustices against men even if this fact is troubling for those concerned to strengthen coalitions for social reform on behalf of women. of course, it is right that men be overrepresented among the prison population given that they commit more violent offenses. we must protect victims and potential victims, and incarceration presently offers the best means of doing so. But is the higher likelihood of incarceration among ma les unjust? the ha rms of inca rcerat ion ca n be severe. they include foregone opportunities for flourishing, alienation from spouses and children, enhanced risk of being oneself a victim of violence, and difficulty finding and keeping employment subsequent to release.4 if men are, through no fault of their ow n, likelier to suffer these harms, then we must at least entertain van Parijs’ question—a puzzling question to be sure, since the putative injustice to men would result, most proximally, from their doing violence to their victims: often, women. in this brief response, i canvass some tempting avenues by which we might think we can dispel the puzzle, and argue that each is unsuccessful. no doubt other avenues for response exist, but i consider what i take to be the most plausible. having explored these possible responses and found them unsatisf ying, i tentatively conclude that men’s higher likelihood of 3 no doubt rates of inca rceration wou ld be higher in t hese communities even if crime rates were not, but i assume that part of this correlation is due to elevated crime rates. as van Parijs says, elevated crime rates among the poor are “in part no doubt but not only because they tend to be sentenced more severely for the same crimes” (87). 4 See na acP cr i m i na l Just ice Fact Sheet. Some of t hese ha r ms a re i nt r i nsic to incarceration, but some are contingent—incarceration need not be as harmful as we make it. i suspect that an elevated likelihood of criminal behavior is bad for offenders even if they are never caught: whether or not they feel remorse for their crime, violent offenders are likely to experience greater difficulty maintaining or developing intimate relationships. even those with a propensity to violence who never offend are likely to struggle to achieve and maintain the kinds of interpersonal relationships that, for so many, are crucial contributors to wellbeing, and they may be worse off for this whether or not they themselves judge it to be a loss. But nothing i say in the rest of this paper relies on the mere propensity to violence being harmful. all i will assume is that, on average, incarceration itself is harmful; i take it that any plausible metric of justice will have the resources to register it as such. Are Unequal Incarceration Rates Unjust to Men? 138 LEAP 3 (2015) incarceration is a distinct injustice to men. this tentative conclusion is highly counterintuitive, but i suspect that a great deal of our resistance to it owes to worries about the strategies we might pursue to remedy the injustice. So i conclude by briefly sketching what seem to me some promising social policies to address inequalities in incarceration prospects—including unequal prospects based on sex, if it turns out that such inequalities are unjust to men. how might we try to dispel the puzzle concerning men’s incarceration? i first consider some reasons for thinking there is no injustice at all. i then consider a response that grants that there is some injustice but maintains that it is overridden by the many injustices of which men are beneficiaries; this response acknowledges that there is an injustice to men, but maintains that it is of no practical consequence, for men are owed no recompense. 1. natural or Social? we might start by questioning van Parijs’ causal claims. are the differences between men and women that lead to men’s higher rates of violent crime really genetic, as he suggests? isn’t it plausible that some of these behavioral differences are due in part to social or environmental influences? Plausibly, even if genet ic dif ferences a re present, cer ta in socia li zat ion pract ices exacerbate their effects: if young boys are encouraged or indulged more when they display aggression, or if they are indulged more in losses of temper because gender norms make us more tolerant of male anger than female anger, these trends might help explain men’s greater criminality. even if they do, this does not dispel van Parijs’ puzzle. if rawls was right that social and natural contingencies are “equally arbitrary” from a moral point of view (1971/1999, p. 64), then social contingencies justify inequalities no more than natural contingencies. if we have reason of justice to mitigate unearned disadvantage, those reasons apply no less to the disadvantage that results from socialization than the disadvantage due to genes. even if social and natural contingencies are equally morally arbitrary in t he sense t hat t he person whom t hey disadva ntage is equa l ly non- responsible for t hem, however, socia l cont ingencies at least seem to be within society’s control. Because society appears responsible for creating it, socially-caused disadvantage might be thought more urgently to call for remediation. i find this implausible. Suppose there really is a fact of the matter about the extent to which the causes of any particular disadvantage a re socia l or natura l. St i l l, socia l ly-caused disadva ntage need not, in principle, be more a menable to cha nge by col lect ive act ion, eit her by mitigating the disadvantage or by mitigating the social differences that 139 Gina Schouten LEAP 3 (2015) cause it. neither genes nor their justice-relevant effects are immutable. in a paper on educational justice, christopher Jencks asks us to consider two deaf children: one child’s deafness is due to an environmentally-caused early childhood disease; the other child’s deafness is due to a genetic defect. according to Jencks, “the fact that one child’s deafness was a product of heredity while the other child’s deafness was environmental in origin tells us nothing about the physical character of the problem or the likelihood that it has a medical remedy” (1988: 523).this point about immutabilit y increasingly applies to the source of disadvantage as well, as social sources of disadvantage become increasingly complex and gene therapy becomes increasingly sophisticated. whatever the source of men’s greater aggression, it could be addressed through collective social action—either by efforts to change socialization patterns, by existing gene selection and therapy, or by developing new technologies for genetic modification (casal 2013, 2015, 2016; rainier 2013). But t his is a l l la rgely beside t he point. if men’s g reater li keli hood of criminality is due to social inf luences contrary to what van Parijs claims, and if social inequalities do more urgently call for remediation contrary to what i have cla imed, t hen we have on ly st reng t hened t he g rounds for t hin k ing t here is injust ice here. But if va n Pa rijs is right to rega rd t he difference as genetic, then we’re back to the puzzle we began with: is it not unjust that genetic make-up renders men likelier than women to engage in violent behavior, thereby rendering them more susceptible to the harms of incarceration? whatever configuration of social and natural causes are at work, they presumably make males likelier to be incarcerated because they make it more difficult for males than for females to avoid the kinds of behaviors that lead to incarceration. if so, then the inf luence of unchosen genetic or social endowment on males’ prospects for incarceration seems to be the sort of starting gate disadvantage that justice condemns. 2. harM to otherS? violent crime is deeply harmful. it harms v ictims, and its harms extend beyond its immediate victims; for example, it inf licts opportunity costs in the form of public resources spent on prosecution and incarceration rather than other socially valuable projects. can we dispel the puzzle van Parijs’ question raises by arguing that the serious and pervasive harms that crime inf licts tel l aga inst men’s g reater li keli hood of inca rcerat ion being a n injustice to them? is it a plausible condition for an ex ante inequality in life prospects to constitute an injustice that those on the losing end not harm others in accruing the deficit they were ex ante likelier to accrue? no. Just Are Unequal Incarceration Rates Unjust to Men? 140 LEAP 3 (2015) as men are disproportionally likely to be incarcerated relative to women, the least advantaged are disproportionally likely to be incarcerated relative to the more advantaged. this elevated likelihood of incarceration is plausibly one dimension of the injustice suffered by those who grow up poor through no fault of their own, and this would be true even if the effects of poverty on incarceration were mediated entirely by actual criminality—that is, even if poverty did not elevate one’s likelihood of incarceration beyond the extent to which it elevates one’s likelihood of committing a crime. Similarly, the effects of hormones on men’s high likelihood of incarceration are mediated by their criminality—by their harming others. But to be consistent, we must regard their unequal propensity to criminality as no less unjust on that count. this is true even if, plausibly, men’s criminality and the criminality of those born into disadvantaged circumstances disproportionally victimize those who are already unjustly badly off themselves. 3. Free choice? Genetic and hormonal differences may render men likelier than women to engage in certain behaviors, but whether or not any of us in fact engages in t hose behav iors is, at t he end of t he day, up to us. va n Pa r ijs read i ly acknowledges that “the role played by free will in the causal process is by no means irrelevant” (86), and clarifies that his drawing attention to the role of genetics is meant in no way to exonerate men for their violent crimes. how, then, is men’s greater propensity to violence an injustice, if we acknowledge that choice plays a role in determining whether any particular man acts on this propensit y? if we are right to hold indiv iduals accountable for the choices t hey ma ke, even when factors beyond t heir cont rol a f fect t heir likelihood of making those choices, why should we think that men suffer injustice due to the genetic endowments that make them, on average, likelier to be violent? consider the income inequality between women and men. Some of the inequality is due to outright sexism, and some to implicit biases or statistical discrimination that render women less likely to be hired and promoted whether or not they are or will become caregiving specialists, simply because they are statistically more likely to be caregiving specialists. another cause of income inequality is unequal uptake of unpaid caregiving labor between men a nd women. women ta ke more t ime of f for ca reg iv ing a nd more frequently work part-time so that they can perform caregiving. Full time working women have more caregiving constraints on their availability for overtime work or travel and are likelier to be on call for caregiving emergencies. they are also likelier to develop career aspirations in light of anticipating 141 Gina Schouten LEAP 3 (2015) that they will be the caregiving specialist within their families; they are thus likelier to choose the relatively flexible (and less socially valued) careers that will enable them to prioritize caregiving. Some might think that if men’s higher incomes are due to sexist bosses, that’s unjust; but if the inequality is due to women’s occupational or work- life balance choices, it is not unjust. this is a mistake. women do indeed choose how to divide their time and energy, but they do not choose against a background of equality. Due to genes or socialization or both, women are likelier than men to subordinate the demands of paid labor to the demands of caregiving. relative to men, women’s options about how to allocate time a nd energ y come w it h dif ferent const ra ints a nd payof fs. to ma ke t he counter-gender-typical choice of prioritizing paid labor, the average woman will have to overcome either ingrained social norms or a natural predisposition to prioritize others’ needs for care, or both; and she will have to pay the costs of violating social norms that cast women as “cold” or “hard” for prioritizing paid labor and as “bitchy” or “domineering” for success in paid labor, which success itself will have to be won in a competition the terms of which largely favor men. So while women do indeed choose which careers to pursue and how to prioritize those careers against other life projects, we nonetheless rightly object to the terms of that choice: women who choose less esteemed and less well–remunerated positions face higher costs than men for choosing more esteemed and better remunerated alternatives. women who choose to shoulder more than their share of the caregiving load do so against a context that makes it costlier for them than for their male partners to resist doing so.5,6 clearly, there are important differences between women’s choices to prioritize the needs of dependents over paid labor and men’s engagement in violent crime. My point is not to claim that they are analogous, but to make one very specific comparison: Both involve choice. considerations of justice must be responsibilit y-sensitive, and so the role of choice is not 5 one might think that diagnosing this social context of choice as unjust requires a welfarist metric of justice. i deny this, and in fact think it would be a mistake to invoke such a metric. i offer an account of the injustice of the gendered division of labor—an account that does not rely on a welfarist metric—in Schouten (forthcoming). nor does the case for regarding the gendered division of labor as unjust rely on assuming that men and women have different preferences; rather, the arrangement of institutions that makes transgressing gender norms so costly is unjust. 6 one might point out that the unfair terms of choice are due to men’s intransigence. i do not t hin k t his is releva nt for t he point i a m ma k ing here, which is about whet her t he consequences of choice can be unjust to the chooser if the terms of the choice are unfair through no fault of the chooser. i do not think that others’ culpability bears on that question, though it is certainly relevant to others. Moreover, i do not think that the unfairness of terms is due primarily to men’s intransigence, as will become clear below. Are Unequal Incarceration Rates Unjust to Men? 142 LEAP 3 (2015) insignificant. But in both cases, the inequalities in the background against which the relevant choice is made are not chosen; and in both cases, the relevant choice is harmful to the chooser. women are worse off in many doma ins by v ir tue of ma k ing gender-norm-complia nt labor a l locat ion choices (as well as by the norms themselves, whether or not the women comply with them), and these harms have long been a concern of theorists of justice. Men are made worse off by virtue of committing violent crimes that result in their disproportionate incarceration. through no fault of t heir ow n, women a re ex ante li kelier to be worse of f in v ir tue of t heir greater likelihood to prioritize the needs of dependents over their careers. through no fault of their ow n, men are ex ante likelier to be worse off in virtue of their greater like lihood to engage in violent behavior. Perhaps the unequal propensities in the two cases are due to different configurations of social and natural causes. But if we are committed to neutralizing the inf luence on our life prospects of circumstances beyond our control, then this difference is irrelevant to our deeming it unjust that unchosen contingencies impact on life prospects in these ways. Men should not be exculpated merely on the basis of their ex ante elevated likelihood of criminality any more than women’s gender-compliant choices should be disparaged as not genuine choices. For the purpose of theorizing justice, we want to be able to hold agents responsible for the choices they make even when alternative courses are very costly; thus, we must attribute to individuals the capacity to make costly choices. this capacity is the basis on which we hold perpetrators responsible for their crimes and respect women’s gender-compliant choices. But in neither case does the role of choice exempt the backdrop against which choices are made from criticism on the grounds of justice. Just as the norms and institutions that make gender egalitarianism so costly may be unjust, so too it might be unjust that social structures permit men’s unchosen genetic endowment so heavily to impact their likelihood of incarceration. we have seen that the effects of natural contingencies are not categorically immutable. if the incarceration effects of male hormones are not immutable—and i shall tentatively suggest in concluding that they are not—then the element of choice in criminal behavior does not exempt society from an obligation to intervene to lessen the likelihood of the harm: in the case of incarceration, by expending social resources to make violent crime less common.7 7 i have not argued positively that society does have such an obligation; rather, i have argued more modestly that the role of choice would not lessen or undermine it if we did. Moreover, social resources are scarce, and the question of how to prioritize remediation of the various injustices we confront is complicated. even if we do have the obligation i consider here, it may be that in our non-ideal circumstances other obligations of justice must take priority. 143 Gina Schouten LEAP 3 (2015) 4. an inJuStice overriDDen? Suppose there is some injustice in men’s higher likelihood of incarceration. Still, we might think that, given the very many ways in which women are disadvantaged relative to men, that injustice is simply overridden by the many gendered harms to women of which men are beneficiaries. indeed, some of the ver y features that plausibly help explain men’s greater likelihood of incarceration also have disadvantageous consequences for women: Men are, on average, physically larger and stronger than women and so likelier to be successful when they undertake to commit a violent crime; this physical strength and stature might be a disservice to the men who are incarcerated for the crimes they successfully carry out, but those traits are much more pervasively a threat to women. of course, even if men are all-things-considered advantaged such that t hey a re owed no recompense i n v i r t ue of t hei r h ig her l i kel i hood of incarceration, that disadvantage might still matter. if the various constituents of good lives are commensurable such that gains in one domain can make up for losses in others, any justice-relevant disadvantage men suffer might simply diminish the compensation owed to women on account of gender injustice favoring men. But it is not obvious that the putative disadvantage to men would be relevant merely for lessening the compensation owed to women. Many ca ndidate goods of just ice —work, income, a nd leisure —appea r to be commensurable in this way. But it is not always true that being advantaged in one way can compensate for being disadvantaged in another—that if the quantities and severities match up correctly, there is no injustice all things considered. Some goods are not commensurable. certain health def icits t hat involve chronic pa in plausibly ca nnot be out weighed by surpluses of other goods like income and wealth, or even by surpluses of goods that we regard, like health, as intrinsic constituents of wellbeing— intellectual stimulation, for example. Similarly, it may be that men’s greater likelihood of committing v iolent crime is a disadvantage that cannot be compensated for by other goods, even goods in such important domains as those in which men appear to be favored, including social status and occupied positions of political power. none of this is meant to deny that the goods of which men enjoy unfairly large shares are ver y good goods; nor is it to deny that their large shares constitute an injustice. it is simply to point out that the impact on one’s life of certain kinds of bads cannot fully be remediated by a larger share of goods. Presumably, the harm of suffering physical assault is such a bad. we may regard the harms of incarceration as similarly un-compensable without thereby committing to men’s susceptibility Are Unequal Incarceration Rates Unjust to Men? 144 LEAP 3 (2015) to suffering them being a disadvantage comparable in severity to women’s vulnerability to assault. here we might be tempted to think that the badness of men’s greater incarceration is not best characterized as unjust. Maybe the world is somehow worse in virtue of this inequality, but justice is about the distribution of commensurables. if men’s higher li keli hood of crimina lit y ca nnot be outweighed by the very many advantages they have in virtue of being men, then it is not unjust. Justice cannot plausibly be restricted in this way, because such a restriction would also exclude paradigmatic cases of gender injustice. consider t he incommensurable harms of the gendered division of labor which account—at least in part—for our regarding it as unjust. imagine, counterfactually, that traditionally male and traditionally female work were esteemed and remunerated at comparable levels. Still, the persistence of social norms and institutions arranged in compliance with those norms could make gender-counter-typical choices very costly for both men and women. the costs of transgressing gender norms within institutions that affirm those norms can constitute justice- relevant harms, even if gender-norm-compliant alternatives resulted in equal distributions of commensurables between women and men. on this basis, i argue elsewhere that the gendered division of labor could remain unjust even if caregiving work were compensated and its status elevated such that esteem and remuneration accrued equally to traditionally male and traditionally female work (2016). But at the very least, it is coherent to cla i m t hat t he gendered d iv ision of labor cou ld be u njust despite a l l commensurable goods being fairly distributed. if so, then the concept of justice must extend beyond commensurables. the injustice of the gendered division of labor also shows that a justice- relevant, incommensurable disadvantage can remain justice-relevant when the disadvantaged group enjoys a surplus of different incommensurable goods. if we are to take seriously the insight that we presently fail to value caregiv ing in proportion to its true worth—both in terms of the public good that caregivers generate and in terms of the personal value of intimacy that caregiving enables—then we must accept that women are not the only parties harmed by the gendered div ision of labor. Just as many women would have been better off with more opportunities for stimulation and esteem in the world of paid work, many men would have been better off with more opportunities for the intimacy and fulfillment that caregiving 145 Gina Schouten LEAP 3 (2015) enables.8 women are harmed by their sub-optimal share of paid work, and men are harmed by a sub-optimal share of caregiving work. of course, these harms are not of equal magnitude for women and men. But suppose, again, that traditionally female work were remunerated and esteemed equally with traditionally male work. under these circumstances, the harms of a gendered division of labor could be equal in their extent and severity. Still, it would remain unjust that men and women are so thoroughly socialized in ways that make it very costly for them to attain what for so many of them is an important good, where the basis of this socialization is nothing more than (faulty) (institutionalized) assumptions about who is best suited to or equipped for different kinds of work. For those who would find fulfillment through non-caregiving work, a deficit in that domain cannot fully be compensated by larger allocations of commensurable goods or even by larger a l locat ions of other non-commensurable goods. For those who would find f u lf i l lment through caregiving, a deficit in that domain is similarly incommensurable. St i l l, none of this makes it incoherent to think of the gendered division of labor as a problem of justice. the gendered division of labor could remain unjust even if (counterfactually) it imposed only incommensurable harms, and even if (counterfactually) the harms accrued in equal magnitudes to men and women. Similarly, men’s greater likelihood of incarceration could be unjust despite the harms it inflicts being incommensurable, and it could remain unjust even though women suffer incommensurable harms of even greater magnitude. Because these (putative) injustices cannot fully be compensated by surpluses of other goods, to fully restore justice we must remove the ex ante inequality—by changing the gendered socialization patterns and institutional arrangements that sustain the gendered division of labor on the one hand; by removing or overcoming men’s genetic or social propensity for violence on the other. in other words, fully remediating these injustices requires reform of social institutions rather than straightforward redistribution of goods. in one sense, this is nothing new. even straightforward income and wealth inequalities might be best addressed not by giving more to those whose share is unfairly small, but rather by making careful and empirically-informed 8 it is tempting to think that if a dearth of caregiving really made men worse off, they would simply do more of it. But, first, even if their small share of caregiving work is simply due to t heir ow n intra nsigence, t hey might nonet heless be better of f doing more. Just as women’s socia lization (or genetic endow ment) a f fects t heir preferences a nd t he choices t hey ma ke, so too might men’s. Second, t here is ev idence t hat men increasingly do prefer gender ega l ita r ia n pa r t nersh ips a nd a la rger sha re of ca reg iv i ng work, but wor r y t hat “mounting job demands and a lack of caretaking supports” make egalitarianism not a viable option (Gerson 2010: 11). in other words, many of the same factors that make egalitarianism so costly for women—not intransigent partners but intransigent workplaces, for example— also make it costly for men. Are Unequal Incarceration Rates Unjust to Men? 146 LEAP 3 (2015) institutional changes to schools, zoning policies, or campaign finance regimes.9 the difference is that, when we are dealing with commensurables, redistributing goods can still, in principle, fully restore justice, albeit perhaps less efficiently. when the injustice involves incommensurables, redistributing goods is not only less efficient; it falls short of fully restoring justice. if incarceration inflicts incommensurable harms, then men’s greater likelihood of incarceration might call for redress despite the very many inequalities from which they benefit. 5. unJuSt But not urGent? Men’s many advantages do not render hormonal inequality irrelevant from t he perspect ive of just ice, but perhaps t heir adva ntages render it a less urgent injustice. Plausibly, hormonal differences that disadvantage men are less urgent than many of the inequalities that disadvantage women. Still, i question how far this can take us in resolving the cognitive dissonance van Parijs’ puzzle generates. the fact that men enjoy so many advantages in virtue of their gender may well depress the urgency of remedying the d i sadv a nt ageou s con sequences of hor mona l i nequa l it ies, but ot her considerations should figure into our calculations of urgency as well: how severe is the harm? how per vasive? how difficult is it to avoid? a re the advantages which its v ictims enjoy commensurable advantages? Judging from these questions, we can see that many injustices against women are exceedingly urgent problems of justice. we routinely fail to make women safe in public spaces from threat of v iolence and assault. the resulting harms are severe, pervasive, and exceedingly difficult for women to avoid. we should try to ease these harms, but their seeming incommensurability would make them impossible fully to remediate, which makes it urgent indeed to do what we can to avoid them in the first place. w here do the harms of men’s greater likelihood of incarceration fall along these metrics of urgency? they are presumably less urgent than the harm women disproportionally suffer in virtue of living under threat of violence, but neither can the inf luence of unchosen genetic endowment on men’s likelihood of imprisonment be dismissed as unimportant. i do not know how difficult it is for those with the genetic endowment in question to avoid criminality. But surely the harms of incarceration are severe and per vasive: the Bureau of Justice reports that, as of the year 2000, male violent offenders made up “about one violent offender for every nine males age ten or older” (Greenfeld and Snell 2000). if the harms of incarceration 9 this is not a claim that these issues no longer fall within the purview of distributive justice. the injustices might be distributive even if the ideal remedies are not redistribution. 147 Gina Schouten LEAP 3 (2015) are incommensurable, that would heighten the urgency of finding ways to avoid them. even if i am wrong about this assessment of urgency, moreover, relative non-urgency does not exempt us from responsibility to theorize and address injustices. the harms of the present day gendered division of labor are, on any plausible measurement, less urgent than the harms of institutionalized practices of female genital mutilation. But concern over the persistence of the latter has not prevented a great deal of attention to the former, and this is as it should be, assuming we can maintain perspective and allocate scarce resources and attention appropriately. on reflection, the unjust consequences of hormonal inequality seem relatively urgent; but even less urgent injustices merit attention. 6. what to Do? Men’s genetic or socialized propensity to aggression is a circumstance beyond t h e i r c ont r ol . we s h ou ld b e c om m it t e d , a s a m a t t e r of j u s t ic e , t o minimizing the effects of such circumstances on life prospects. this comes to us as puzzling, because we are accustomed to thinking of women as being victims of gender injustice. no doubt readers will have other ideas for how to d ispel t he pu z z le, or idea s for how more ef fect ively to execute t he resolutions i have considered. i welcome such ideas. Diagnosing sex-based unequal prospects for incarceration as unjust is counterintuitive, and i am open to the possibility that creative maneuvers to avoid this diagnosis can be made to work. But it seems to me that we must also ref lect on the status of the intuition being contradicted. at one extreme, we might treat it as a desideratum of a theory of justice that it not diagnose the unequal likelihood of incarceration between the sexes as unjust, or that it not do so when males comprise the disadvantaged group. this would too strongly privilege the intuition that men are not victims of injustice in van Parijs’ puzzle. a weaker way to privilege the intuition would be to treat it as a sufficiently reliable piece of data to justif y creative refinement of our theories of justice to accommodate it. at some point, though, the creativity of our maneuvers will come at the cost of the plausibility of the theories. if the intuition is so reliable, that cost might be worth bearing. But at some point, ingenious maneuvers become at best ad hoc and at worst implausible on their own terms. there are certainly options i have not considered, and some of them may impose no plausibility cost to the best theory of justice. But suppose not. what amount of “plausibility points” should we be willing to sacrifice in our theories of justice to preserve the intuition that unequal likelihood of incarceration is not unjust to men? i don’t know. But for two reasons, i think that it would Are Unequal Incarceration Rates Unjust to Men? 148 LEAP 3 (2015) not be the disaster we might at first have thought it to be if we had to admit that our intuition in this case is misguided. First, we have long known that certain gender inequalities harm men as well as women. Men have historically been discouraged from developing the kind of intimacy with their children that makes parenting so rewarding for some. t hey have been encou raged to rega rd pa id employ ment a s fundamentally important to their self-worth and role in society. there is no denying that men have been mal-formed under patriarchy in ways that constitute real harms to them, and acknowledging these harms as dimensions of gender injustice takes nothing away from the urgency of addressing harms suffered by women, who remain the prime victims of gender injustice. nor should acknowledging an injustice in incarceration prospects detract from our commitment to the diverse array of feminist goals that we’ve long recognized as morally urgent. Second, if our intuition that there is no injustice here turns out to be misguided, the practical upshots are not the unpalatable measures we may have feared but rather social policy measures that we already have independent reason to undertake. certainly we should work to ameliorate the harms of incarceration by making prisons safer, but this does not mean that we should decriminalize violence, exonerate its perpetrators, or lessen any of our efforts to better protect victims of violence. From the fact that a man’s propensity to violence is beyond his control, it does not follow that he should be exonerated for acting on that propensity. if they can be shown to be safe and effective, we might incorporate technological solutions to lower recidivism, for example offering male offenders drug or gene therapies to lessen aggressiveness.10and while it is a far less exotic proposal, i think we have reasons to be optimistic that education reform could lower men’s likelihood of incarceration.11 high quality early childhood education might better enable boys to manage and process anger. arts and enrichment programming throughout primary and secondary school might help them find healthy outlets for it. lengthening school days and school years could diminish students’ availability for gang activity, drug use, and other behaviors that raise the likelihood of subsequent criminality. this strategy could be especially effective among students, like boys from 10 For more on these possibilities, see Persson and Savulescu 2012, casal 2011, 2013, and 2015. 11 there are good reasons to worry about educational programs aimed at changing people’s propensities to engage in certa in behav iors. indeed, ma ny such ef forts ca n be inef fective a nd even oppressive (casa l 2016). But ev idence suggests t hat non-oppressive education initiatives can be effective in reducing criminality. For example, studies of early childhood educationa l inter ventions, like Perr y pre-school a nd t he abeceda ria n Project, show that test scores improved in the short term, but faded out quickly, while other benefits associated w it h t he inter ventions (including lack of involvement in t he crimina l justice system) persisted. See, e.g., heckman et al. (2010). See also Machin et al. 2010 and Deming 2011. 149 Gina Schouten LEAP 3 (2016) poor communities with high levels of unemployment, whose intersectional group membership further elevates their risk. Perhaps most importantly, education reform could mitigate the severe deprivation and hopelessness that often lead to criminality. well-educated students have more options for meaningful life pursuits, more developed capital to make those pursuits successful, and higher opportunity costs to criminality. For these reasons and others, we should work to diminish the extreme inequality in our society through education reform and other forms of social support. it might seem as though education reform could only make a difference if the problem had its root in social causes, but this impression is mistaken. Just as corrective lenses can improve poor vision whether it has environmental or natural causes, education could offset whatever environmental inf luences raise men’s likelihood of incarceration and lessen the likelihood that they will act on—or raise the likelihood that they w ill resist acting on—any natural predisposition toward criminality they happen to have. in short: whether men’s greater propensity to violent crime is due to genes or socialization or both, social solutions like education reform could help reduce their likelihood of acting on that propensity. Perhaps, if all this fails, we will have to accept that the problem, at present, cannot be ameliorated, or that it cannot be ameliorated without making the world more unjust overall than it is if we tolerate this disadvantage to men. if so, some might think that the disadvantage is therefore not unjust. i doubt that injustice is limited in this way, if only because restricting the concept based on what we are presently able to redress risks removing reasons to develop new mechanisms for redress. But even if the concept is rightly limited in that way, we should not accept the conclusion suggested without having made a good faith effort to deploy the kinds of social solutions conjectured here. i have suggested that they hold promise for reducing the inf luence of hormones on men’s criminality, and there is little reason to doubt that, if they can be made to do so, they could do so without imposing decisive costs to other pursuits of justice. it is indeed counterintuitive to think that men are victims of injustice because their genetic or social endowment makes them likelier to end up in prison. it might nonetheless be true. if so, then many of the social policies that could mitigate the injustice are policies about which we should have little reservation. indeed, many of them are long overdue. Are Unequal Incarceration Rates Unjust to Men? 150 LEAP 3 (2015) BiBlioGraPhy casal, P., 2011: “love not war. on the chemistry of Good and evil”, in Arguing about Justice: Essays for Philippe Van Parijs, ed. a. Gosseries and y. vanderborght,145- 157,louvain la neuve: louvain university Press. — 2013: “Sexual Dimorphism and human enhancement,” Journal of Medical Ethics 39: 772-8. — 2015: “on not taking Men as they are: reflections on Moral Bioenhancement,” Journal of Medical Ethics 41: 340-42. — 2015: “Distributive Justice and Female longevity,” Law, Ethics and Philosophy 3: 90-106 — 2016: “Distributive Justice and human nature,” in Oxford Handbook of Distributive Justice, ed. S. olsaretti, oxford: oxford university Press. Deming, D., 2011: “Better Schools, less crime?”The Quarterly Journal of Economics 126: 2063–2115. Gerson, K., 2010: The Unfinished Revolution, oxford: oxford university Press. Greenfeld, l. and Snell, t., 2000: u.S. Department of Justice, Bureau of Justice Statistics Special report on women offenders. http://www.bjs.gov/content/pub/pdf/wo.pdf heckman, J., Moon, S., Pinto, r., Savelyev, P.a.,yavitz, a.,2010: “the rate of return to the high/Scope Perr y Preschool Program,” Journal of Public Economics 94: 114–128. Jencks, c., 1988: “whom Must we treat equally for educational opportunity to Be equal?” Ethics 98: 518–33. Machin, S., Marie, o., and vuji, S., 2010: “the crime reducing effect of education,” the institute for the Study of labor Discussion Paper Series, iZa DP no. 5000. na acP cr i m i na l Just ice Fact Sheet, ht t p ://w w w.naacp.org/pages/cr i m i na l- justice-fact-sheet Persson, i., and Savulescu, J., 2012:Unfit for the Future: The Need for Moral Enhancement, oxford: oxford university Press. rainer, a., 2013: The Anatomy of Violence: The Biological Roots of Crime, new york: Pantheon Books. rawls, J., 1971/1999 : A Theor y of Justice, rev ised ed it ion, ca mbr idge : ha r va rd university Press. Schouten, G., forthcoming: “citizenship, reciprocity, and the Gendered Division of labor: a Stability argument for Gender egalitarian Political interventions,” Politics, Philosophy, and Economics. Pre-published September 4, 2015, Doi: 10.1177/1470594X15600830. — 2016: “is the Gendered Division of labor a Problem of Distribution?” in Oxford Studies in Political Philosophy, vol. 2., ed. D. Sobel, P. vallentyne, and S. wall, oxford: oxford university Press. van Parijs, P., 2015: “Four Puzzles on Gender equality,” Law, Ethics and Philosophy 3: 79-89. thornhill, r., and Palmer, c. t., 2000: A Natural History of Rape: Biological Bases of Sexual Coercion, cambridge, Ma and london: Mit Press). http://www.bjs.gov/content/pub/pdf/wo.pdf http://www.naacp.org/pages/criminal LEAP 3 (2015) The Rich also Cry1 AnA dE MiGuEL Universidad Rey Juan Carlos Abstract Philippe van Parijs (2015) reports a hostile reaction to some remarks he made suggesting that men’s stronger sexual drive disadvantages them compa red to women, in pa r t because it causes t hem to v isit brot hels, thereby incurring financial and reputational losses. this paper describes how satisfying sexual desire can be very cheap, or even free, and explains why the way a man’s reputation is affected by a greedier libido is not always significant or negative. More importantly, the paper tries to explain why van Parijs’ remarks were received with so much disapproval by feminists. Keywords: sexual exploitation, prostitution, human trafficking, harassment, feminism introDuction i have been asked to comment on a text by a philosopher i have never met called Philippe van Parijs. he tries to describe some possible advantages women have compared to men and comes up with these: women outlive the men they look after; women earn less but study more; women have less political representation but vote more; women are the victims of crime rather than the perpetrators; and women tend to be those whose body is sold, rather than the client or pimp (van Parijs 2015). wow, men must be really envious! he warns that he is speaking “tongue-in-cheek.” you don’t say! it would be really worrying if this was seriously all one could come up with. i hope he can appreciate other people’s sense of humor, for i work on prostitution and the alleged handicap i have been asked to discuss is men’s 1 i thank Paula casal for her help with the translation, the structure, and countless ex a mples (t h i rst, sea food, subord i nat ion fa nta sies, coet zee, su nscreen…). in fact, her contribution was so great, that i thought we should both sign the paper, but she declined. i am also grateful to Jesús Mora for his references and revisions, and to antonio García valdecasas for the title and other suggestions. Finally, i am very grateful to three anonymous referees for their criticisms and encouragement and to laura Sánchez de la Sierra and hannah weber for their thorough proofreading. 152 Ana De Miguel LEAP 3 (2015) greedier libido. van Parijs explains it thus: “Men’s greedier libido turns them into handicapped individuals, sometimes even super-handicapped à la Dominique Strauss-Kahn.” it causes them financial losses because they find themselves paying for prostitutes and, if caught, can also cause them reputational damage (86). i was myself really puzzled when i read, and then had to re-read, that he is now telling the world that this is what he actually prepared for a feminist, predominantly female audience at a major gender equality event (!). Predictably, the talk did not go down well. and he could have left it there. Philippa would have gone home wanting the earth to swallow her and quietly researched into where she went so horribly wrong until she understood. But not Philippe. two and a half years later he remains conv inced that the problem lay w ith the female audience. they misunderstood him. all of them. they must have. there can be no other explanation. So, he is repeating it all again, trying to reach an even larger audience, without changing even a comma. he seems to believe that the problem lay with these women’s poor mastery of english, the insufficient time they gave him, and their unfamiliarity with a philosopher’s job ( 79-80), for it could not have been what he said. absolutely not. having carefully read his piece, i think i know what happened. he was spea k ing to wel l-educated women, united to promote equa lit y in t he workplace, concerned with depressing gender facts, and they were outraged by their guest’s speech. they were outraged because they understood him and – what’s more unusual – they dared to say so. i will try to spell out why, despite the additional complication posed by va n Pa rijs’ a mbiva lence about whet her t he behav iors he describes as hormonal inequality are actually about socialization (16). if i understood correctly – in spite of my being a woman and a feminist with imperfect english – the problem he was drawing attention to is this: men’s libido has t he u n for t u nate ef fec t of c au si ng t hem to go w hor i ng , w h ich i s bad because of the expense and potential damage to their reputation. women are more fortunate in this respect, as they do not need to v isit brothels, and therefore do not waste money or risk reputational losses. he calls the whoring propensit y “a ha ndicap,” perhaps of fending t he disabled a nd women at once. his paradigmatic super-handicapped male is Strauss- Kahn, a thrice-married millionaire who, swept away by the force of his libido, damaged his public reputation with various affairs – well past the age of sixty, i would add. The Rich also Cry 153 LEAP 3 (2015) 1. the alleGeD hanDicaP l et us a ssu me t hat, because of t hei r hor mones, men wa ke up w it h a burning desire that prevents them from functioning in life. let us also g ra nt t hat such sensat ion rea l ly is li ke being ver y t hirst y, sta r v ing, or extremely cold, so that they truly cannot focus on other matters until they are relieved. ‘it must be a handicap!’ says Philippe the Philosopher. and he quickly closes his computer satisfied to have found yet another disadvantage he bets feminists have never before considered. however, let us suppose men have a plentiful and permanent supply of water, but love being thirsty. they like it so much that the moment their thirst subsides, they try to increase it with pills, pictures, videos, toys, or whatever works best for each of them. they do this in order to enjoy the thirst, and then the drink which they can always find – even if they could not, the pleasure derived from simple thirst would have made it worthwhile. after all, the market is full of stuff to increase this thirst and delay its satisfaction. it seems to me, then, that if men themselves are delighted w ith this ‘thirst-thing’ they possess and can easily relieve, there is no justification for telling women that they are not as far from equality as they would have thought otherwise. and the desire for sex is like this ‘thirst-thing’ for most men. they love having it, and so long as they are not handicapped in other ways, and so still have hands, relief is simple, instant, and gratis. this is the cartesian “clear and distinct” idea carol Pateman explains in the Sexual contract (1988), a w idely cited book van Parijs’ audience may well have read and discussed. Men prefer, of course, women pouring the drinks for them, but none dies for having to help himself (and nowadays we know it does not cause blindness either). you can, by contrast, die working as a prostitute. even if nobody attacks you, it is a largely nocturnal life of risks, drinking, drugs, driving, disease, and weirdos. this is my field of research: a heart-breaking world of rows of naked or half-naked women freezing in parks at night, or roasting in plastic chairs on the side of busy roads, with just a bottle of water to wash themselves between clients. it is a sinister world of women in glass windows in red light districts and industrial parks: “24 hours, all services,” “asian, very young, submissive,” “sluts, totally shaved, do what you want with us.” w hat was Philippe the Philosopher thinking, when he persuaded himself that conjuring these images in the minds of the concerned feminists was going to make them appreciate the disadvantages suffered by...men, and in particular one man, Strauss-Kahn? what were the chances of that audience ever thinking of this horrendous, ever-growing meat market as a massive charity operation to assist the poor men with their handicap? 154 Ana De Miguel LEAP 3 (2015) it is strange to describe as a handicap a disposition that is catered to and celebrated both by those who possess it and their broader culture. consider, for instance, the protagonist of coetzee’s Disgrace (2000) or Freud’s discussion of the greater male libido as a sign of male superiorit y and the primar y cause of greater creativity and inventiveness in men (1923). it is also very strange to say that somebody is to some degree disabled in an injustice- involv ing sense merely because they have, or are more likely to have, a preference. the same is true if the preference is a passion, for instance, for the sea or the snow, that might kill you in some circumstances. the word ‘handicap’ suggests something stronger than the frustration of a mere preference, t he ex istence of a n u n met need. But what k i nd of need, preference, or handicap are we really talking about? Does it involve the need for quick relief that can easily be obtained manually? no, it cannot be so simple or the whole sex industry would be redundant. is it a desire to see a woman dow n there, on her knees, naked and obey ing? or the w ish to humiliate her, to call her a ‘slut’, and to make her say that she wants you, when you know it is not true? is it a desire to see women as nymphomaniac school girls, raunchy nurses, or interviewees who would otherwise not get the jobs (three of men’s classic favorites)? or is it the need to show who is boss and prove that ‘women are whores’ who will do anything you say for money? research shows that most men know that many of the girls they use are not self-employed but parts of net works of exploitation and trafficking (raymond 2003). Many of them, we hear in the news, have been sold by their families, while others are captured by experts in supply and demand and in identifying girls from broken homes, prone to substance abuse or low self- esteem, who are more easily captured.2 in any case, the majority of them come from the most sex ist and unstructured countries, from poor and dysfunctional backgrounds, and cultures where a girl is worth nothing. we all know about this. But when entering a brothel and seeing the “asian, very young” or “sexy caribbean, barely 18,” do ‘the handicapped’ step back in shock? Do they make any inquiries? “Hey, I am handicapped, I hope you are not handicapped too and can help me. Are you here of your own free will? Could you leave anytime? Are you really this desperate for money? Are you really 18? Where is your family? ” the handicap must be an extreme form of selfishness and indifference, for the handicapped customer asks nothing. in fact, he wants not to know: he is interested only in his handicap and in whether you have the body to relieve it. and so, an audience of women already concerned by the suffering 2 the Daily Mail, 2014. http://www.dailymail.co.uk/news/article-3300016/human- traffickers-preying-refugees-europe-forcing-slave-labour-child-prostitution-warn-europol.html http://www.dailymail.co.uk/news/article-3300016/Human-traffickers-preying-refugees-Europe-forcing-slave-labour-child-prostitution-warn-Europol.html http://www.dailymail.co.uk/news/article-3300016/Human-traffickers-preying-refugees-Europe-forcing-slave-labour-child-prostitution-warn-Europol.html The Rich also Cry 155 LEAP 3 (2015) caused by men’s selfish focus on their itch had to listen to the Philosopher blanketing out all else, claiming ignorance and telling them to focus on this matter of such great importance. as if they themselves had not had many occasions to hear men going on about it, demanding pity and relief. Feminists know full well how manipulative, rhetorical, and persistent men can be about the importance of relieving their itch. “oh, i suffer so much! if you love me, you w ill make me happy (w ithout thinking about pregnancy or venereal disease).” even if they had not read it in feminist texts, they would have heard the male ‘pity me’ countless times directed at them. one wonders if the Philosopher knew this when he told the women they were to pity men. 2. the alleGeD coStlineSS the Philosopher observes that the man must pay (van Parijs 2015: 16), as an added disadvantage, just in case this escapes us or seems unimportant in view of men’s higher average income. it is true, you are supposed to pay. in Madrid or Barcelona you can pay 5€ for a blowjob performed by black girls with really good prices, plus those very special mouths, so perfect for the task.3 For 10€ more, you can then penetrate one of those skinny asians in the park, a car, or some back street. For 30€ you can have a half an hour with a breast-enhanced latina in a room in central Gran vía. and now there are also ‘low-cost’ brothels, brothels with “refund if unsatisfied” policies, and even brothels with loyalty cards where you can “enjoy and forget,” as they say in the ads.4 Driving along the Spanish east coast, you can find anything at really good prices: alleged sado-masochists, exotic girls with unusual bending or swallowing abilities, group acts, the lot. i am just reading the current menu to van Parijs, since he seems unaware of the fact that whoring is rather inexpensive. it is cheaper than seafood, for example, or watching the local fallas, and presumably the Philosopher does not count seafood or firework lovers as handicapped too. But perhaps he has in mind the exclusive services that arrange for you to have sex with top models, news readers, and top university students struggling with their fees,5 assuring the ‘handicapped’ that there is no woman they cannot buy. after all, the paradigmatic super-handicapped is the economics professor, minister, and iMF Managing Director, Strauss-Kahn, and these high-f liers sometimes spend exorbitant sums on their handicap (or get 3 Que, 2013: http://www.que.es/ultimas-noticias/sociedad/201310250800- prostitucion-nigerianas-recien-llegadas-cinco-cont.html 4 See aPr aMP: http://apramp.org 5 the Gua rdia n, 2015: http://w w w.t heg ua rdia n.com/education/2015/ma r/27/ universit y-students-sex-work-liv ing-costs-tuition-fee-debts http://www.que.es/ultimas-noticias/sociedad/201310250800-prostitucion-nigerianas-recien-llegadas-cinco-cont.html http://www.que.es/ultimas-noticias/sociedad/201310250800-prostitucion-nigerianas-recien-llegadas-cinco-cont.html http://apramp.org http://www.theguardian.com/education/2015/mar/27/university http://www.theguardian.com/education/2015/mar/27/university 156 Ana De Miguel LEAP 3 (2015) funding from tax payers). But how could the Philosopher pick this man as the paradigmatic victim of any specific form of injustice? Strauss-Kahn did not lose his reputation in a brothel or a party with prostitutes. he made it to the front pages as somebody accustomed to “getting away with murder” who decided to grab his chambermaid and try to rape her.6 at the time, he was with his third beautiful wife, heir of a millionaire, but hey, the male itch is so important, how could a maid refuse to cooperate in its relief? he was later accused of further rapes and involvement with a pimp network.7 the super-handicapped and self-proclaimed libertine – super-handicapped and proud8 – soon acquired a new girlfriend, and his business continued to boom until his customers accused him of fraud in october 2015.9 and yet, as i write, Strauss-Khan is not in jail, or alone, or abandoned. Surely, while having a girlfriend, he finds time to frolic with the “very young asian,” “submissive black beauty,” “operated Brazilian,” and “all-waxed russian” that are routinely trapped in prostitution rings organized to relieve the all-important itch at all prices for men of all classes. 3. the alleGeD rePutational loSS the Philosopher, i am reliably informed, is a nice guy who honestly just wants to understand things, and so might reply: “i didn’t realize buying the services of prostitutes is so cheap, and perhaps i was mistaken about Strauss- Kahn too. But what about the others?” Perhaps there are some men who buy sex only from self-employed, mature prostitutes, and take the trouble to ensure they are not prostitutes in part because they have been abused, are mentally ill, addicted, or need to support a sick child. But who are these people who unfairly suffer a reputational loss in such circumstances? the greater understanding for the specifically male handicap that the Philosopher tries to promote gives the Berlusconis of this world a great sense of impunity. their endearing “weakness for the girls” is said to make them “more human” ( walston 2010). they know they w ill not lose their reputation for doing what they want. it is after all a “handicap,” and a sort of need-based claim. Bill clinton did not think that being the most powerful man on earth as President of the united States came with the responsibility to behave himself 6 The Guardian, 2012: http://w w w.theguardian.com/world/2012/dec/10/ dominique-strauss-kahn-case-settled 7 Sott, 2015: https://www.sott.net/article/292198-Dominique-Strauss-Kahns-pimping-trial-starts 8 Fra nce 24, 2015: http://w w w.f ra nce24.com/ en/20150210-liber t ine-st rauss-ka hn-adm its-org ies-denies-prost it utes 9 BBc, 2015: http://w w w.bbc.com/news/world-europe-34549950 http://www.theguardian.com/world/2012/dec/10/dominique http://www.theguardian.com/world/2012/dec/10/dominique https://www.sott.net/article/292198 http://www.france24.com/en/20150210 http://www.france24.com/en/20150210 http://www.bbc.com/news/world The Rich also Cry 157 LEAP 3 (2015) at least until the end of his term in office. no, with so many centuries of the ideological compassion for the male weakness, he felt untouchable or at least less liable to indignation and sanction. Maybe he even felt entitled, and claimed that sex with the young intern was “consensual.” i am just a teacher, and a woman, but would not think that sex in my office with one of my students could count as consensual. Monica lew inski’s reputation (and much of her life) was ruined, of course.10 But what happened to Bill? he remained married and President, and the world remembers him as one of the best contemporary Presidents, and a rather nice guy. 4. the alleGeD lacK oF unDerStanDinG Perhaps the Philosopher would judge Franco’s Spain superior to Zapatero’s in one respect. there was such understanding for the male handicap that it was normal for the Señor of the house to have access to the maid’s young body with neither the maid, nor the wife, having any say about it. “Men have to throw a grey hair in the wind” was the catch phrase (meaning: “copulate w ith somebody besides the w ife”). until 1963, a womanizing man could even kill his wife for adultery and be acquitted. why? Because men have a weakness women lack.11 Given the Philosopher’s insistence on the need to abstract from all else, he may also want to focus on the unique way in which society accommodates for the male itch at war: at home, the soldiers’ prerogative is to leave a trail of pregnant girls behind, and while away, occupying armies are more readily permitted to ‘whore around’ than to read in the local library. occupying armies are so understanding of the male need that soldiers can rape with impunity just about anyone.12 the poor soldier forced into so much discipline has to let off steam somehow, right? van Parijs condemns such actions, of course, but he seems to believe he is the first one to suggest the men are to be pitied for their weakness when in fact there is no novelty in this: this is the rancid ideology that has been oppressing humanity for centuries. he may say he does not mean his words to excuse such behaviors, but the fact is that his message has been used in this way for far too long. he cannot reasonably be surprised that feminists did not appreciate that his contribution to their empowering meeting was a disempowering message: “the handicap we ought to pit y” is just too similar to the discourse fed to us ad nauseam which has done so much damage and we have to fight. 10 teD, 2015: http://w w w.ted.com/talks/monica_lewinsky_the_price_of_shame 11 aBc, 2010: http://www.abc.es/20100915/internacional/adulteras-espana-201009151646.html 12 independent, 2014: http://www.independent.co.uk/news/world/middle-east/no- justice-in-sight-for-iraqi-victims-of-alleged-murder-rape-and-torture-9849305.html http://www.ted.com/talks/monica_lewinsky_the_price_of_shame http://www.abc.es/20100915/internacional/adulteras-espana-201009151646.html http://www.independent.co.uk/news/world/middle-east/no-justice-in-sight-for-iraqi-victims-of-alleged-murder-rape-and-torture-9849305.html http://www.independent.co.uk/news/world/middle-east/no-justice-in-sight-for-iraqi-victims-of-alleged-murder-rape-and-torture-9849305.html 158 Ana De Miguel LEAP 3 (2015) For what made Strauss-Kahn assault the maid is not a handicap or a need, but a product of overindulgence in the male itch. the ideolog y of calling it “a handicap” misdirects attention and empathy away from the maid, and towards Strauss-Kahn’s desires. By reproducing it, the Philosopher is maintaining a discourse according to which, although men are already richer and more powerful, women must have some understanding and pity for the distinctively male “weakness.” although they would have applauded loudly, Strauss-Kahn, Berlusconi, and Franco do not need this message, so van Parijs instead delivers it to a feminist audience. But these are people devoted to ending precisely that ideology, people who encourage poor women to stand firm and tell their husbands to stop talking about his needs when they cannot even feed their existing children. Feminists tell women to stand up a nd show no mercy in denouncing men who rape or ha rass t hem.13 Feminists tell women not to listen to his veiled threats of leaving her for somebody more accommodating to his whims. Feminists tell women not to risk hiv because a man tells them that he suffers. Feminists are people like Pateman, who tell women not to be afraid to say “why do i have to use my mouth when you have two able hands” (Pateman 1988: 172)? Feminists, then, are not people reluctant to voice, or hear, challenging views. But they are people who would not have invited a speaker, philosopher or not, to repeat an old myth that women have worked long and hard to combat. 5. the alleGeD claSS anD GenDer SiMilarity Philippa would have thought that having accepted such an invitation, she ought to engage in some research. But not Philippe. with the confidence society imbues so many men, Philippe thought he could quickly improvise something, thinking of four possible advantages for women and perhaps some comparisons bet ween class and gender should suffice. and off he goes. and like so many men before him, but perhaps never to such a large audience of gender-aware listeners, repeatedly displays the androcentric understanding of class that feminists have so often criticized. For he writes, “people who grew up in poor families (...) are disproportionately in prison (van Parijs 2015: 87).” no, Philippe, it is “prisons and brothels,” for not everybody responds to povert y in the same way. Depending on sex, race, and age, people face different risks: for some the risk is gang warfare or crime, for others it is, or also includes, teenage pregnancy, single motherhood, the sex industry, Stis, and encounters with Strauss-Kahn. the main cause of death for women aged 18 to 40 is gender violence (un women 2015). and 13 even Barak obama had to speak against the view of rape as an inevitable part of life on uS campuses (w hite house, 2014). The Rich also Cry 159 LEAP 3 (2015) even if a poor, black man’s chance of imprisonment was higher, anybody prefers a higher chance of committing a crime and a lower chance of being the victim, because the victim does not have a choice. only for the rapist, not for the raped, is it enough to say “no.” the Philosopher then makes us search into our conscience w ith the phrase: “especially if we happen to enjoy a more privileged background” (van Parijs 2015: 87), assuming, once again, before so many gender-conscious women an androcentric view. Perhaps his female listeners were middle-class, but that would not have saved them from a violent or oversexed father, an important portion would have been raped,14 and tending to be pioneers in the workplace, most would have been harassed or threatened at some point (Fine 2010: 87). Knowing this, is it appropriate for a man to go to this female- empowerment meeting to attempt a sympathetic look at the men who can pick a poor, naked, maybe terrified girl, and use her for their pleasure? and why stop there and not include testosterone-filled tyrants, sadistic torturers, hangmen, and nazi officials, who were all also overwhelmingly male? loS ricoS taMBiÉn lloran nobody, and certainly not Philippa, would go to a meeting in a South- african shantytown and attempt to move people with stories about privileged white lives, perhaps expressing frustration about servants’ unreliability and showing how the rich can also cry. one could imagine the reaction on hearing about the puzzle arising from their need for more expensive sunscreen to avoid skin cancer. and why not go to a disability conference to talk about the four downsides of being able-bodied? Maybe van Parijs would think that doing so is fine, because philosophers are licensed to focus on whatever they find interesting, blanketing out all else. But such things do not normally happen. it is usually women that have to put up with good philosophers coming to talk to them about gender and telling them the first thing that comes to mind. Philippa would have not dared to do such a thing. But Philippe may tell himself that the cold reception for his speech was not due to its being inappropriate or ill-researched, but due to some uncomfortable truth he alone unearthed. it is more likely, however, that there was little in it the feminists did not already know, and much the speaker should have known. at t he meet i ng, t he women were concer ned w it h d iscr i m i nat ion, exploitation, and power and sex abuse in the workplace. in this context, van Parijs’ idea of comparing the scores of men and women must have 14 in the uK, for instance, one in five women report having been victims of sexual offences since the age of sixteen (Ministry of Justice 2013: 6). 160 Ana De Miguel LEAP 3 (2015) seemed rat her juveni le to t hem. they were t here to incite men to help create a cooperat ive a nd fema le-f riend ly work env ironment. in such a context, creating some petty competition (Men: 4, women: 0) is unlikely to be of a ny help. Simone de Beauvoir (1966 : 28) la mented t he way men attempted to turn the female struggle for justice into a trivial diatribe, and perhaps this is just how these feminists felt. and, no, men do not have to be eliminated, but the world would be a better place without patriarchal men. BiBlioGraPhy archive of prostitution advertisement of aPr aMP, http://www.apramp.org De Beauvoir, S., 1966: Le deuxième sexe, les faits et les mythes, Paris: Gallimard. coetzee, J.M., 2000: Disgrace, new york: Penguin Books. Fine, c., 2010: Delusions of Gender, new york: icon Books. Freud, S., 192 3 : D a s Ich und d a s E s, v ien na-l eipz ig-Zu r ich : i nter nat iona ler Psychoanalytischer verlag. Ministr y of Justice, uK home off ice & t he off ice for nationa l Statistics https://w w w.gov.uk/government/uploads/system/uploads/attachment _ data/f ile/214970/sexua l-offending-over v iew-jan-2013.pdf Pateman, c., 1988: The Sexual Contract, oxford: Polity. ray mond, J., 2003: “ten reasons for not lega li zing Prost it ut ion a nd a lega l response to the Demand for Prostitution,” Journal of Trauma Practice 2: 315-332. un women, http://w w w.unwomen.org/en/what-we-do/ending-violence-against- women/facts-and-figures van Parijs, P., 2015: “Four Puzzles on Gender inequality”, leaP 3. wa lston, J., 2010, “w hy Silv io Berlusconi is still standing,” The Daily Telegraph, http://w w w.telegraph.co.uk/news/worldnews/europe/ita ly/8114902/w hy- Silv io-Berlusconi-is-still-standing.html www.apramp.org https://www.gov.uk/government/uploads/system/uploads/attachment_data/file/214970/sexual-offending-overview-jan-2013.pdf https://www.gov.uk/government/uploads/system/uploads/attachment_data/file/214970/sexual-offending-overview-jan-2013.pdf http://www.unwomen.org/en/what-we-do/ending-violence-against-women/facts http://www.unwomen.org/en/what-we-do/ending-violence-against-women/facts http://www.telegraph.co.uk/news/worldnews/europe/italy/8114902/Why-Silvio-Berlusconi-is-still-standing.html http://www.telegraph.co.uk/news/worldnews/europe/italy/8114902/Why-Silvio-Berlusconi-is-still-standing.html LEAP 3 (2015) Real Freedom for all Women (and Men): A Reply PHiLiPPE vAn PARijS Université Catholique de Louvain Abstract the disadvantages men suffer relative to women in certain dimensions are not always as significant as they seem. and even when they are real, they are not necessarily unjust. this reply to a set of six reactions to “Four Puzzles on Gender inequality” offers a critical discussion of these claims. above all, it questions the very idea of discussing issues of gender and justice in terms of “gender justice,” i.e., of justice between two categories of human beings. Keywords: gender equality, longevity, education, political representation, social justice introDuction yes, my short speech on gender inequalities is what i think most of my commentators understood it to be: a modest invitation to help us better understand the demands of so-called gender justice and of justice more generally, by reflecting on some puzzles, none of them new but some of them sticky.1 ana de Miguel’s superbly formulated and entertaining commentary was most useful in helping me see better why my initial speech could be misunderstood, even with the explanatory notes i subsequently added.2 i never read any masculinist pamphlet and do not intend to do so. But i can now imagine that some of what i said could have been reminiscent of some of what can be found in such w ritings and thereby suggest that i may be supporting their cause. ana de Miguel can rest reassured. i do not believe, 1 in addition to the authors of the six comments included in this volume, i am most grateful to Sophie heine, Meira levinson, anja topolski, and the participants in the lovanium Seminar in ethics and Public Policy (leuven, 21 november 2014) and the nuffield Political Philosophy seminar (oxford, 1 June 2015) for the sort of comments i was hoping to trigger – and be enlightened by. 2 Perhaps contrary to her expectation, i particularly enjoyed de Miguel’s contribution. i hope she enjoyed writing it at least as much as i enjoyed reading it – and more than i did trying to reply to it. 162 Philippe Van Parijs LEAP 3 (2015) and never claimed, that it is high time we should start pitying the male gender, let alone that justice demands that it should be compensated for its many “weaknesses.” as a male member of a well-off segment of a wealthy society, i am only too aware of the privileges i enjoy, not only nor mainly by virtue of being a man, but definitely partly by virtue of being a man.3 thus, the aim was not pro-male advocacy but philosophical clarification, and the point of departure, as so often for us philosophers, was a set of genuine puzzles, the nature of which is well captured by Paula casal (2015: 90-106) in the case of longevity. She is sure, she writes, “that if a random mutation resulted in women starting to die far ahead of men many of those who currently find van Parijs’s suggestion [that men’s shorter life expectancy may be unjust] absurd would start listing lesser longev it y as one of the disadvantages women suffer” (90-106). if this is the case, and holds more genera l ly for at least some of t he ot her inequa lit ies i listed, does it not follow that they should count, albeit prima facie and pro tanto, as injustices against men? this is, at any rate, the upshot of Gina Schouten’s careful discussion of differential incarceration: “i tentatively conclude that men’s higher likelihood of incarceration is a distinct injustice to men” (3). Schouten usef u l ly d ist i ng u ishes t wo ways of accom modat i ng t h is ack nowledgment. if one is w illing to adopt a genera l metric of justice, gender inequa lities in favor of women would reduce t he overa ll level of injustice t hey suf fer: good news for overa ll gender justice. if instead no inequality in life expectancy, homicide, or incarceration can do anything to offset inequalities in, say, labor income, social status, or sexual violence, a l l t hese i nequa l it ies si mply con st it ute i ncom men su r able for m s of injust ice, a nd if a n unjust inequa lit y develops in favor of women, t his would not reduce but further worsen gender injustice. But we are not there yet, a nd may never get t here : most of my commentators deny t hat t he inequalities i listed are injustices against men. in this response, i shall discuss several of their insightful, sometimes ingenious arguments. But i shall not bore the reader with a point by point response, in particular w ith a defensive inventor y of the many cases in which i feel that a (genuinely or falsely naïve) question i was asking was misunderstood as a suggestion, or even as an assertion. the literary genre 3 in particular, had i been a woman, it is most unlikely that i could have enjoyed as much as i did the immense privilege of combining a large family and a demanding job (see the section “Femmes Francqui” in my “allocution à l’occasion de la remise du Prix Francqui 2001,” www.uclouvain.be/8611). Possibly in a slightly weakened form, Jesús Mora’s apt remark can most probably be generalized: “Men with very successful careers in the hard sciences often have several children, successful female scientists often have no families at all, as they have to compete with men who have housewives that do everything for them whilst lacking one. So a group of well qualified women are childless or even entirely alone” (Mora 2015:). www.uclouvain.be Real Freedom for all Women (and Men) 163 LEAP 3 (2015) of my initial piece is certainly largely to blame for such over-interpretations. Precisely because it (uncharacteristically) abstained from making specific proposals, it did not need firm assertions by way of premises.4 it stopped at listing and motivating some questions. asking a question leaves open the possibility of an answer my critics would find objectionable but does not amount to proposing it. 1. no DiSaDvantaGe the general format of the question i asked was: are the apparent disadvantages of men that i listed unjust and, if not, why not? a first type of response to this sort of question consists in arguing that, once looked at closely, the appearance of advantage vanishes, or at least much of it does. this is the case for life expectancy. Paula casal (90) usefully invites us to have a look at the age pyramid. if it turns out that there is little difference between the two sides except at the very top, it reinforces the idea that the advantage, if any, cannot be that great. at the limit, women simply “enjoy” some extra miserable years in their nineties which they may prefer not to have to endure (and would not if euthanasia and assisted suicide were legally and socially easier). unequal numbers of years in good health would arguably be a better indicator of a genuine inequalit y of advantage, despite the unavoidable arbitrariness of the cut-off point between good and bad health. But this would still not do. as brief ly pointed out in my piece and insightfully developed in casal’s, this would overlook the asy mmetric care-giv ing to the ageing partner. even if preaching and material incentives (favorably discussed by casal) could drive down the average age gap between partners to zero, even if the disposition (and competence) for caring for one’s ageing partner had been equalized across genders, even if as much as possible was outsourced (as also recommended by casal), there would remain, on average, a greater burden for the female members of heterosexual couples, simply owing to t hei r longer l i fe ex pecta nc y. t h is g reater bu rden f u r t her reduces t he associated advantage. in order to assess what advantage is left (if any), this suggests designing a notion of Qaly (quality-adjusted life years) that does not only take health into account, but also such burdens. inequality, using this amended metric, might still be in favor of women, but it will definitely be far smaller than when measured by the raw gap in life expectancy. 4 w hen in other contexts i asked such incongruous questions as whether surfers should be fed( van Parijs 1991), or the elderly disfranchised( van Parijs 1998) – which some hard workers and some pensioners might have found offensive – i did not leave the questions open but argued for an answer (yes to food for surfers, no to taking away the old folk’s vote!). 164 Philippe Van Parijs LEAP 3 (2015) a second interesting example of an advantage that arguably melts once scr ut ini zed is prov ided by Jesús Mora in his st imu lat ing discussion of education. while claiming that education should be regarded as a dimension of advantage not entirely reducible to the earning power it generates, i had also stressed the relevance of a paradox: “having to work so much harder to be rewarded so much less is, as van Parijs at one point suspects, one of the forms of compound injustice that women face” (Mora 2015: 114). Mora does not challenge the independent importance of education: “it is true t hat educat ion could potent ia l ly, in some possible world, of fset men’s economic advantage” (108). But his explanation for the paradox i stress makes the educational advantage enjoyed by women a necessary by-product of the inequality they suffer in other respects. here is the core of the argument. Females invest more than males in their own education because they anticipate that they w ill need it more than men for their ow n material security: “with every pregnancy and every year into the marriage, women become less desirable both in the love and the labor markets”(109). this is ref lected, he conject u res, i n a mater ia l ret u r n to educat ion t hat is systematically higher for women than for men. women’s greater educational achievements“are thus sy mptoms of gender inequalit y, not signs of its disappearance” (114). to the extent that the higher average level of education is inextricably linked to disadvantages in other dimensions and hence, by hypothesis, would disappear in its absence, it is therefore no longer clear that it could be considered a separate, possibly compensating, dimension of advantage, or at least it is less clear than i had made it sound. this is an interesting conjecture, and certainly part of the story.5 even if it is not the full story, it can legitimately be used to argue that the alleged advantage is less than it seems. 2. DiSaDvantaGe JuStiFieD let us now accept, as several of my commentators do, that along some dimensions women enjoy some advantage, though possibly smaller than what it looks at first sight.6 a second response then consists in arguing that t here is not hing unjust about it. a f irst version of it is t he “rawlsia n” 5 can the comparatively high rates of absenteeism, unruliness, and dropping out among male teenagers and their long-term consequences on the education gap be entirely accommodated by this conjecture? i doubt it. 6 one candidate i did not mention is strikingly documented by casal (2015: 93): the probability of being killed is 2.5 times less if you are a white woman than if you are a white man, 9 times less if you are a black woman than if you are a black man. Does the fact that the overwhelming majority of the perpetrators are men prevent us from regarding men’s much larger probability of being murdered as a genuine and potentially unjust disadvantage? Real Freedom for all Women (and Men) 165 LEAP 3 (2015) argument developed by casal (2015:98) against the background of fascinating evolutionary conjectures: “the inequality in longevity is not unjust because its removal would make humans worse off.” in the human and some other species, the females having longer lives than males is apparently beneficial to the care, survival, and education of all their offspring, male and female. this arguably turns women’s greater longevity into an adaptive feature, which natural selection has preserved throughout the millennia and is still with us. let us suppose that this explanation is correct. By no means does it follow that the inequality it explains is thereby justified. For the surplus of strength or resilience that enabled more mothers to steer their offspring into adulthood, despite the ha zards of deliver y and other perils, is now what accounts for a life expectancy of 85 rather than 80 or so. we are therefore talking here about one of those features which, however crucial they might have been in a more or less remote past, have lost their function in a deeply altered env ironment. Similarly, male aggressiveness must have been a handsome asset, in both individual and group selection, throughout the millennia in which some of our ancestors lived in rival tribes of hunters, but this is no justification for it in our societies. the other challenges to the injustice of a recognized disadvantage suffered by men rely on the assumption that this disadvantage –in terms of longevity, incarceration, education, etc. –is mediated by a lifestyle or behavior pattern that is male-specific or at least displayed by men more often than by women. the phrasing of my puzzles occasionally suggested that it was essential to them that this propensity to behave in a certain way should be linked to man’s hormonal constitution. But i fully agree with convergent remarks by casal (2015: 91, 98), ottonelli (2015: 134), and Schouten (2015: 139) to the effect that, however big a difference this may make as regards possible remedies, there is no crucial difference as regards justice or responsibility between causal accounts in terms of genetic equipment, early socialization, or socially sanctioned expectations about what it is to behave as a “real woman” or as a “real man.” early socialization and social sanctions are no more chosen by the individual men and women shaped by them than is their genetic equipment. this being clarified, let us consider the suggestion that women’s greater longevity is (prima facie and pro tanto) unjust, against the background of the factual assumption that men are predisposed, either by their genetic equipment or by their social environment, to a behavior pattern that will inf lict on them a genuine disadvantage relative to women, by costing them on average several years of valuable life. casal formulates t wo “liberal- egalitarian” challenges to this disadvantage constituting an injustice, one inspired by tim Scanlon, the other by ronald Dworkin. 166 Philippe Van Parijs LEAP 3 (2015) according to the “Scanlonian” challenge, once society has done enough, i.e., once men, under appropriate circumstances, have been sufficiently warned that some behavior pattern can have detrimental consequences for them, there is no injustice involved if they persist in behaving in a damaging way. one serious problem with this challenge is that making people aware of the consequences of their choices does not get rid of the underly ing unchosen disadvantage, as well characterized by Schouten in the case of incarceration: “whatever configuration of social and natural causes are at work, they presumably make males likelier to be incarcerated because they make it more difficult for males than for females to avoid the kinds of behav iors that lead to incarceration” (Schouten 2015: 139). Much of t he material injustice suffered by women is of fundamentally the same nature: “to make the counter-gender-typical choice of prioritizing paid labor, the average woman will have to overcome either ingrained social norms or a natural predisposition to prioritize others’ needs for care, or both; and she will have to pay the costs of violating social norms.” (141) whether or not men or women a re being properly wa rned about t he consequences of following their natural or social inclinations, “in both cases, the inequalities in the background against which the relevant choice is made are not chosen; and in both cases, the relevant choice is harmful to the chooser” (142). if appropriate warnings are deemed sufficient to nullify the alleged injustice suffered by men as a result of their choices, the door is wide open for this sort of excessively easy justification of inequalities suffered by women. the “Dworkinian” challenge presented by casal deactivates the imputation of injustice by focusing on what the alleged victims of injustice identify with, rather than the warning given to them. there is no injustice involved (let alone compensation due), so the challenge goes, if men identify with the behavioral pattern that triggers the disadvantage. to the extent that they identify with it, such a behavioral pattern is not a handicap, like an addiction, which they would prefer to be w ithout. it is part of their identit y, like a religion which they may never have chosen – if they grew up within it – but which they embrace. the test proposed by Dworkin in order to determine what counts as an injustice calling for redress or compensation consists in a counterfactual insurance dev ice, where people are supposed to know their ambitions but not their endowments. when performing this exercise, men “would have insured against illness or disability but not against being male” (casal 2015: 100). the trouble with this challenge is that nothing prevents, in Dworkin’s dev ice, taking male, or female, or atheist, or Muslim, as part of what one identifies with, and hence of one’s ambitions (like wanting to be a pianist or a gardener), while insuring against how costly it w ill prove to be. this them.There embrace.The Real Freedom for all Women (and Men) 167 LEAP 3 (2015) presupposes that one can dissociate being male from the cost it involves (here in years of life), and there is no reason why such dissociation should be ruled out, unless the cost is what one identifies with (as some may do w it h fa st i ng ).if one d id r u le it out, a s i mpl ied by ca sa l’s D work i n ia n argument, it is true that one could no longer make sense of the injustice of a number of disadvantages suffered by men, but equally of many putatively unjust disadvantages suffered by women. “Some may worry,” casal (100) notes, “that this Dworkinian use of self- identification as a criterion for justif ying compensations may not always favor feminist demands.” indeed they should worr y. Spending plent y of time with their children is part of an identity some women embrace, and if the implied cost in foregone (current and future) income could not be dissociated from what they identify with, they would have no “Dworkinian” complaint of justice against the income inequalit y stemming from this source, just as men, for analogous reasons, would not have a “Dworkinian” claim of justice against inequalit y in life expectancy stemming from a lifest yle w ith which they identif y. if we are not to miss a big part of the injust ice inf licted to women, it wou ld t herefore seem w ise to a l low a dissociation between gender-specific behavioral patterns and their cost, at the price of acknowledging the failure of the “Dworkinian” challenge. are we then forced to admit that any disadvantage – whether higher chance of being killed or more expensive consumption – stemming from men’s specific lifestyle or pattern of behavior is, albeit prima facie and pro tanto, unjust, given that it is causally linked to the unchosen fact that they a re men? we a re not. clea rly, a ny plausible concept ion of just ice must manage to make a distinction between a handicap that justifies redress or compensation and preferences the cost of which need to be borne by those who have them. this point is forcefully made by de Miguel (2015: 154) in the case of prostitution: “it is also very strange to say that somebody is to some degree disabled in an injustice-involving sense merely because they have, or a re more li kely to have, a preference. the sa me is t r ue if t he preference is a passion, for instance for the sea or the snow, that might kill you in some circumsta nces. the word ‘ha ndicap’ suggests somet hing stronger than the frustration of a mere preference, the ex istence of an unmet need.” thirst, she argues, can qualify as a need, but not the preference for having it satisfied in a fancy way. “and the desire for sex is like this ‘thirst- t h i ng’ for most men. t hey love hav i ng it, a nd so long a s t hey a re not handicapped in other ways, and so still have hands, relief is simple, instant, and gratis” (de Miguel 2015: 153). any sensible conception of justice must make room for a distinction of this sort. in the following section, i shall drop the ad hominem (or ad feminam) posture i have adopted so far (as well as in 168 Philippe Van Parijs LEAP 3 (2015) my initial piece) and sketch how the conception of justice to which i subscribe myself tries to accommodate this important distinction and to address other key issues raised in the comments. 3. Social JuStice aS real FreeDoM For all ottonelli (2015: 126) finds it puzzling that i assumed as unproblematic “some version of equality of opportunity for welfare or resources,” which fails to capture key aspects of the injustice suffered by women: “for example, women’s higher unemployment rates, lower income, and greater hardship resulting from divorce,” which should be “taken as signs of the domination, oppression, and exploitation that women suffer in our society.” She is right to complain. these aspects need to be taken on board, and the conception of justice i subscribe to can accommodate them, i believe, far better than the vague notion of equality of advantage which i have been relying on so far for the sake of the argument(s). this conception can be captured in the slogan “real freedom for all.” it essentially requires empowering as much as is sustainable those with least power to shape their lives. and it is leading me to advocate, along with carole Pateman, for example, repeatedly cited by de Miguel (2015: 153, 158), and along with many others, an unconditional basic income.7 For the sake of justice as real freedom for all, this unconditional income should be pitched at the highest sustainable level, part of it being given in the form of qua lit y education, health care, and a sane environment, in addition to an unflinching protection of physical integrity. however they are funded, the introduction of an unconditional basic income and the rise of its relative level are bound to involve a net redistribution from men to women and, more importantly, a greater expansion of life options for women than for men. it should not take too much effort to imagine, in particular, what difference the highest sustainable unconditional basic income would make to the prostitutes described by de Miguel (153-6). its prospective effect is not mainly to increase their purchasing power. it is above all to increase their bargaining power on all fronts by multiplying exit options. nor should it take much effort to show that such a conception of justice is more than compat ible w it h ot tonel l i’s (130) v iew t hat “ou r t reat ment of ma le’s unfortunate hormonal constitution represents indeed a rare case of over- accommodation of an impairing disability”or with de Miguel’s (158) call for putting an end to “overindulgence in the male itch.” Moreover, if it is 7 See Pateman (2006), Murray &Pateman eds. (2012), and, for recent discussion of the connection between gender inequalities and basic income, Mclean (2015) and elgarte (in progress). Real Freedom for all Women (and Men) 169 LEAP 3 (2015) the case that “an overwhelming presence of men in dangerous, difficult, and hazardous jobs […] causes countless episodes of killings, torture, physical aggression, humiliation, maltreatment, medical malpractice, physical injuries, and deaths by negligence” (ottonelli 132), then there is no doubt that justice as real freedom for all would command that an end should immediately be put to this over whelming presence of men. there may well ex ist sound evolutionar y explanations for male-specific dispositions that generate despicable behavior, but this can never amount to justifying giving the latter free rein. this being said, it is of course intrinsic to a conception of justice that adopts freedom as its distribuendum that it should not erect into an ideal the achievement of equal average scores – or of an equal grand total score – by all categories of human beings for variables expected to be affected by the latter’s free choices. the monitoring of gender gaps, in particular, can play a useful role in locating forms of discrimination or intimidation that hinder the pursuit of justice as real freedom for all. But the existence of significant gender gaps in terms of expected lifetime earnings or quality- adjusted life years, for example, is not, as such, decisive ev idence that injustice is being perpetrated. the choices made by men and women that lead to such gender gaps are not made in an angelic vacuum. they are made by people enabled and inclined by their genes to do, on average, different t hings or do t hem dif ferent ly, depending on whet her t hey a re men or women. these human beings also grew up and currently live in immediate surroundings and wider societies that tend to expect different things from them depending on their gender. Men and women may or may not identify with these expectations. a just society is not one in which all gender-specific capabilities and expectations have been eradicated. it is one whose institutions allocate resources in such a way that those women and men with least real freedom are made as really free as possible to live as they might wish to live, including of course by refusing to fulfill the existing gender-specific social expectations. So far (perhaps) so good. But how can such a conception of justice make room for a distinction between, on the one hand, handicaps for which it is fair that one should be compensated and, on the other hand, preferences the consequences of which one should bear? Quite simple – in principle. as ment ioned above, pa r t of t he highest susta inable uncondit iona l basic income is to be given in kind, in particular, in the form of a health care package. how big this component should be, and what it should cover and how,is to be determined, in Dworkinian fashion, through a thought experiment that requires us to hide behind a veil of ignorance those of our features – including our gender –that affect the probability of our suffering disabilities 170 Philippe Van Parijs LEAP 3 (2015) and other health impairments in a very broad sense.8 the resulting just health care system can safely be expected to cover,for example, pregnancy, abortion, contraception, perhaps female and male infertility. it may well accommodate a dependency insurance that reduces the chance of elderly people needing to rely heavily on their close relatives. But i would not count on its including prostitution vouchers. 4. aGainSt cateGorical JuStice this is not the place to further spell out the content and implications of social justice as real freedom for all, except to further clarif y, using illustrations provided in the comments, in what sense it is incompatible with the very idea of gender justice(and, more generally, of category-based justice), and why this matters. to illustrate the incompatibility, let us first return to longevity. in her insightful discussion, casal (2015: 94) notes: “it would not make sense to compensate men who avoid all life-shortening behavior and are thus likely to live long. For then there will be nothing they have to be compensated for[…]. But it would make even less sense to compensate individuals who, despite engaging in all the life-shortening gendered behavior, still escape the fate for which they are supposed to be compensated.” Quite right. let us radica li ze t he exa mple by considering t wo f ict it ious situat ions. in situation a, all females die at 85 and all males at 80. in situation B, everyone dies at 85 except for one baby boy out of seventeen, who dies shortly after birth, thereby giving males a life expectancy at birth of 80. Surely, it would be absurd to count this lower life expectancy at birth as a disadvantage for the surviving males. if anything, it should count as an advantage, since the form taken by this shorter life expectancy has made them scarcer relative to females in the mating segment of their lives. But this is not only about just-born babies. Suppose that the whole of the gender gap in life expectancy was the result of a higher probability of males dying before forty. there would be no longevity disadvantage in being a male over forty. this should suffice to convey the intuition of why the very idea of talking about justice between stat ist ica l categories, gender or ot her w ise, is problemat ic. wit hin t he framework of justice as real freedom for all, in particular, categorical justice makes no sense. 8 as explained in van Parijs (2009: section 4), i now believe that this is a better way of accommodating what is usually captured by the preference/needs distinction than the criterion of “undominated diversity” proposed for this purpose in van Parijs (1995: chapter 3) and mentioned by casal (2015: 9). Real Freedom for all Women (and Men) 171 LEAP 3 (2015) to illustrate the real-life relevance of this rejection of categorical justice, let us return to Mora’s stimulating discussion of women’s educational advantage. i liked the compact summary of his analysis:“female educational efforts, far from signaling the arrival of equality, are the knotted rope women use to escape the f lames of discrimination, domestic and workplace exploitation, and poverty” (Mora 2015: 110). in the same vein, Mora points out that female higher educational efforts are worth pursuing because it is women’s “protection, and perhaps the only one, against being short-changed at work and at home,” and that higher education is the “irreplaceable tool for them to achieve levels of employability similar to men’s” (110). one conclusion one may be tempted to draw from this is that promoting the education of women, and in particular their access to higher education, is the only serious hope for addressing the injustice suffered by women. But i am sure that Mora will want to resist this conclusion. For what about the countless women who, even in the best circumstances, will never go into higher education? Surely, the injustice they suffer is in no way diminished as a result of other women escaping the f lames of discrimination and exploitation. Justice as real freedom for all does not care about justice between genders, or any other categories, taken globally. it demands that prior attention be given to the real freedom, to the bargaining power of the worse-off, most likely women a nd men who never at tended a nd w i l l never at tend h ig her educat ion. therefore, the privileges, big and small, enjoyed by those who do get access to higher levels of education can be justified only by the extent to which they contribute to the real freedom of those who do not. the pursuit of social justice as real freedom for all may require policy tools that are categorical, in particular gender-specific. But social justice and injustice themselves must be understood as obtaining or failing to obtain between individuals. one of the great contributions of feminism to the thinking about justice is to have made it more indiv idua list ic by blow ing up t he black box of t he household and exposing intra-household injustice. thinking about justice as applying between categories is no better than thinking about justice as applying between households. 5. Political ineQuality i have said nothing so far about one inequality i mentioned as a potential injustice suffered by men, the fact that they systematically form a political minority. as well explained by Pierre-Étienne vandamme (2015), this case is quite different from the other ones. the inequality, here, is not as such an advantage, but only a potential source of advantages. and it is, moreover, a source that is most unlikely to ever be activated. 172 Philippe Van Parijs LEAP 3 (2015) vandamme does not question the existence of a solid majority of female voters in mature democracies. he even mentions the stunning figure of seven million more women than men voting at recent uS presidential elections. however, he does challenge the expectation that this gap will widen as a consequence of the widening gap between the educational level of women and men. apparently, with some exceptions such as the uS and Switzerland, the positive correlation between education level and turnout is vanishing in mature democracies. By contrast, the positive correlation between age and turnout remains firm, even though one cannot expect the ageing of the population to deepen the gap in life expectancy, nor therefore the male-female imbalance in either the electorate or the turnout. the key issue, however, is whether belonging to a numerical majority – whether racial, religious, linguistic, professional, whatever – is a feature that matters as regards justice. clearly, no procedural injustice is involved: one person, one potential vote. hence, vandamme (2015: 120) rightly argues that injustice can only arise from a numerical imbalance if the more numerous g roup uses its electora l power to “turn t his numerica l adva ntage into a substantial injust ice.” one ca n imag ine t wo situat ions in which t his is unlikely to happen. one is a perfect deliberative democracy, in which all voters are guided by an impartial conception of justice or of the common good, not by their personal interests. the other situation is that of a democracy that is less than perfect in this sense, but in which the interests of majority and minority are so closely intertwined that the majority could not pursue its own interests without also pursuing those of the minority. if we diverge significantly from either of these situations, a serious risk of injustice arises, unless special constitutional or customary constraints are introduced in order to protect the minority, such as veto powers, guaranteed representation, quotas, and parity rules in executives and in legislative assemblies. w hy do such protections seem to make obv ious sense in the case of Flemings versus walloons, Shiites versus Sunnites, etc. and not in the case of women versus men? the reason is not that the categories of women and men a re each ver y heterogeneous. So a re t he ot her major it y/m i nor it y pairs. the difference, i submit, lies elsewhere. if ever y Fleming needed a walloon, or each Shiite a Sunnite, in order to procreate, if each of them was born from a mixed couple and if most of them cohabited in mixed households and ended up with offspring from either group, their interests on most issues would converge sufficiently for the risk of a tyranny of the majority to be very limited, far more limited at any rate than if none of this were the case. But this is exactly the situation that obtains between men and women. there is a (quasi) unavoidable territorial and personal closeness between genders that makes for a far more systematic convergence of interests Real Freedom for all Women (and Men) 173 LEAP 3 (2015) than in the case of ethnic categories. not a total convergence, needless to say, but one sufficient for no protective veto power to make sense, however large the gap between female and male voting power ever becomes, especially if, next to the convergence of interest, public deliberation plays some of its civilizing, justice-seeking role. For the time being, any way, the danger of misuse of political power is rather coming from the other side. vandamme rightly stresses that political power does not reduce to electoral power. whether because of the misplaced celebration of “leadership” qualities denounced by ottonelli (2015: 130) or because of the unequal distribution of relevant resources, more men than women tend to be involved in forms of political participation more demanding and more consequential than casting a vote at distant intervals. hence, if political power is being misused in those areas in which the interests of men and women systematically diverge, it is more likely to be at the expense of women rather than in their favor, for example, because platforms and policies are surreptitiously concocted and packaged in gender-biased fashion. this is why the presence of women at all levels of public (and private) power is so important. not for the sake of equalizing the chance of access to top positions for the select few, but in order to prevent the specific interests of women of all social classes being systematically under appreciated or completely overlooked. this is about political power, though not the power to impose one’s will through majoritarian voting, rather the power to make problems visible and intelligible in time, and to create the conditions for the adoption and implementation of solutions that can be regarded as fair by all women no less than by all men. ePiloGue “why not go to a disability conference to talk about the four downsides of being able-bodied?” de Miguel (2015: 159) asks. Good question. no, i would not do it. w hy t hen did i ag ree to do somet hing a na logous on gender i nequa l it y ? no doubt bec au se i bel ieve t hat t here a re some c r uc ia l differences bet ween the case of gender and that of disabilit y. a nd also because in this case i was specifically asked to raise some philosophical quest ions on gender by someone i li ke a nd whose act ion i wa nted to support. Given the short time at my disposal, my first puzzles were the way i thought i could satisfy the request most effectively. this turned out to be a mistake in the short run, but perhaps not in the longer run, judging by the discussion in this volume, very instructive and clarifying certainly for me and probably for others too. 174 Philippe Van Parijs LEAP 3 (2015) never t heless, as Schouten (2016 : 137) puts it, “we might la ment t he opportunity costs of theorizing alleged injustices against men when women continue to be victimized by pervasive structural injustices, and worry that such theorizing will slow progress toward women’s equality.” i entirely share the underlying conviction that concern with real-life injustices should be at the core of much of our work as political philosophers. it has certainly been at the core of mine. asking, as i did, some seemingly incongruous questions was certainly not intended to “slow progress toward women’s equality” (137). as should be clear by now, it was meant to invite more careful thinking about the relation between gender and justice in a way that should have some relevance to the public debate on these issues, and hence also to real-life gender-related public policy. in particular, i wanted to highlight the possibility that gender justice, understood as justice between two categories, may be the wrong way to think about justice and gender –a point that, in different ways, both casal (2015: 91) and de Miguel (2015: 159-60), also touch upon. to illustrate the relevance of this challenge to real life, consider the Gender Equality Index developed by the vilnius-based european institute for Gender equality.9 Such a composite index aggregates a number of variables each of which ref lects some aspect of gender inequalit y, for example, the male-female gaps in earnings, in rates of participation in the labor market, in proportions of ter t ia r y educat ion g raduates, in life ex pecta ncy or in pa rlia menta r y representation. when collected in a reliable and comparable way, the data sets used as inputs are extremely useful for the sake of assessing a country’s performance and guiding its policies. But the categorical-justice approach such a composite index encourages and the arbitrary weights on which it relies are, in my view, obstacles rather than tools in the effort to guide and design public policies in the service of social justice. in order to engage w it h rea l issues, we phi losophers of ten have to venture outside our tiny field of professional expertise. no problem as such: this is both our right and our duty. But it inevitably involves taking the risk of saying or suggesting things that turn out to be wrong, and hence of being corrected by colleagues who know more about the subject or have thought more about it. this is part of the never-ending attempt to give a coherent picture of what we can and must be heading for, to address the objections this picture may give rise to, and to correct it whenever needed. i am most grateful to my commentators and especially to Paula casal, who master-minded t his sy mposium, for hav ing helped me a long on t his – sometimes bumpy – road. 9 Gender Equality Index 2012, european institute for Gender equality, https://w w w. eige.europa.eu/gender-statistics/genderequality-index, consulted March 2016. https://www.eige.europa.eu/gender-statistics/genderequality https://www.eige.europa.eu/gender-statistics/genderequality Real Freedom for all Women (and Men) 175 LEAP 3 (2015) BiBlioGraPhy elgarte, J., in progress: Gender Justice and the Future of the Welfare State, doctoral dissertation in philosophy, université catholique de louvain. Mcl e a n, c ., 2015 : “Be yond c a re : e x pa nd i ng t he Fem i n i st Debate on Ba sic income,”WISE Working Paper 1, Glasgow ca ledonian universit y, September 2015. Murray, M.c. and c. Pateman, eds. 2012: Basic Income Worldwide. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan. Patema n, c., 2006 : “Democrat i zing cit i zensh ip. Some adva ntages of a Basic income,” in Redesigning Distribution, ed. e.o. wright, london: verso, 101-119. va n P a r ij s , P., 19 91: “ w hy Su r fer s Shou ld b e Fe d : t he l i b er a l c a s e f or a n unconditional Basic income,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 20, 101-31. — 1995: Real Freedom for All. oxford: oxford university Press. — 1998 : “the Disf ra nch isement of t he elderly, a nd ot her attempts to Secu re intergenerational Justice,” Philosophy and Public Affairs, 27, 292-333. — 2009: Basic income and Social Justice: Why Philosophers Disagree, Joint Joseph rowntree Foundation/university of york annual lecture 2009, https://w w w. jr f.org.u k/repor t/joseph-row nt ree-fou ndat ion-lect u re-basic-i ncome-a nd- social-justice-why-philosophers-disagree https://www.jrf.org.uk/report/joseph https://www.jrf.org.uk/report/joseph LEAP 3 (2015) Symposium Family Justice: The Ethics of Parent-Child Relationships LEAP 3 (2016) Family Values: An Introduction AndREW WiLLiAMS ICREA & Universitat Pompeu Fabra the social, legal, and political institutions that constitute the family play a profound and unavoidable role in shaping individuals’ lives and distributing opportunities amongst them. they strongly inf luence our psychological development, including the acquisition of a sense of justice, as well as various cognitive skills, and our prospects of success in the competition for positions conferring authority and inf luence in the economy and the state. those institutions also have non-instrumental importance insofar as we have weighty reasons to care about our capacity to enjoy love and intimacy both as adults and children, and the degree to which we are protected from various objectionable forms of control by other agents. Since the design of the family is malleable any reasonably complete political philosophy needs to ref lect on these and related issues. Fortunately, contemporary anglo- american political theorists have attempted to respond to this challenge. in recent years, some of the most notable contributions to the emerging debate have arisen v ia joint work by harr y Brighouse and adam Sw ift, leading eventually to the publication of their book, Family Values: The Ethics of Parent-Child Relationships (Brighouse and Swift, 2014). Brighouse and Swift provide a sophisticated liberal egalitarian account of the essential role of the family in a just society. the account is distinctive in part because of the role it affords to the interests of parents in enjoying valuable relationships with their offspring as well as the interests of children and adults in being raised in families. at the same time as showing how their favored dual interest case for the family justifies parental partiality, the authors are keen to establish their account offers no support for the types of substantial inequality in opportunity characteristic of most societies. these claims and others made by Brighouse and Swift raise a host of questions within ethics and political philosophy, several of which are pursued by the authors of the follow ing three thought-provoking papers. Sarah St roud ca l ls i nto quest ion some of t he ega l ita r ia n a ssu mpt ion about in herita nce that animate many recent discussions of justice and the family. anca Gheaus focusses on the extent to an adult’s interest in parental authority over a child can plausibly ground its possession. luara Ferracioli asks whet her Brighouse a nd Sw if t a re over-relia nt on a n idea l of persona l autonomy, and extends our attention to the interests of offspring in family membership over the course of their lives and not merely during childhood. LEAP 3 (2015) the discussion concludes with a substantial response by Brighouse and Swift that elaborates their position, and defends it where necessary. the editors hope the four papers advance debate on issues of pressing personal as well as public concern. they are grateful to all the participants for their commitment to the Sy mposium, and to Marcos Picchio for his invaluable administrative and philosophical assistance with the project. LEAP 3 (2015) Egalitarian Family Values? SAR AH STROud McGill University Abstract Family Values seeks to offer a compelling defence of the family in the face of concerns that the institution of the family disrupts fair equality of opportunity. Brighouse and Swift endorse the concern but think that the great value of family relationship goods is nonetheless sufficient to vindicate the existence of the family. this response applauds Brighouse and Swift’s insistence on the interests of parents in raising children and on the lov ing and intimate character of the parent-child relationship. however, it suggests that Brighouse and Swift’s egalitarian framework prevents them from taking the full measure of the above salutary commitments. Keywords: family, parent-child relationship, love, egalitarianism, relationship goods, parents’ interests, equality of opportunity, intrinsic goods, positional goods harry Brighouse and adam Swift are our leading theorists of the family.1 their previous joint papers have greatly advanced our understanding of the ethics and politics of relations between parents and children. their work exemplifies a rare combination of qualities: it is bold, path-breaking, and yet rigorous and attentive to nuance. For this reason, we already owe a number of game-changing insights and argumentative strategies to Brighouse and Swift. i would number among the most significant of these a) their insistence on adults’ interests in parenting as an indispensable factor in the moral and political equation; b) their emphasis on the value of the parent-child relationship in particular; and c) their use of the latter to work out in a systematic and principled way the rights and priv ileges which attend, or ought to attend, parenthood. the above insights and strategy also drive the new book, Family Values. readers already familiar with Brighouse and Swift’s joint articles will not 1 Following Brighouse and Swift, i will always mean by “the family” a “nuclear” family consisting of at least one parent and at least one child. 181 Sarah Stroud LEAP 3 (2015) find the authors taking a radically new approach here. instead, the elaboration at book length of their basic line of thought has given Brighouse and Swift the space to embed their core argument within a larger and more explicit overall argumentative architectonic. My remarks here will focus on the shape of that structure and the route it offers to the conclusions Brighouse a nd Sw if t a re a lready wel l k now n for endorsing. But i wa nt to beg in by lingering over a nd underlining t he sig nif ica nt insights t heir work has already brought to the table, and which continue to play a prominent role in this new book. to start with a), we owe Brighouse and Swift a great debt of gratitude for expanding the discourse around the family by highlighting the interests of (would-be) parents as well as those of children. i find much of the pre- Brighouse and Swift literature on the family excessively, or too exclusively, child-centred; in much of this literature families and parents are treated essent ia l ly as dev ices to ser ve chi ldren’s interests. Surely, however, as Brighouse and Swift emphasize, this is only part of the story. taking care of and raising children is a hugely rewarding and meaningful activ it y for many adults, one to which they freely choose to devote a substantial portion of their time and energy, and one which they may view as a central contributor to their own personal flourishing. Parenting is, quite simply, what they want to do (or among the things they want to do) with their life (Brighouse and Swift 2014: 22). Brighouse and Swift insist (their word) on the importance of this fact, maintaining that “adults’ interest in parenting (and not only children’s interest in being parented) helps us to understand the moral basis of the family” (2014: 176). thus, to neglect these parent-centred factors in discussing the ethics of the family would be to omit a significant piece of the equation. i wholeheartedly agree; i w ill question only whether this insight and the shift in perspective which it induces receive their full due in Family Values. we also owe to Brighouse and Swift a more precise specification of the content of the adult interest in parenting just mooted. as per insight b), Brighouse and Swift propose that parents (and those who desire to be parents) have a strong interest, specifically, in establishing and participating in a parent- child relationship. this is shorthand for an intimate, loving relationship with a child in which the parent has both considerable responsibilities toward the child and considerable decisional authority over the child. Brighouse and Swift argue that relationships of this distinctive kind are of great value to both parents and children, and (as we shall see under c)) they use this value as the linchpin for deriving further ethical and political conclusions about the family. to place a valuable relationship so explicitly at the core of family Egalitarian Family Values? 182 LEAP 3 (2015) ethics was a major conceptual advance,2 and one which fits in especially well with an inf luential strand in recent moral philosophy.3 again i think Brighouse and Swift are right to put the emphasis on the relationship between parent and child as the, or at least a, central ethical element when considering the family.4 i will again question, however, whether they have taken the full measure of the implications of this commitment. this last point brings us to c), Brighouse and Swift’s distinctive argumentative strategy for resolving questions about the rights and privileges that ought to at tend pa rent hood. t hei r si mple but i n novat ive idea is to deploy t he aforementioned value of the parent-child relationship as the sine qua non in assessing t he merits of putat ive pa renta l rights. if failing to accord parents a certain right or priv ilege would prevent the development of a valuable parent-child relationship, then that creates a strong moral and political case for granting parents that right or privilege, even in the face of possible mora l counter-a rg uments.5 on t he ot her ha nd, if disallowing parents a certain right or privilege would not impede the development of a f lourishing parent-child relationship, then that putative right or privilege sta nds ex posed a nd undefended aga inst a ny a rg uments t hat cou ld be ra ised aga i nst it. t h is double-edged cr iter ion a l lows us to adjud icate questions about legitimate parental rights or parental partiality in a principled way, taking us beyond mere reliance on intuition to discern their scope or limits. as mentioned earlier, in Family Values Brighouse and Swift embed these key insights within a larger argumentative superstructure, to which i will now turn. i w i l l t r y to bring out some points where resista nce to t heir conclusions can plausibly be traced back to unease with something more basic, namely their vision of the dialectical situation: their conception, for instance, of what kind of claim requires what kind of argument, or of where the burden of proof lies. Job one, as Brighouse and Swift see it, is to offer a “defense” (2014: xi, xii) or “justification” (2014: 5, 20, 51) of the family. and it soon becomes clear 2 they credit Schoeman (1980) with originally introducing this idea; but his account seems not to have had much inf luence on the subsequent literature in family ethics. 3 See for i n st a nce t he work of Schef f ler (20 01), espec ia l ly “relat ion sh ips a nd responsibilities” and “Families, nations, Strangers”, and Kolodny (2003). 4 i am pleased to see that word seems to be getting around that a parent’s relationship with his child is more important to both than any financial advantages the parent might be able to procure for his child by working more (Brighouse and Swift 2014: 136). From a recent entr y in the Guardian’s “My family values” series: “the people w ith the biggest stereos at boarding school were the ones who saw their parents the least… you cannot cover up for a loss of time with money” (hassell, 2015). 5 “Parents have the right to engage in those activ ities and interactions w ith their children that facilitate the realization of the extremely valuable goods that justif y the family in the first place” (Brighouse and Swift 2014:118). 183 Sarah Stroud LEAP 3 (2015) that what they have in mind is a distinctively consequentialist defense or justification. their aim, they tell us, is to demonstrate that and why it is “a good thing” (2014: i, 114) that the family exists: “to explain why it is good that children be raised by parents” (2014: 48). while Brighouse and Swift do not further explain the locutions “it is a good thing” or “it is good that”, such expressions are typically used to evoke a consequentialist conception of (impersonally or objectively) good states of affairs; and Brighouse and Swift’s approach to justifying the family confirms this interpretation. the task they set themselves is to show that and how the existence of the family realizes, or at least facilitates or makes possible, a distinctive set of desirable states of affairs: to prove, in short, that the world would be objectively poorer without families in it. the “familial relationship goods” alluded to earlier are the star players in this demonstration. Some readers, however, may already be feeling uneasy with Brighouse and Swift’s felt need to provide a justification of this kind for the family. For one thing, it may well strike readers as rather an idle question whether it is “a good thing” that families exist. it is, i take it, practically idle to ask whether families should exist: as far as i know, no one anywhere is seriously advocating, let alone threatening to effect, the abolition of the family. there is thus no actual interlocutor demanding to be convinced that the existence of the family is preferable to its nonexistence, and in that sense no actual threat against which the family needs to be defended. there are two further, more theoretical reasons why a reader might doubt that there is really a question here which needs dialectically to be answered. Brighouse and Swift’s self-appointed task is to adumbrate the distinctive values and goods which the existence of the family makes possible. But one m ig ht doubt whet her pa rents ra isi ng ch i ld ren requ i res a sui generis justification in terms of the distinctive values it realizes, as opposed to simply falling under a more general and less demanding moral schema. as we noted earlier, being a parent is something that a great many adults very much want to do with their life. if someone very much wants to do x with her life, one might think that alone creates a significant moral presumption in favour of allowing her to do x—regardless, it would seem, of x’s specific content, or of whether her (or anyone’s) doing x would realize important objective values.6 as a significant (but not all-consuming) life activ it y, parenting cou ld perhaps be compa red w it h t he choice of a pa r t icu la r ca reer. if someone ver y much wa nts to be a ta x law yer (for insta nce), wou ld we 6 this presumptive permission could be defeated, e.g. if xing caused severe harm to the participants or to others. But this is a weaker standard of v indication than needing to establish that “it is a good thing” that the world contains people who x, or that people’s xing realizes a distinctive set of objective values. Egalitarian Family Values? 184 LEAP 3 (2015) require proof that the universe would be objectively worse off without tax law yers in order to think it would be presumptively wrong to prohibit her from pursuing that career?7 in asking for a justification in terms of adding distinctive value to the universe, Brighouse and Swift set a high standard; but that is to place a burden of proof on the family which some will feel the family need not bear. to emphasize in this way the desires and choices of individual adults poi nts towa rd a f u r t her rea son one m ig ht be i l l at ea se w it h t he way Brighouse and Swift frame the issue. they write (2014: xi-xii) as if we as a society faced a question whose answer is to be decided collectively, namely, how we ought to arrange the bringing up of children. “in families” is of course one possible answer; but there are also other possible answers (such as “in state-run institutions”). as Brighouse and Swift see it, if we are to select the former option we should be sure it is the right choice, i.e. that it is better than the alternatives; whence the need to demonstrate the superiority of the family to other possible arrangements. But i find this way of describing the issue puzzling. at the risk of sounding thatcherite, i would have ventured that there is no issue facing us as a society, to be settled collectively, about how to bring up children: there are only indiv idual adults who want to parent children.8 i have expressed skepticism about whether the family really requires a “defense” or a “justification” of the consequentialist kind that Brighouse and Swift have in mind. But one might think it is at worst harmless to subject the family to such a test, since Brighouse and Swift make such a convincing case that it passes. as per insight b) noted earlier, Brighouse and Swift argue that the existence of the family does make possible certain distinctive goods, namely valuable parent-child relationships. a world which lacked families would be a world without those relationships, and thereby very much the poorer in at least one important respect. as it happens, Brighouse and Swift believe that the family is also the arrangement which best meets children’s needs and interests. For that reason alone, “if the family did not exist, it would be necessary to invent it; its invention would be morally required” (Brighouse and Sw ift 2014: x ii), and the world is indeed in a better state 7 one might argue that this case is not analogous, because being a parent essentially requires the existence (and the participation in the parent’s project) of nonconsenting partners with separate interests of their own, something not true of being a tax lawyer. however, the above general schema about x would seem also to hold of being, say, a dairy farmer. if what someone really wants to do with her life is to look after and interact with cows—nonconsenting partners in her project who have separate interests of their own—then surely that fact alone creates a presumptive moral case for allowing her to do just that. See the previous footnote for a gesture toward when that presumption could be overridden. 8 compare: there is no issue facing us as a society, to be settled collectively, about how to look after cows: there are only individuals who want to be dairy farmers. 185 Sarah Stroud LEAP 3 (2015) with families than it would be without. By contrast, could one say that it would have been necessary to invent tax law, or dairy farming, had no one spontaneously come forward wishing to engage in those activities? we do not normally demand this of activities in order to conclude that it would be prima facie wrong to prevent someone from engaging in them. even if the family can easily be shown to meet Brighouse and Swift’s high standard for justification, however, it is not harmless to ask for, and then to provide, such a justification. For there is a sting in the tail of Brighouse and Swift’s positive argument for the family: that argument is later used to limit the rights and privileges which parents can be said to enjoy. as we shall see, Brighouse and Swift accept only parental rights and privileges which must be granted if the distinctive values cited in the justification of the family are to be realized. a ny putative right or priv ilege which is not essential to the realization of those values is stricken from the list. this is the basis for many of Brighouse and Swift’s controversial conclusions, of which i will focus here on just one: that parents do not have the right to bequeath substantial wealth to their children.9 Before examining how exactly they reach this conclusion, i must first, in the spirit of full disclosure, confess significant antipathy to it. i simply cannot bring myself to believe it! i am writing the first draft of this piece at my country house: an old vermont farmhouse surrounded by pasture and fields which my family was able to purchase this past spring only thanks to an inheritance my husband received from his late mother. (we would never have been able to buy a country house on my philosopher’s salary.) we are very sorry she is not getting to see her son plant fruit trees, her grandson learn the names of wildf lowers, or her granddaughter pick blackberries and make preserves. But she loved her son, and the rest of us, and we know she would be deeply gratified by all the new horizons her bequest has opened up for us. Faced with this vivid awareness of what her bequest has made possible for her son and my family, i find it simply impossible to accept that my mother-in-law ought not to have been able to leave my husband that money, or that it would violate nobody’s rights to prevent or prohibit people from doing any such thing. let us look at the argument supporting this (to me) unwelcome conclusion. i reconstruct it as follows: (1) “the family is justified because it produces certain goods that would other w ise not be available or ... would be much more difficult to produce” (Brighouse and Swift 2014: 56), viz., familial relationship goods, which are “hugely valuable for many adults and 9 By “substantial” i mean wealth that exceeds what would be required in order to meet the child’s basic needs or to satisf y the parent’s duty of care toward the child. Egalitarian Family Values? 186 LEAP 3 (2015) a l l ch i ld ren” (Br ig house a nd Sw i f t 2014 : 20). (just i f icat ion of the family) (2) the scope and limits of parental rights and privileges should— indeed must (Brighouse and Swift 2014: ix, x, 5, 54, 115)—be derived from the justification of the family. (methodological premise) (3) More specifically, genuine parental rights and priv ileges are limited to the smallest set necessary for the realization of the goods cited in the justification of the family. (4) therefore (from (1) and (3)), any supposed parenta l rights or pr iv i leges t he withholding of w h ich wou ld not jeopa rd i z e t he rea l i z at ion of fa m i l ia l relat ion sh ip good s — ot her w i se put, t he g ra nt i ng of wh ich is not cr it ica l to establ ish i ng or pa r t icipat i ng i n a va luable pa rent-ch i ld relat ionsh ip — a re not genuine parental rights. (5) the freedom to bequeath significant wealth to your child is not essential to establishing or participating in a valuable parent- ch i ld relationship. Such a freedom is largely exogenous rather than endogenous, to the parent-child relationship and to its value; withholding this pr iv i lege f rom pa rents wou ld t herefore not jeopardize the realization of familial relationship goods (Brighouse and Swift2014: chapter 5; see 119 for the internal-external contrast). (6) therefore (from (4) and (5)), parents do not have a right to bequeath significant wealth to their children. Before delving more deeply into this “master” argument, i should note that Brighouse and Sw ift also offer what i consider to be an ill-adv ised narrower specification of their methodological premise: (2') the scope and limits of parental rights and privileges should— i nd e e d mu s t— b e d e r i v e d s ol e l y f rom th a t p or t i on of th e justification of the family which appeals to children’s interests (2'), however, seems clearly inconsistent with the conjunction of (1) and (2), and for that reason i propose to set it aside in the remainder of the discussion. if we are assuming that the correct account of parental rights is to be derived from the justification we offered for the family, and parents’ interests were an important element in that justification, then surely parents’ interests should not drop out of the picture as irrelevant when it is time to limn 187 Sarah Stroud LEAP 3 (2015) parental rights.10 if “it would be wrong to think that the well-being of ch i ld ren shou ld be t he sole cr iter ion by wh ich to a ssess ch i ld- rearing arrangements”, why should “the rights and duties of parenthood” be “ident i f ied ent i rely by considerat ion of children’s i nterests” ? (Brighouse a nd Sw if t 2014: 121, w it h added emphasis a nd some words rearranged). what then of the original “master” argument? we should start by noting that (2) is questionable. it is not obvious that the same considerations used to justify the very existence of the family ought to be expected to settle the parameters of parental rights—let alone that that is the only way properly to settle those parameters (as their “must” implies). Perhaps, having offered a consequentialist justification for the family—having established that it is “a good thing” for there to be families—we would go on to resolve questions about t he scope of pa renta l rights w it hin such fa mi lies in a completely dif ferent way. we might for example offer a non-consequentialist account of parental rights and privileges founded in the liberties it is proper to extend to autonomous agents as a function of their status and moral powers.11 Second, (3) seems ad hoc even if we accept (2). why should parental rights be limited to the smallest set necessary for, rather than the largest set consistent with, the values cited in the justification of the family? let us grant that it’s very important that any rights or privileges accorded to parents be consistent with the realization of those goods. this would mean that any putative parental rights inconsistent with valuable parent-child relationships would need to be stricken from the list. But why strike putative parental rights that are perfectly consistent with the realization of such values? here i would expect Brighouse and Swift to cite the possibility that other considerations might militate against the granting of such rights.12 if there is an independent objection to parents’ having a certain right or privilege, then we should accept the latter as a genuine right only if we need to: only if we must accord parents such a right in order for families to realize the values that justify their existence. Brighouse and Swift press just this possibility against the putative right to bequeath wealth to your children. there is a powerful objection to parents’ having such a right, in their view: such bequests 10 Brighouse and Swift may be assuming that any parental right that went beyond what is required by children’s interests wou ld be against children’s interests. But t his is unwarranted. 11 Frances Kamm has been a pioneer in seeing rights as expressive of the moral status of rightsholders. See Kamm (2013) for an accessible treatment. 12 in that case, (4) should strictly speaking be reworded so as to refer only to supposed parental rights or privileges to which objections could be raised, and (5) should make explicit that objections could indeed be raised to the putative freedom to bequeath significant wealth to your child. Egalitarian Family Values? 188 LEAP 3 (2015) disrupt equality of opportunity. let me set out the argument for that conclusion, as i see it: (a) all people are of equal moral worth, equally valuable (Brighouse and Swift 2014: 23). (B) “the fact that people’s lives are equally important has distributive implications—implications about the distribution of opportunities to flourish” (Brighouse and Swift 2014: 27). in particular, it implies that those opportunities should be distributed fairly. (c) it is prima facie unfair for one person to have a greater prospect of gett ing a desirable job or ot her socia l ly produced rewa rd t ha n a second person of equal abilities and equal willingness to use them. (D) therefore, there is a well-founded objection to, and thus a reason to prevent or prohibit, any action which results in the state of affairs described in (c). (e) Bequeathing significant wealth to your children is such an action. therefore there is a well-founded objection to, and thus a reason to prohibit or prevent, such bequests. if this argument is sound, then there is a morally considerable objection to granting parents a general permission to make such bequests. and if (5) in the “master” argument is also true, we cannot rebut that objection—as we might in certain other cases—by claiming that parents’ having such a permission is essential to the realization of familial relationship goods.13 the alleged right to bequeath significant wealth to your children would sta nd si lent in t he dock, unable to ma ke a ny (suf f icient ly compel ling) answer to the prosecution’s case. an indictment would appear forthcoming. without seeking to directly assess the soundness of the argument in (a)-(e) above, i do want to comment that it seems to prove an awful lot. if there is a st rong case for prohibit ing or prevent ing pa rents f rom bequeathing sig n i f ica nt wea lt h to t hei r ch i ld ren, t hen t here oug ht to be a si m i la r prohibition on parents’ gifting significant wealth to their children while they (the parents) are still alive. (otherwise i guarantee rich people will switch to the latter method.) and if parents are prohibited from bequeathing or gifting significant wealth to their children, then surely they ought to be prevented from bequeathing or gifting significant wealth to anyone else either. after all, the wealth they bequeath or gift would presumably have 13 an appeal to familial relationship goods, were it permitted, would not undercut the leg itimacy of t he objection but wou ld suggest t hat it out weighed is by somet hing more important, and thus does not prevail all things considered. “Simply put, familial relationship goods are more important than fair equality of opportunity” (Brighouse and Swift 2014: 143). 189 Sarah Stroud LEAP 3 (2015) the same disruptive effect on fair equality of opportunity whether it went to their child or to someone else;14 and it would be very peculiar if parents were prohibited from giv ing to their children but perfectly at libert y to confer significant wealth on anyone other than their children. Finally, even the restriction to significant wealth appears ad hoc if we are concerned with disruptions to fair equality of opportunity as such. even giving someone $100 for a nice shirt and tie, or a good haircut, will give him a better prospect of obtaining a desirable job than he had before. according to Brighouse and Swift’s reasoning, such a gift unfairly harms all those of similar abilities (and willingness to use them) whose chances of getting that desirable job just went down. in sum, if we are prepared to object to any action which produces a more unequal distribution of opportunities and prospects (across those of similar abilities, etc.) than the distribution which held prior to that action, there seems to be no limit to what we would have to stamp out. i suspect Brighouse and Swift would reply by underlining that they, too, are on record as being against “pursu[ing] fair equality of opportunity wholeheartedly” (2014: 36) or “all the way” (2014: 44). Perhaps they agree that it would be ridiculous, if not intolerable, to forbid people ever to give anyone $100. But the moral i take from this is, i suspect, different from theirs. they see an admirable ideal whose moral force is sometimes outweighed by even more powerful considerations, such as the great value of familial relationship goods (see for instance 2014:33). i, on the other hand, see a plausible-sounding principle ((c) plus (D)) whose implications on closer inspection suggest that it is not an attractive ideal after all.15 i would also like to take issue with (5) in the “master” argument. there is of course some sense in which bequeathing significant wealth to your child is “external” to the parent-child relationship, simply in that such bequests necessarily take place after one party to the relationship has died. insofar as they literally postdate the person-to-person interactions which constitute a parent-child relationship, bequests take place outside rather than within the course of that relationship in a temporal sense. however, this very literal sense of “external” is not the one which is appropriate to the argument, and i think bequests cannot be so easily set aside from what is valuable in a parent-child relationship. let me explain why. 14 you might think disadvantaged recipients would be an exception to this rule; but in fact a large gift to a disadvantaged recipient advantages him relative to what used to be his disadvantaged confrères, and thus “contravene[s] … fair equality of opportunity” (Brighouse and Swift 2014: 132). 15 See Stroud (2013) for more on principles which sound appealing as slogans but whose implications (ought to) cause us ultimately to reject them. Egalitarian Family Values? 190 LEAP 3 (2015) a central component of the valuable parent-child relationship is that it is a loving relationship. in particular, the parent in such a relationship loves her child. it is a near-truism, and one that Brighouse and Swift endorse, that when you love someone you very much want him to flourish (2014: 123, 124, 132). (indeed, it is typical of love that you want to play some positive causal role in his f lourishing.) Suppose, then, that you are in a position to expose someone you love to something that you take to be an intrinsic good—that is, to a potential intrinsic contributor to his well-being or f lourishing. it would seem to be part of love—and thereby part of the valuable parent- child relationship—that you will want (all else being equal) to do so. as a lov ing parent, you w ill naturally seek to expose your children to music, animals, nature, and whatever else you think is non-fungibly valuable. Such behaviour is internal or endogenous to love, not external to and cleanly separable from the latter. note that i am not speaking of wanting to confer advantage on your loved one, where adva ntage is a n essent ia l ly compa rat ive not ion. (i a m not claiming that it is part of love to want your loved one to be in the top decile.) i actually think—and i take this to be broadly in the spirit of Brighouse and Sw if t’s ega lita ria n et hos—t hat t here is somet hing disreputable about w ishing for, and pursuing, purely positional goods for your loved ones, although it is an interesting question (which i will not take up here) whether and how this could be defended within moral theory.16 By contrast, it is hard to see anything objectionable in someone’s wanting to expose her children to intrinsic goods: what mistake could such a person be accused of making, and what grounds could there possibly be for seeking to restrict such conduct?17 unfortunately Brighouse and Swift think there are grounds for restricting it. For even exposing your children to what you take to be intrinsic goods may have instrumental effects which push your children ahead of others in the competition for socially produced rewards. this will inevitably occur if interacting with intrinsic, non-fungible goods tends to enhance skills, abilities, and character traits whose benefits are transferable to other, competitive contexts. (i would rather hope such interaction does tend in this way to improve your character.) when this happens, however, that will suffice to put your action under the disapproving purview of principle (D), which frowns on any action which results (even adventitiously) in a more unequal distribution of opportunities across those of similar ability, etc. than was the case prior to that action’s being performed. (D) will disapprove even if 16 Brighouse and Swift (2006) have themselves written eloquently on purely positional goods. For an argument that comparative judgements distract us from what is truly significant, see Frankfurt (1987). 17 Brighouse a nd Sw if t seem to concede t he force of t his worr y when t hey discuss t he idea of equa l opportunity for well-being (2014: 42). 191 Sarah Stroud LEAP 3 (2015) the action was aimed only at bringing your children into contact with intrinsic goods, and not at all at procuring competitive advantage for them. it must be said that it is not at all obv ious how my son’s hav ing the opportunity to gaze at the night sky far from urban light pollution, or my daughter’s learning to use a scythe, is really likely to give either of them a (further) competitive advantage in the modern economy. however, i am perfectly prepared to believe that it might, through some indirect route.18 if their being exposed to these activities does have that effect, then—back to that country house again!—there is, as Brighouse and Swift see it, a moral case for keeping me from offering these goods to my children. and as we already underlined, this will be so even if the procuring of a competitive advantage for my children is not at all my aim in exposing them to these new experiences. For me this again casts doubt on the soundness of the essentially consequentialist egalitarian principle on which Brighouse and Swift rely.19 More broad ly, i wa nt to suggest t hat ega lita ria ns li ke Brighouse a nd Swift are playing with fire in granting broad licence to loving parent-child relationships. From an egalitarian point of view, love is dangerous; it threatens to break out of the tight constraints on beneficence which Brighouse and Swift seek to erect in the name of equality of opportunity.20 Brighouse and Sw if t might say t hey do not disag ree t hat love tends to spi l l outside t he boundaries they try to set, but in their view the balance of values favors putting a protective firewall only around the highly valuable “core” of the parent-child relationship—even though this means placing some actions taken out of love, and in the context of such a relationship, off limits.21 there is however an irony in Brighouse and Swift’s judgement of relative value on this particular point. For by their own admission, the prohibition not just of bequests, but of all the various ways in which parents might seek to use their superior financial resources to benefit their children (think private schooling), would have only an insignificant effect on the unequal distribution of prospects for desirable jobs, etc. across children. that is, parents’ direct use of money to benefit their children is—it turns out—a relatively minor contributor 18 Perhaps (for instance) the patience Francesca is forced to develop as she (slowly) learns how to swing a scythe will further advantage her for desirable jobs later on. 19 consequentia list because t he test which t he principle a rticu lates is concerned solely with what results from our actions. 20 a more fruitful, although more radical, approach for Brighouse and Swift’s purposes might be to challenge standard understandings of love and in particular its supposed tie to wishing to benefit the loved one. See along these lines ebels-Duggan (2008). 21 Brighouse and Swift seem to take this line at times (2014: chapter 5, 132-137). this more nuanced view effectively concedes that such actions are indeed “internal” to love, but it maintains that the value of giving parental love more freedom to operate does not measure up to the disvalue of the resulting disruptions of fair equality of opportunity. Egalitarian Family Values? 192 LEAP 3 (2015) to inequality of opportunity. (Brighouse and Swift allude to this at 2014: 31-32 and 125-127.) Brighouse and Swift thus seem overly optimistic when they say early on that they will “offer an account of ‘family values properly understood’ … that mitigates—massively mitigates—the conf lict with equality” (2014: 4; added emphasis). it would appear rather that the egalitarian value to be gained by decreeing some loving actions to be beyond the pale of interpersonal justification is unequal to its cost. BiBlioGraPhy Brighouse, h. and Swift, a., 2006: “equality, Priority, and Positional Goods”, Ethics 116: 471-497. — 2014: Family Values. The Ethics of Parent-Child Relationships, Princeton: Princeton university Press. ebels-Dugga n, K., 2014: “aga inst Benef icence : a nor mat ive accou nt of love”, Ethics 119: 142-170. Frankfurt, h., 1987: “equality as a Moral ideal”, Ethics 98: 21-43. hassell, K., 2015: “Jeremy vine: my family values”, The Guardian www.theguardian.com/lifeandstyle/2015/sep/11/jeremy-vine-my-family-values Kamm, F., 2013: “nonconsequentialism” in The Blackwell Guide to Ethical Theory, ed. h. laFollette and i. Persson, 261-286, 2nd ed., chichester: wiley-Blackwell. Kolodny, n., 2003: “love as valuing a relationship”, Philosophical Review 112: 135-189. Scheffler, S., 2001: Boundaries and Allegiances, oxford: oxford university Press. Schoeman, F., 1980: “rights of children, rights of Parents, and the Moral Basis of the Family”, Ethics 9: 6-19. Stroud, S., 2013: “they can’t take that away From Me: restricting the reach of Morality’s Demands”, in Oxford Studies in Normative Ethics: volume 3, ed. M. timmons, oxford: oxford university Press. http://www.theguardian.com/lifeandstyle/2015/sep/11/jeremy LEAP 3 (2015) Is There a Right to Parent?1 A nC A GH E AuS Universitat Pompeu Fabra Abstract this paper examines harry Brighouse’s and adam Swift’s attempt to justify the family by appeal to the interests of both children and parents. according to their dual-interest account, adults’ interest in parenting plays a role in explaining why less than optimal parents can exercise legitimate authority over children. i analyze this claim and raise doubts about the existence of any fundamental right, which is non-derivative from children’s own interests, to parent understood as a right to control the child. Keywords: parents, children, right to parent one of the main questions to which Family Values offers an answer is how to just if y t he fa mi ly g iven what its aut hors—self-ident if ied libera l ha rr y Brighouse and adam Swift—call “the liberal challenge”. By “the family”, Brighouse and Swift mean a childrearing arrangement whereby a small number of particular adults stand in fiduciary, and authoritative, relationships with particular children, but which is not exclusively justified by reference to the child’s interest. this is an anomaly for liberals, who believe that all authoritative relationships between individuals with full moral status ought to be justified by appeal to the interest of the party over whom authority is being exercised. as self-identified liberals, Brighouse and Swift take this challenge seriously. the family is definitely not like this. consider: First, there exist—or we can imagine—ways to rear children alternative to the family. Brighouse and Swift list some of them: “[s]tate-regulated quasi-orphanages, in which children are raised by trained and specialised employees; [a]rrangements, such as those associated with Kibbutzim, in which child raising is shared between “parents” and designated child-raising specialists’ and [c]ommunes 1 For comments i am grateful to andrew williams and to participants to an open session on academia.edu and in particular to John Baker, Sally haslanger, r J leland, Michele loi and erik Magnusson. academia.edu 194 Anca Gheaus LEAP 3 (2015) in which a la rge g roup of adu lts col lect ively a nd joint ly ra ises a group of children, with no adult thinking of herself as having any special responsibility for any particular child, and no child thinking of herself as the responsibilit y of any particular adult” (Brighouse and Swift 2014:70-71). it may be that good families serve children’s interests better than any of the above alternatives – as Brighouse and Swift go on to argue. they draw on empirica l literature to ex pla in why chi ldren fa re best when ra ised by lov ing a nd suf f icient ly competent adu lts, which a re referred to as ‘adequate parents’. But, as far as i see, this is not in itself enough justification for a child-centred account of the family, that is a defense of the family by exclusive appeal to children’s interests. we do not know how many adequate parents there are around, and have no reason to think that we can identify t hem (especia l ly w it hout serious v iolat ions of persona l autonomy a nd intimacy). it may well be that childrearing arrangements other than the family would, on average, serve children’s interests optimally, even if the best imaginable way to bring up children is to give them adequate parents.2 But if there aren’t enough such parents, and if we cannot help enough people to become adequate parents, rearing children in the family may unjustifiably expose too many children to serious risks. the well-run orphanage, Kibbutz, or communal childrearing may be the best feasible arrangements as far as the children’s interests are concerned. if good versions of these arrangements— but not of the good family—are feasible on a sufficiently widespread scale, the family is to be rejected on child-centred grounds. there is a second reason why the institution of the family as is cannot be justified on child-centred grounds. if the family was merely meant to protect children’s interests we ought to give priority of access to parenting to people who would make best parents and who are willing to take over this role. this is clearly not the case, even allowing for the possibility that we cannot—usually—tell in advance who would make the best parent. But some cases are clear-cut: when a new child is born to parents who already have numerous children, and who we have reason to think are particularly bad at parenting, liberal states nevertheless grant custody to biological parents. at the same time people who are likely to make wonderful parents and who 2 veron ique Mu noz-Da rde a rg ued t hat t he ex istence of t he fa m i ly is especia l ly objectionable if we ought to g ive priorit y to t he worst of f: “whet her or not a g reat ma ny individuals are better off because of the existence of the family is irrelevant in settling whether the family would be one of the institutions of a just societ y. w hat matters is whether the existence of the family ensures that the least advantaged members of society are better off than they would be with its abolition”. her own answer to this question seems to be negative (Munoz-Darde 1998-9: 42). Is There a Right to Parent? 195 LEAP 3 (2015) are more than willing to raise children remain childless due to inability to procreate and the difficulties of adoption. More generally, custody rights follow biological connections, absent special circumstances. now, the family defended against the liberal challenge in Family values is different, perhaps very different, from the current legal institution of the family. Brighouse and Swift argue for more limited parental rights than what existing states recognize. nevertheless, they do want to reject, rather than bite the bullet of, the ‘best available parent’ possibility. in their own words: “would there be any thing w rong w ith a system that distributed children to adults in the way that maximized the realization of children’s interests, even if it left out some adults who would be willing, and adequately good, parents?” (Brighouse and Swift 2014: 86). they think there would be. not because children lack full moral status, which would make it unproblematic to allow parents’ own interest in authoritative relationships with children to determine what is a legitimate way of bringing them up.3 instead, they defend a dual-interest theory of what makes the family legitimate. the reason why— according to Brighouse and Swift—it is all right to settle for childrearing arrangements that are sub-optimal for children is the way in which childrearing makes a unique and crucial contribution to a fully f lourishing life. in their elaborate account of the value of parenting, Brighouse and Swift argue that adults have a fundamental moral right to be parents. the reason, in a nutshell, is that intimate and authoritative relationships with children a re uniquely va luable for most adu lts ; such a relat ionship is not “just another intimate relationship, valuable to both sides but substitutable for the adult by an additional relationship with a consenting adult” (Brighouse and Swift 2014: 88). rather, they have a different moral quality, make a different kind of contribution to the flourishing of adults, and so are not interchangeable with other relationships. Because childrearing makes a substantial and unique contribution to adults’ flourishing, adults are said to have an interest-based right to pursue such relationships. the unique value of parenting, according to Brighouse and Sw ift, resides in the combination of four features which characterize parent-child relationships. First, relationships between parents and children are structurally unequal, given children’s unavoidable, involuntary and asymmetrical dependency on the adults. By contrast, dependency in relationships between adults is less encompassing, often voluntary and more reciprocal. Second, parents are in charge of their children’s well-being and development to an extent to which people are not responsible for other individuals, with whom they stand in different types of relationships. to discharge this responsibility 3 “children are individuals distinct from their parents, individuals whose interests it is the state’s job to protect and promote” (Brighouse and Swift 2014: 5). 196 Anca Gheaus LEAP 3 (2015) pa rents need recou rse to coercion a nd ma n ipu lat ion. t h i rd, pa rents u navoidably shape t hei r ch i ld ren’s m i nds —t hat is, t hei r bel iefs a nd i nter e st s. Fi n a l l y, c h i ld r en a r e c a pa ble of lov i ng t hei r pa r ent s i n a sponta neous, u ncond it iona l a nd non-ref lect ive way t hat is not to be encountered in other kinds of loving. the first three features of the parent- child relationships generate the distinctive moral burdens of parenthood: responsibi lit y for t he wel l-being a nd development of indiv idua ls who are dependent on you and who cannot exit the relationship with you at will. according to Brighouse and Sw ift, it is va luable to meet t his cha llenge, as part of a process of self-knowledge and personal development that most people find uniquely fulfilling. the last feature of the parent-child relationship, that of spontaneous and unconditional love, points to the specific value of loving, and being loved by, children and to the source of hedonic value afforded by parenthood. it is thanks to these features that parenting is essential to the f lourishing of (most) adults. this account of parenting allows Brighouse and Swift to reject the ‘best ava i lable pa rent’ possibi lit y, because adu lts’ f unda menta l interest in parenting limits children’s entitlement to being raised by the best parent who is willing to take over this role: “within certain limits, adults’ interests in being a parent can trump children’s interests in having the best possible parents. no child has a right to be parented by the adult(s) who would do it best, nor do children as a whole have a right to the way of matching up children and parents that would be best for children overall. Both scenarios could leave perfectly competent parents missing out on the goods of parenting” (Brighouse and Swift 2014: 95). if Brighouse’s and Swift’s defense of a dual-interest account succeeds, then adults have a right to parent that is sui generis—i.e. fundamental, grounded in their ow n interests—rather than derivative from children’s ow n rights to protection and care. this would not change the fact that a right to parent is an anomaly by liberal lights: liberals acknowledge no other entitlement to exercise power over another individual legitimised in part by reference to an interest—no matter how important—of the one exercising power. But how could one go about rejecting this account of a sui generis right to parent? it does not look very promising to question the importance that raising children has for most of us. the evidence is very strong: most people want children, go ahead having them often in spite of serious adversity and in spite of the inevitable difficulties of the job, and many people agonize Is There a Right to Parent? 197 LEAP 3 (2015) for long periods of time over not being able to become parents. nor does it help to note that not all people believe that parenting makes such a great contribution to their f lourishing. as Brighouse and Swift themselves note, it is possible that the f lourishing of some, but not of all, people depends on being able to parent well (Brighouse and Swift 2014: xx). Some people may be unable to parent well (even with help) and therefore parenting will not contribute to their flourishing. other people’s lives may be so rich in alternative venues to flourishing, some of which incompatible with childrearing, that they will flourish best without rearing children. But neither of these facts mean that rearing children is not essential to the f lourishing of those of us who can parent well and whose f lourishing is not incompatible with parenting. More promising, one may believe that we do not have a right to pursue fully f lourishing lives—but merely to pursue sufficiently f lourishing lives. this is a plausible thought, in a world of competing claims over limited resources. on this view, would-be adequate and willing parents who miss the opportunity to rear children do not suffer from a rights violation provided they have other, adequate, opportunities to f lourish. an interesting way of answering this challenge would be to argue that, for people who can be adequate parents and who wish to parent, the failure to rear children somehow blocks other avenues to f lourishing. For instance, as in some fairy tales, grief of being childless may cast a thick shadow over every other joy, or take away the drive to engage in other projects, or otherwise undermine the ability to pursue other worthwhile goods. But this is not what Family values argues. another way to try to rebut this challenge would be to note that raising children is not merely a permissible—and very valuable—activity, but a morally mandatory one in the sense that each generation has a duty to bring up a minimum number of chi ldren to ensure t he ca re of t hose indiv idua ls in need of assista nce a nd t he cont inuat ion of some sor t or political society.4 in this case, parenting would be a very peculiar activity that not only makes an essential contribution to full f lourishing, but also enables individuals to f lourish by doing what was their duty to do in the first place. Perhaps there is a fundamental right to aim at full f lourishing, if thereby you also do your bit to discharge a collective duty. (Suppose, by analogy, that there was a duty to defend your country against unjust attack and that fighting wars was essential to most people’s full flourishing. would that be a reason to allow all would-be adequate soldiers to participate in self- defence, should they find themselves under unjust attack?) i do not know if the last argumentative strategy could succeed, but note that in an overly populated world like ours it is very likely that the number 4 i defend t h is v iew i n Gheaus (2015). For ot her a rg u ments why t here may be a (individual) duty to have children see Smilansky (1995). 198 Anca Gheaus LEAP 3 (2015) of children that we (collectively) have a duty to rear might well be much smaller than the number of would-be adequate parents. if it were not possible for all would-be adequate parents to parent-as-dutiful-behav ior, there cannot be a right to parent partly justified as dutiful behavior. above i have outlined what are, in my experience5, the most usual types of criticism leveled at Brighouse and Swift’s defense of a right to parent. i do not aim to draw a conclusion yet: on the one hand, in their favor speaks a very powerful widespread intuition that we have a right to rear children if we would parent them adequately. on the other hand, and against their view is the very plausible liberal belief that if you are denied a chance to parent either because alternative childrearing arrangements, or other would- be parents, would serve children’s interests even better, you do not suffer from the violation of a fundamental right.6 in the remainder of the paper i explore an intuitive way to adjudicate bet ween these t wo contradictor y beliefs, and in conclusion i suggest a way of reforming childrearing in line w ith the liberal stance, while also v indicating the intuition that adults have a right to involvement in childrearing (a right which nevertheless falls short of a right to parent). Much of the argumentative power of Brighouse and Swift’s defense of a dual-interest account of legitimate childrearing comes from their appeal to the unique value of parenting. in turn, this value derives from the unique combination of features displayed by parenting. Since their conclusion— t hat t here is a right to pa rent— coincides w it h a n a lready w idespread belief, it is tempting to think that a right to parent can really be justified by appeal to the combination of the four unique features of the parent-child relationship. and, since there is nothing quite like parenting in the world— that is, no other relationship that displays all of the features identified by Brighouse and Swift—this connection (between the four features and the right to parent) is difficult to test. But what if other social relationships also displayed the combination of these four features? would we respond with t he sa me intuit ion t hat one’s interest in such a relat ionship ca n pa r t ly justify one’s authority over another? consider the following imaginary situation, meant to show how intuitively extraordinary parents’ rights are over their children (at least in the absence of certain empirical assumptions that do not figure amongst the reasons that Brighouse and Swift provide in their case for the right to parent). imagine that, as a result of a natural cataclysm, a group of adult refugees reaches your country. they have nowhere else to go. you live under a just and benevolent 5 From numerous conferences and referee reports to work in which i describe (and endorse) their account. 6 For a convincing elaboration of this, see vallentyne (2003). Is There a Right to Parent? 199 LEAP 3 (2015) government that automatically grants the refugees the right to stay and settle down in the country and, in due course, to become citizens. as it happens, the refugees come from a very remote culture, described by anthropologists as ‘primitive’.7 they speak a language that nobody has heard of before and nobody understands, and they do not seem able to pronounce simple words in your own language. they cannot read or write, and have never been in contact with any technologically advanced civilization. they do not understand how any of the machines work, and understand complicated social rules even less. they appear scared of traffic and large crowds. their bodies are beautiful, fragile, relatively small, and unusually agile. they quickly acquire a wonderful reputation for being uncomplicated, trust y, direct, curious, affectionate and playful.8 For good reason, the belief spreads that having one of these refugees around can bring into your life a kind of joy and fun that nothing else could, and hence that an intimate relationship with one of them would be a special blessing. Moreover, these people are in much need of patient introduction into your own ways of living; somebody has to ta ke over t he job of socia li zing t hem. a nd you a re right to t hin k t hat engaging in such an extraordinary task would make a significant and unique contribution to your own personal development. now imagine that, after a few visits to the camp where the refugees get emergency lodging, you become particularly attached to one of them and from all you can tell the affection is reciprocal. your new friend responds to you with spontaneous trust, joy, and unconditional attachment. you would like to spend as much time as possible with this person. would it be a legitimate policy to allow you to lodge your new friend in your home and take upon yourself the entire responsibility, and with it the power, to ensure that her life goes well and that she acquires adequate knowledge of your society’s language, moral sensitivity and expectations, laws and customs such that she can, eventually, become an autonomous citizen? Moreover, would it be legitimate for you to have the authority to decide with whom she is allowed to spend time, and under what circumstances—i.e. to have the power to exclude others from having a relationship with her? would it be permissible if the state gave you a right, against all others, that they do not undermine your relationship with this person?9 7 Perhaps these anthropologists are objectionably condescending; i apologize on their behalf. 8 So they are, indeed, very close to how 17th and 18th century europeans imagined native inhabitants of america: they are a reincarnation of the bon sauvage. 9 this is a feature of the right to parent as defended by Brighouse and Swift: “those people given the job of parenting a particular child will have a right to parent that child in the weak sense that others will be under a duty not to undermine the relationship” (Brighouse and Swift 2014: 87). 200 Anca Gheaus LEAP 3 (2015) if you had the right to do these things, your relationship with the refugee wou ld acqu i re t he sa me combi nat ion of feat u res t hat cha r ac ter i z e relationships between parents and children, and which are said to generate a powerful interest in parenting and hence the right to parent. the relationship would be asymmetrical, and very difficult to exit for the refugee; it would involve significant moral responsibility on your part, given the power you would have to protect and shape the person in your care; and it would make possible a kind of spontaneous, unconditional and unref lective love that is not usually possible between adults. if people have a right to enjoy relationships that display the above combination of features, then you should be allowed to take control of the refugee’s life in the way in which parents control their children’s lives. yet, i contend that a policy allowing you to take control of the refugee’s life would be obv iously unjust to the refugee, your powerful interest to pursue intimacy with her notwithstanding, unless—for whatever reason— this kind of policy would best promote the interests of the refugees. the reason that would make it unjust is not its paternalism towards the refugees. indeed, the refugees in this example need paternalistic treatment if they are to survive at all in their new environment and if they are to become autonomous individuals with a chance to lead their own life in your society. the reason that would make it unjust for you to take control of her life is that, if it were possible to promote her current wel l-being a nd f uture autonomy in a different way—for instance by letting her reside in the refugee center, or by letting her move in with someone equally willing and better prepared to serve her interests—it would be unfair towards her to ask her to move in with you. this is a first, liberal response to the imaginary case. a different, related intuitive response is that, if it were possible to promote the refugee’s current well-being and future autonomy without locking her i nto a ny pa r t icu la r relat ionsh ip, t hen g iv i ng you— or a not her pr ivate individual—authority over her would be wrong because it would make her subject to (perhaps benevolent) domination. this is a republican response. you may think that, since you have such a powerful interest in sustaining the relationship with the refugee, you are entitled to the necessary means for protecting the relationship—including the right to prevent others from forming and sustaining a close relationship with her. But a parental-like power to exclude other individuals in this way comes at too high a moral cost to the refugee, especially if is not necessary for optimal protection of her own interests. the fact that you have relational interests at stake here does not seem to make any difference. Since the well-being and development into autonomous individuals of the refugees is a matter of public responsibility, social arrangements should Is There a Right to Parent? 201 LEAP 3 (2015) be sought that can best ensure meeting this responsibility. ‘Best’ may be interpreted as either ‘well-being maximization’ or ‘ensuring a certain level of wel l-being in a non-dominat ing ma nner’. Possibly, concern for t he refugee’s well-being and respect for their moral status will indicate that they ought to live together with many other people: some fellow refugees and some of your co-citizens whose main occupation will be to provide welfare and integration to the refugees. or, perhaps, it would be best for them to live in the home of private individuals—call them ‘hosts’—but have access to a broad range of intimate and caring relationships with many of your (socially and emotionally competent) co-citizens, without needing their host’s approval. in any case, it seems that it is exclusively the refugee’s interests that determine the ideal way of socializing them: the host’s ow n interest in pursuing a relationship with one of the refugees (even if this relationship was highly, and uniquely, valuable to the host) does not seem to do any work in settling the matter. this story is obviously meant to provide a close analogy to the situation of parents and children. the two cases share the features which, according to Brighouse and Swift, generate parental rights. if your intuition is that these features cannot justify parental-like authority over the refugees, then probably they are also unable to generate a right to parent as defended in Family Values. the same hypothetical case triggers a second intuitive reaction—at least, on my side. the fact that your interest in having an intimate and authoritative relationship with the refugee is irrelevant to your having rights over her. this does not mean that you do not have a right to pursue a long-lasting, intimate relationship with the refugee. your interest in this unique relationship is, i assume, powerful enough to generate a right to pursue it. you may spend some time with her every day and provide constant company and guidance to her. you may decide to become one of the people whose main occupation is to work in the refugee home part-time or full-time until she is sufficiently autonomous to take charge of her own life and leave the refugee home. while the state would be wrong to allow would-be competent hosts to assume parental-like authority over one of the refugees, it would also be wrong to set up an institution of socializing refugees that denies citizens a chance to develop close and benefiting relationships with the refugees. if the citizens really have a powerful interest in entering and sustaining close relationships with the refugees, then it would be arbitrary to exclude some from having access to such relationships—assuming the relationships do not set back the refugee’s interests—in order to benefit others. note that the pursuit of an intimate caring relationship with a person does not require a right to exclude other individuals from pursuing such relationships with her—it 202 Anca Gheaus LEAP 3 (2015) requires only that nobody else have a right to arbitrarily interrupt your relationship with this person. (this is of course consistent with the possibility that the highest possible degree of intimacy, as well as the most secure kind of intimacy, requires the exclusion of intimacy with others.) Perhaps the analog y carries over, again, to the case of childrearing. Parental authority—as we have it and as it seems10 to be defended in Family Values—comprises a right to exclude others from having close relationships with one’s child for reasons other than the protection of the child’s interest. and, as we have seen, a right to parent is justified by Brighouse and Swift by reference to the unique value of relationships of intimacy and authority with children. yet, it seems to me, intimacy, more than authority, contributes to the value of the adult-child relationship. this is so especially once we acknowledge that being in a sustained intimate relationship with a child involves considerable responsibilit y on the part of an adult even if that adult does not play a full parental role. indeed, the justification of a right to parent starts from the observation that for “most people, intimate relationships with others are essential for their lives to have meaning” (Brighouse and Swift 2014: 87). and progresses by noting the unique value of parent-child intimacy. Similarly, it is appeal to intimacy with a child that most plausibly explains the common intuition that people ought to be free to parent and the possibility that some people’s f lourishing could be irremediably undermined if they had no children in their lives. But the most problematic element of the parental right, in a liberal perspective, is the authoritative, not the intimate, side of the relationship. if it is possible to disentangle intimacy and authority in childrearing—both analytically and practically—the intuitive support for a right to rear children might be salvaged without need of taking exception from liberal beliefs. therefore, i suggest that Brighouse and Swift’s case for a fundamental right to parent is only partially successful: it fails to show that appeal to adults’ interests does any work in establishing a right to control the child. But it can show how adults’ interest in relationships with children grounds an associative right: adults whose company would not be detrimental to children’s interests have a right to seek and maintain close and caring relationships with children. yet the claim to a right to control a child’s life must be grounded exclusively in the child’s interest, in which case there is 10 “Seems” because Brighouse and Swift defend a child-centred view with respect the content of parental rights. yet, they also say that the right to parent involves that others are “under a dut y not to undermine the relationship” (Brighouse and Sw ift 2014: 87). But my making close friends with my neighbor’s child can—if the neighbor has no power to interrupt the relationship—undermine the child’s relationship with her parent. Is There a Right to Parent? 203 LEAP 3 (2015) no sui generis right to parent.11 it is possible that more people will want to reject the pertinence of the analogy between welcoming refugees and engaging in childrearing, than to refute the conclusions i draw about the just treatment of the refugees. to do this, they would likely point to some empirical features that set apart parenting from my imagined example. unless they are adopted, children are never complete strangers to their parents or at least to their gestational mother, in whose body they come into existence and develop for a while. Many believe that parents are inevitably more attached to their own offspring t ha n t hey ca n ever be to ot her chi ldren (a lt hough t here is a debate on whether the explanation is to be found in the fact of gestation or in genetic relatedness; if such special attachment exists, i think that it springs from gestation12). this alleged fact contributes to the belief that, in general, (biolog ica l) pa rents ma ke t he best pa rents for pa r t icu la r chi ldren. So, perhaps, you are inclined to think that, should babies come into the world unrelated to a ny pa r t icu la r indiv idua ls—shou ld t hey, for insta nce, be brought by storks—we ought indeed to set up childrearing practices that serve their interests as well as possible, including the possibility of allowing the best available parents to rear them. But, in fact, babies come into the world from the bodies of other people and so you may also think that this fact sett les t he quest ion of what chi ldrea ring pract ices ser ve best t he children’s interests (the family) and who are the best parents (procreators). (For instance, you may be convinced by evolutionary biology.) therefore, the beliefs that the family is legitimate and that procreators have a (non-fundamental) right to rear their own children—that is, support for the status quo—can be compatible with a child-centred account of who has the right to assume authority over children. the compatibility depends on the above-mentioned beliefs that procreators are, on average, able to love their children best and that a child is best off in the custody of the person most able to love her.13 if childrearing within the family really is in the vast majority of children’s best interest, and if the beliefs concerning procreation and love are true, then it may be fine to settle for minor reforms of the family. But, contra Brighouse and Swift’s account, this would be based entirely on the child’s interest. 11 that is, as far as Brighouse and Swift’s argument goes. For a different defense of a right to parent as part of a dual interest account of just child-rearing see clayton (2006). 12 i discuss t his in Gheaus (2012) where i a na lyze, more genera lly, t he normative import of gestation for a right to rear a particular child. 13 For more on this, see Munoz-Darde (1998-9: 45-46). For a child-centred account that is compatible with the status quo of raising children in the family, and perhaps with the raising of children in their biological family (as a default) see archard (2003). 204 Anca Gheaus LEAP 3 (2015) BiBlioGraPhy archard, D., 2003: Children, Family and the State, london: ashgate Publishing. Brighouse, h. and Swift, a., 2014: Family Values. The Ethics of Parent-Child Relationships, Princeton: Princeton university Press. clayton, M., 2006: Justice and Legitimacy in Upbringing, oxford: oxford university Press. Gheaus, a., 2012: “the right to Parent one’s Biological Baby”, Journal of Political Philosophy 20: 432-455 — 2015: “could there ever be a Duty to have children?”, in Permissible Progeny, ed. S. Brennan, S. hannan and r. vernon, 87-106, oxford: oxford university Press.Munoz-Darde, v., 1998-9: “is the Family to be abolished then?”, Proceedings of Aristotelian Society 99: 37-56. Smila nsk y, S., 1995: “is there a Mora l obligation to have children? ”, Journal of Applied Philosophy 12: 41–53. vallentyne, P., 2003: “the rights and Duties of childrearing”, William and Mary Bill of Rights Journal 11: 991-1009. LEAP 3 (2015) Why the Family?1 LuAR A FERR ACiOLi University of Amsterdam Abstract a mong t he most pressi ng ph i losoph ic a l quest ion s occ upy i ng t hose interested in the ethics of the family is why should parents, as opposed to charit y workers or state officials, raise children? in their recent Family values, Brighouse and Swift have further articulated and strengthen their own justification of the parent-child relationship by appealing to its crucial role in enabling the child’s proper development and in allowing parents to play a valuable fiduciary role in the lives of children. in this paper, i argue that the set of interests Brighouse and Swift identif y as necessary for the justification of the family fails to account for the different stages and the d i f ferent c u lt u r a l set t i ngs t hat ma rk t he pa rent-ch i ld relat ion sh ip. in particular, i ague that their justification of the family fails to satisf y the following two desiderata: (i) that the justification for the parent-child relat ion sh ip shou ld idea l ly t r ack t he good-ma k i ng feat u re (s) of t he relationship that extend across its entire history, and (ii) such justification should ideally explain what is valuable about the parent-child relationship in both liberal and non-liberal family contexts. in light of my critique, i sketch an alternative account of family values, one that appeals directly to the special mode of caring we see in the parent-child relationship, a form of caring that is certainly present in non-liberal societies and that typically extends across a lifetime. Keywords: family, children, parents, paternalism, autonomy, love, Brighouse, Swift “Ser mãe é padecer no paraíso”2 1 a previous version of this paper was presented in the Department of law in Pompeu Fabra university in Barcelona, where i received extremely helpful feedback. i am especially grateful to Pablo de lora, Serena olsaretti, andrew williams and an anonymous referee for this journal. i also would like to thank ryan cox and eric Schliesser for helpful discussions on the topic. 2 Popular Brazilian expression: “Being a mother is like suffering in paradise” (My translation from Portuguese). 206 Luara Ferracioli LEAP 3 (2015) 1. introDuction a mong t he most cha l leng ing phi losophica l quest ions concerning t he ethics of the family is why parents, rather than charity workers, or state officials, say, should raise children. w hat justifies the family as the best arrangement for the rearing of citizens who are not yet in a position to secure their own current and future interests? one a nswer to t his quest ion is t hat t he pa rent-chi ld relat ionship is justified by some fundamental interest that adults have with regard to their biological children, such as the interest in the product of their gestational labor or genetic investment.3 another approach to this question starts from the assumption that children are extremely vulnerable and dependent and that their interests should exhaust any theory attempting to justify what is, at its core, a coercive, and t herefore mora lly suspect, t y pe of intimate relationship.4 this child centred view of family relationships is based on the contention that the parent-child relationship can only be justified on the assumption that no other social arrangement could do a better job at securing the core interests of children. were this empirical assumption to become unsustainable, adults would cease to have a prima facie right to parent. an alternative to both these views is the “dual-interest” account of child rearing.5 those articulating this position have appealed to both the interests of children in being raised by parents and the interests of parents in raising children. the fundamental commitment of the dual-interest view is that the interests on both sides have to be balanced out and that good enough parents retain their right to parent even if it turns out that other social arrangements would do a better job at protecting and promoting the interests of children. harr y Brighouse and adam Sw ift have recently further articulated and strengthened their own version of the dual interest account by defending the position that the parent-child relationship is justified by its crucial role in securing the child’s proper development and in enabling the flourishing of many adults (Brighouse and Swift 2014).6 in this essay, i argue that the specific set of interests Brighouse and Swift identify as grounds for the justification of the parent-child relationship fail to account for the different stages and the different cultural settings that mark the family. in particular, i argue that their account of family values 3 For a genetic account, see hall (1999). For a gestational account, see narayan (1999). 4 the coercive aspect of the relationship here is a result of the fact that due to the lack of a sufficient degree of autonomy, children cannot typically consent to partaking in the relationship. For child-centred views, see Blustein (1982); vallentyne (2003). 5 See Brighouse and Swift (2006); clayton (2006); Macleod (2010); Gheaus (2012). 6 See also rawls (1999: 265). Why the Family? 207 LEAP 3 (2015) fails to satisfy the following two desiderata: (i) that the justification for the parent-child relationship should ideally track the good-making feature(s) of t he relat ionsh ip t hat ex tend across its ent i re h istor y, a nd (i i) such justification should ideally explain what is valuable about the parent-child relationship in both liberal and non-liberal family contexts. in light of my critique, i sketch an alternative account of what is special about the family, one that appeals directly to the special mode of caring we see in the parent- child relationship, a form of caring that is certainly present in non-liberal families and that typically extends across a lifetime. the discussion w i l l be st r uctured as fol lows. in sect ion 2, i brief ly rehearse Brighouse and Swift’s arguments for their dual-interest account of child rearing. in section 3, i motivate two desiderata for a successful theory of what justifies the parent-child relationship and argue that Brighouse and Swift’s account, as it stands, cannot meet them. in sections 4 and 5, i sketch an alternative justification for the parent-child relationship that overcomes the challenges raised in the previous section, and briefly discuss some of its implications. 2. BriGhouSe anD SwiFt on FaMily valueS let us start our inquiry by briefly rehearsing Brighouse and Swift’s argument in favor of taking the family to be the best institutional setting for the rearing of children.7 according to the authors, there are a number of interests on the part of children that ground their right to be raised by at least one parent.8 First, children are highly dependent on adults for their most basic emotional and biological needs. Second, children are profoundly vulnerable to the quality of other people’s decisions, and the sort of paternalistic treatment they are subjected to in childhood can significantly impact how well their lives go as a whole. third, children are capable of eventually developing a capacity for autonomy a nd so a re sig nif ica nt ly dif ferent f rom ot her v u lnerable indiv idua ls who w i l l never become capable of attending to t heir ow n interests. Brighouse and Sw ift believe t hat, when ta ken toget her, t hese interests give children an overarching interest to be ‘manipulated’ and ‘coerced’ into doing what is good for them, or what will prepare them for becoming autonomous later on in their lives (Brighouse and Swift 2014: 62-70). 7 like Brighouse and Swift (2014: Xi), i will employ the concept of “the family” to refer to the parent-child relationship in the context of this discussion. note that i do not take a stand on whether or not other intimate relationships should also be picked out by this concept. 8 For Brighouse and Swift (2014: 53-54), a has a right to X, when a’s interest in doing X or having X is weighty enough that it gives rise to a duty on the part of others that they allow a to do X or that they provide a with X. Moreover, whether an interest in doing X or having X is weighty enough to give rise to a duty on others will depend on the importance of X and the costs that come with the provision of X. 208 Luara Ferracioli LEAP 3 (2015) it is certainly true that children’s lack of autonomy and vulnerability makes it appropriate that others act paternalistically towards them, but there is still a further question as to why such paternalism should come primarily from adults acting within the context of a private and intimate family relationship.9 For Brighouse and Swift, the answer lies in the fact that such relationships are typically marked by love and that love renders the exercise of paternalism more effective (Brighouse and Swift 2014: 71). the underly ing empirical assumption here is that a lov ing relationship between a child and a competent parent allows the latter to exercise authority with knowledge of the former’s unique dispositions, and with the sort of spontaneity and care that encourages the child to see the parent as her central disciplinary model (Brighouse and Swift 2014: 73). For the authors, the quality time which parent and child typically spend together, and the intimacy that develops as a result, are so central to the effective exercise of paternalism, that there cannot be many of these relationships in a child’s life (Brighouse and Swift 2014: 73).10 if Brighouse and Swift are correct, we now have the beginning of a story that purports to explain what is so special about the parent-child relationship: I. children need paternalistic treatment to enjoy the goods of childhood and to develop the capacities they need later on in adulthood. ii. Such paternalistic treatment will be more effective or successful if exercised in a context of an intimate loving relationship. iii. competent parents can typically exercise paternalism in a context of an intimate loving relationship. conclusion: children have a basic interest in being cared for by at least one, but not too many, competent parents. So far, so good, but this does not yet give us a dual-interest account. in order to explain why it is good for adults to parent children even when children could conceivably fare better under alternative arrangements, we need to say something about the interest parents have in playing their own role in the relationship. For Brighouse and Swift, adults have a strong interest in playing the fiduciary role that secures the child’s present and future well- being. that is, the interest that some adults have in parenting is precisely to be in a loving relationship where they can act paternalistically towards a child, guaranteeing her basic needs and seeing to it that she develops the cognitive, emotional, physical, and moral resources she needs to become an autonomous person later on in her life (Brighouse and Swift 2014: 86-90). 9 Brighouse and Swift (2014: 67) write that “paternalism involves manipulating or coercing another person with the purpose of serving her good”. 10 note that Brighouse and Swift (2014: 70) also recognize that the exercise of paternalism should be constrained by the child’s stage of development. Why the Family? 209 LEAP 3 (2015) here then is the final justificatory step taken by Brighouse and Swift in favor of their dual-interest account of child rearing: i v. Some competent adu lts a re not on ly capable of exercisi ng paternalism, but have an interest in playing such a fiduciary role within the context of a loving relationship.11 conclusion: all children have a strong interest in being cared for by at least one, but not many competent parents, and some adults have a strong interest in parenting. these interests are sufficiently weighty, and the costs involved in securing them are sufficiently reasonable, so as to ground the right of children to have at least one parent, and the right of competent adults to parent. the ba la ncing of t hese interests a lso just if ies t he fa mi ly as t he best socio- institutional arrangement for the rearing of children.12 3. two DeSiDerata: continuity anD PluraliSM in the previous section, we learnt that for Brighouse and Swift, the need for paterna lism w it hin t he contex t of a lov ing relat ionship u lt imately grounds the right of children to have at least one parent and that the same paterna lism g rounds a (condit iona l, limited) right of adu lts to pa rent children. the aim of this section is to take a step back and think about what we want a theory of family values to deliver, as well as evaluate how Brighouse and Swift’s dual-interest account fares with regards to such theoretical aims. to begin with, Brighouse and Swift’s fiduciary account certainly points in the right direction by starting with the recognition that children typically fare better if they can count on at least one competent adult to actively attend to their well being. the account also seems to capture something important about how there can be a weighty interest on the part of adults to be in a relationship with children that cannot be replaced by other kinds of intimate relationships, such as relationship with a pet, or a friend. But do Brighouse and Swift really get to the heart of the matter when they point to the interest of children in being subjected to this sort of loving paternalism and the interests of parents in exercising loving authority as part of the parental role? that is, do they succeed in identifying the most basic property or set of properties that justify the existence of the family even in a context where other actual and conceivable arrangements could do a better job at securing the interests of children? 11 as Brighouse and Swift (2014: 86) put it, “[i]t cannot be substituted by other forms of relationship, and it contributes to the parent’s well-being so substantially, and in a manner so congruent with the interests of children, that it grounds (a conditional, limited) right to parent”. 12 For the rights theory endorsed by the authors, see supra-note 8. 210 Luara Ferracioli LEAP 3 (2015) in the remainder of this section, i argue that although Brighouse and Swift’s fiduciary account helps us make much progress on the ethics of the family, it does not, as it stands, meet two important desiderata. First, their account fails to explain what is special about the parent-child relationship once the child is capable of attending to her own present and future well- being. it therefore fails to explain what is good or valuable about children having parents and parents having children across a lifetime. let us call this the “continuity desideratum”. Second, by arguing that part of what justifies the fiduciary role of the parent is its ability to secure the child’s future autonomy, their account fails to justify the parent-child relationship outside a liberal family context, where parents might lack the disposition in seeing to it that their adult child becomes capable of forming and pursuing her own conception of the good. let us call this the “pluralism desideratum”. i will discuss each desideratum in turn. 3.1. Continuity let me begin by motivating the continuity desideratum, which is that, all else being equal, a successful justification for the child-parent relationship should also be able to explain why it is good that parents have children and children have parents not only during the former’s childhood but also across a lifetime. to make sense of this idea, let us imagine a world that is very similar to ours but where society has structured procreation and parenting differently, and where only elderly members of societ y become parents and where children are conceived and gestated in high-tech government laboratories. let us also imagine that the rationale for this arrangement is efficiency since citizens are more productive if they spend their adult lives fully engaged in the workforce and then later in life, once they have retired, they will have more time to invest in their parental role. Finally, let us assume that quality of life and life expectancy are such that children typically have at least one sufficiently healthy parent during childhood and adolescence, but typically not during their adulthood. as becomes clear, this society is one in which both parent’s and children’s interests, as identified by Brighouse and Swift, are fully met but where it seems that something deeply valuable is lost. what is lost, i take it, is the value for both parent and child in enjoying an intimate and loving relationship that typically extends across different phases of their lives, and that provides the child with the on-going benefit of being subjected to an intense and robust mode of caring by the parent (i will defend this claim in more detail in the following section). if i am right that the parent-child relationship retains its value even when there is no more need for the exercise of paternalism on the part of the parent, then we should ideally aim for a justification of the family Why the Family? 211 LEAP 3 (2015) that does not depend on features that are only present in childhood, but that can explain what is valuable about the parent-child relationship as it extends across time.13 at this stage, a proponent of Brighouse and Swift’s fiduciary account might endorse the continuity desideratum, but deny that the authors fail to meet it in their own justification of the family. the response here would be to appeal to the fact that Brighouse and Swift also give a lot of weight to the role of love in their discussion, and that as a result of love’s continuity, their fiduciary account will hold no matter which developmental stage or life phase parties find themselves in. this would indeed be a charitable reading of their discussion, and later i sketch an account that does appeals to the role of love in explaining what is so special about the parent-child relationship. however, as it stands, it is not clear that this interpretation is available to Brighouse and Swift because their account of why adults have an interest in parenting appeals to the interest that parents have in exercising loving authority over the lives of children. indeed, for Brighouse and Swift, love comes in by playing an important, yet supportive role, in the effective exercise of paternalism.14 as they explain: “the fiduciary aspect remains central. Grandparents, or parent’s friends, or nannies, can have close relationships with children, and when they go well, those relationships will be conducive to the child’s interests and valuable to the adults too. reading bedtime stories, providing meals, and so on, will be contributing to the well-being of both. Still, there’s something distinctively valuable about being the person who not only does those things oneself but has the responsibility to make sure they get done, sometimes by others, and the authority to decide quite how they get done” (Brighouse and Swift 2014: 93). But even if the above passage was somewhat misleading and it was true t hat Brighouse a nd Sw if t were prima ri ly interested in love itself, t hey would still need a further argument to justify the interest that adults have in parenting given that adults can enjoy relationships of love and intimacy with people other than their children. the challenge here is that love per se cannot get a dual-interest account off the ground because such an account is aimed at explaining what is special about the parent-child relationship in particular, not loving relationships more generally. 13 to be sure, as t he child goes t hrough dif ferent developmenta l stages, t here a re contingent features of each stage that will provide distinct sources of pleasure to the parent. however, it does not follow from this fact that the identit y of the relationship changes so dramatically that what made it valuable when the child was a toddler is no longer present when she is middle-aged. 14 as Brighouse a nd Sw if t (2014: 92) put it, “[t]he relationship as a whole, w it h its particular intimate character and the responsibility to play the specific fiduciary role for the person with whom one is intimate in that way, is what adults have an interest in”. 212 Luara Ferracioli LEAP 3 (2015) Before i move on to the second desideratum, let me dispel one potential concern with the discussion so far. the concern might be that the continuity desideratum does not apply to Brighouse and Swift’s fiduciary account because theirs is an exercise in political philosophy, not value theory. Perhaps what these authors are ultimately interested in doing, so the concern goes, is justif ying a relationship where one party lacks exit options and is wholly dependent on the other party for having her basic interests protected and promoted. what motivates the concern here is that the authors might not be answering the question of what is valuable about the parent-child relationship tout ensemble, but rather explaining why it is permissible for adults to enter and maintain intimate relationships with non-consenting children. one reason why this response is unsatisfactory is that the inability of the child to exit a parent-child relationship is not a necessary feature of this sort of relationship and that it is possible for there to be intimate relationships where the child actually enjoys exit options. these are, for instance, relationships where a parent lacks custody rights over the child and decides to give the child a lot of space to choose whether or not, and to what extend, to partake in the relationship. one might think that the enjoyment of exit options on the part of the child dispels the need for justification in such cases, but i take it that the degree of intimacy involved at all stages of the relationship, and the mere possibility that society could be arranged differently, suffice for making the parent-child relationship, at its most general level, proper subject of philosophical justification. it would therefore be unsatisfying if Brighouse and Sw ift were solely in the business of explaining why it is permissible for there to be relationships between competent parents and children where the latter have no prospect of exiting the relationship. 3.2. Pluralism let me now turn to the second desideratum, which is the claim that a successful justification for the parent-child relationship must also be able to justify such relationships in non-liberal family contexts. as mentioned earlier, Brighouse and Swift believe that one of the reasons children need parents is that within the context of an intimate loving relationship, parents have an interest to ensure that children acquire the skills they need in order to become autonomous later on in their lives. For them, this priv ileged position on the part of parents goes as far as to give parents “a duty to try and ensure that the child w ill become an autonomous agent, someone capable of judging, and acting on her judgement, about her own interests” (Brighouse and Swift 2014: 90). Before i ex pla in why t his focus on autonomy is problemat ic for t he fiduciary account, let me endorse the more general claim that children have Why the Family? 213 LEAP 3 (2015) a weighty interest in becoming self-determining in adulthood. let me also note that such capacity for autonomy can be cashed out in different ways a nd elsewhere i have a rg ued t hat chi ldren have a weight y interest in developing some basic agential skills, such as critical thinking, self-esteem and imagination precisely in order to make life choices that sufficiently track their own values and aspirations, as opposed to the values and aspirations of their parents, community leaders and religious authorities (Ferracioli 2015).15 i a m t herefore in deep ag reement w it h Brighouse a nd Sw if t in thinking that something goes wrong when children fail to acquire the skills they need to live adult lives that are genuinely their own. however, as i see it, Brighouse and Swift are too quick in linking this particular interest on the part of children with the fiduciary role of parents. that is, they are too quick in assuming that parents are typically capable and willing to ensure that their child develop the agential skills needed to ma ke t heir ow n life choices as opposed to choices t hat blind ly fol low religious tradition or cultural expectations (Ferracioli and terlazzo 2014; Ferracioli 2015). indeed, it is a well-know n sociological fact that many parents in non-liberal cultural contexts do not value autonomy themselves and actually want their child to uncritically endorse what they take to be deep truths about the world. the result here is that Brighouse and Swift’s inclusion of the capacity for autonomy in the list of interests that ground a dual-interest account makes it the case that only autonomy-promoting parents have a right to parent, because only they have the disposition to protect the interest that the child has in becoming autonomous, and so to protect one of the interests that, according to the fiduciary account, justify the family in the first place. Proponents of the fiduciar y account might respond by resisting the pluralism desideratum, and by arguing that in fact only parents who are committed to the development of autonomy have a right to parent because only they are genuinely in a position to secure the very weighty interest of chi ldren in becoming suf f icient ly self-determining. But t his response wou ld deny t he obv ious a nd mora l ly releva nt fact t hat outside libera l family contexts, parents still manage to enjoy a great degree of intimacy, love and affection with their children, and that the lives of all parties go much better as a result of partaking in such loving relationships.16 Moreover, this response also fails to see that the right of children in becoming sufficiently 15 See also Meyers (1987). 16 note that this position is compatible with the claim (which i do not make here) that, all else being equal, being raised by liberal parents is superior to being raised by authoritarian ones. these are compatible claims because all we need for justifying the parent-child relationship is that the relationship meets some sufficiency requirement. outside the enterprise of justification, we can certainly rank styles of parenting according to some independent moral criteria. 214 Luara Ferracioli LEAP 3 (2015) autonomous can instead correlate with a duty on the part of the state to create a neutral system of compulsory public education where children acquire the agential skills required for the exercise of autonomy later on in their lives (i return to this point later).17 4. Parental love anD the GooD liFe in the prev ious section, i argued that the best candidate for a theor y of what justifies the family should not appeal solely to features of childhood but rather to features of the parent-child relationship that extend across the entirety of the relationship. i have also argued that such an account should explicitly include the interest of adults in entering into intimate and loving relationship with children irrespective of a lack of disposition on their part to see to it that their child becomes sufficiently self-determining. in this section, i sketch an account that can successfully meet these two desiderata. So what is this valuable feature that both parents and children have an interest in? the answer is actually quite simple: a robust form of caring, or what is commonly (but mistakenly) known as “unconditional love”. to begin with, let me make the obvious point that strictly unconditional love is neither feasible nor desirable. it is not feasible because there can be psychological limits on the human capacity to love when love is reciprocated with physical violence, abuse or complete disregard to one’s well being. even a small child might stop loving a parent when the love she gives is reciprocated with extreme forms of violence and abuse. But even if it is possible for some people to love unconditionally, it still not something they have an interest in doing simply because unconditional love is not on the whole desirable. indeed, it is important for person’s self-respect and self- esteem that they place certain minimum conditions on the giving of love, such as the condition that they be treated with some degree of respect and generosity, and that their beloved will, for instance, not offend against the most basic demands of morality. the thought here is that even a devoted parent should try hard to stop loving an adult child who turns out to be an unrepentant mass murderer. So if unconditional love is neither feasible nor desirable, what kind of love do children and parents have an interest in? and what makes this love sufficiently distinct from other kinds of love that allows us to get a dual- interest account off the ground? the love both children and parents have an interest in is parental love, which is of such magnitude and robustness that it typically differs from other kinds of love. 17 For t he role of compu lsor y public education in t he fostering of autonomy, see Ferracioli and terlazzo (2014); Ferracioli (2015). Why the Family? 215 LEAP 3 (2015) let me start with a rough definition of parental love: a type of love whereby the agent cares so much about the good of her beloved, that she is robustly disposed to take on a great deal of personal cost in order to advance the good of her beloved. if i am right that parental love can be so defined, then children have an interest in being cared for by parents as opposed to charity workers or state officials because they have an interest in being at the receiving end of a mode of caring that is of significant magnitude and robustness (Ferracioli 2015). that is, children have an interest in an intimate relationship with an adult who cares so much that the child’s life goes well, that she is disposed to take on a great deal of costs to advance the child’s interests over the course of that relationship. Moreover, children have an interest that such disposition on the part of the parent remains robust across time and counter-factual worlds.18 a child who enjoys parental love, so this view goes, will continue to enjoy it as she becomes older and even if the sacrifices involved become extraordinary. to illustrate the point, we need only think of the hardships we might encounter in our adult lives, and the people most likely to continue advancing our interests should such hardships arise. if, for instance, we acquired a severe illness that made us incapable of attending to our own basic needs, or if we became so depressed that we could hardly respond to the world around us, the people most likely to continuously advance our interests would be our parents, not friends or lovers. the same is true of childhood. charity and orphanage workers might be able to adequately meet the basic needs of children under their care, but they will not move town or country in order to ensure that a sick child will get a special kind of medical treatment.19 they are also unlikely to spend a l l of t heir discret iona r y t ime invent ing ga mes a nd act iv it ies so as to continuously stimulate a child who suffers from autism spectrum disorder, for instance. and in any case, they will certainly not spend their whole lives trying to find a child that has disappeared. charity and orphanage workers will of course typically do what morality or their job description require— the trouble is that, at times, human beings, being the vulnerable creatures they are, need much more than that.20 if i am right that children have an interest in being the recipient of parental love so that across a lifetime, they will enjoy a caring relationship 18 For the notion of a modally demanding value, see Pettit (2008). 19 For a defence of the claim that children can have all their interests secured in an orphanage, see cowden (2012). 20 For a more detailed discussion of this claim, see Ferracioli (2014). 216 Luara Ferracioli LEAP 3 (2015) robustly, then the next question is: why do parents have an interest in providing such robust mode of caring? that is, what do parents have to ga in by being in a relat ionship where t hey a re disposed to ta ke on so much personal cost for the sake of someone else? as i see it, the interest that parents have in the relationship is precisely to enjoy t he mora l va lue of lov ing someone so deeply t hat one becomes sig nif ica nt ly disposed to adva nce her good in ways compa rable to t he advancement of their own good. indeed, the interest in parenting is nothing above and beyond an interest in being in a relationship where one cares so deeply about how well someone else’s life goes that one is disposed to take on the sort of costs that not even morality can demand from moral agents.21 this sort of disposition for a deep mode of caring within the context of an intimate relationship is a great source of meaning—it enriches the lives of adults significantly, despite the fact (or perhaps even partly because) life often feels like “suffering in heaven”. in the previous section, i noted that a general interest in love would not get us a dual-interest account off the ground because adults can partake in a myriad of loving relationships, such as the relationship one has with a f riend or lover. a nd if i a m right t hen, why t hin k t hat f riendships a nd romantic relationships cannot exhibit the sort of robust care we see with the parent-child relationship? at this stage, it is important to clarify exactly what the shape of the claim is. i have not argued that parents necessarily feel parental love. we know all too well that some parents do not experience robust modes of caring. i have also not argued that other relationships necessarily fail to exhibit the features of parental love so far discussed. it is certainly conceivable that some romantic relationships and friendships might give rise to equally robust modes of caring—it is just that they are significantly less likely to do so. indeed, while it is true that some extraordinary individuals might make all sorts of significant sacrifices to advance the good of a friend, friendships are typically marked by more reasonable forms of cost-taking and by less robust modes of caring. the same is true of romantic relationships. while some people would stick with a romantic partner under almost any circumstances, most romantic relationships are contingent on many facts remaining true, such as shared interests, physical attractiveness, financial stability, loyalty, and so and so forth. the modes of love we see in these other loving relationships are therefore not typically as robust as parental love. For those adults who want to maximize their chance of experiencing robust forms of caring, there 21 and of course, such disposition for caring needs to be expressed in the context of an intimate relationship because the relationship itself provides the necessary conditions for effectively acting on the disposition when the need arises. Why the Family? 217 LEAP 3 (2015) will be an interest in parenting. a strong interest in caring about someone else robustly within the context of an intimate relationship then gets us a dual-interest off the ground. 5. DiSPerSeD authority anD the GooD oF chilDren in the previous section i sketched an account that meets the two desiderata motivated earlier: it captures the vulnerability of childhood but it is not exhausted by it. it also makes sense of parent-child relationships in non- l ibera l fa m i ly contex ts, where pa rents m ig ht lack t he w i l l i ng ness i n seeing to it that their child becomes sufficiently autonomous but still have the disposition to take on a great deal of costs to advance many of her other interests. Before concluding, i shall briefly discuss some of the implications of justifying the parent-child relationship by appealing to the robust mode of caring constitutive of parental love. one implication is that a parental love account can leave open how much authority parents can legitimately exercise in a context of the parent-child relationship. So while Brighouse and Swift vindicated the current model of parental authority by arguing that parents had an interest in exercising authority over children, the account sketched above would be compatible with a world where parents exercised much less authorit y over children, and where governments would exercise much more through the provision of a myriad of compulsory public services. For those who worry about growing levels of child obesity and the ill effects on children of the anti-vaccination movement, for instance, the parental love account comes with the benefit of not giving parental authority any justificatory role, and so being much more congenial to state interference in areas such as children’s diet and immunization, for instance.22 a second, and related, implication is that a parental love account does not make the right to parent conditional on a parents’ ability to foster a capacit y for autonomy. it therefore endorses the claim that the right of children to become autonomous correlate instead with an obligation on the part of the state to create a neutral system of compulsory public education where children can develop the agential skills required for autonomy without being steered towards any particular conception of the good (Ferracioli and terlazzo 2014; Ferracioli 2015). now, of course, it is true that such an account 22 indeed, whilst Brighouse and Swift discussion leads to the odd result that adults who do not value autonomy lack the right to parent, a parental love account can recognize that their interest in parenting is on a par with the interest of those who do value autonomy, while still limiting the ability of all parents to deny their children the opportunity to acquire the agential skills required for autonomy. 218 Luara Ferracioli LEAP 3 (2015) would still make the right to parent conditional on the parent not actively interfering with the fostering of autonomy by the state, and so there would still be a negative duty on the part of the parent not to deny one’s child access to public education. the important point to recognize here, however, is that there is an important difference between expecting a parent to respect state interference in the family via a system of compulsory public education, and expecting her to foster herself a capacity she finds detrimental to the pursuit of the good life. the latter, but not the former, is simply overly demanding. a third and final implication of appealing to the value of parental love when justif ying the family is that such an account is, in principle, more liberal with regard to the number of parents a child can potentially have. recall how Brighouse and Sw ift emphasize that their account can only support a small number of parents for each child (at some stage in the discussion, they even stipulate that there should be no more than four parents in a child’s life (Brighouse and Swift 2014: 71)). as they explain, “intimate but authoritative relationships bet ween children and a small nu mber of pa r t icu la r adu lts, relat ionsh ips i n wh ich t he adu lts have considerable discretion over the details of how the children are raised, is t he best a rra ngement for ra ising chi ldren, ta k ing into account a l l t he interests at stake” (Brighouse and Swift 2014: Xii). a parental love account, on the other hand, allows for more dispersed authority among parties who care robustly for a child, and so, in principle, allows for more than four parents (but as Brighouse and Swift recognize, the question of which adults should parent each child is a separate and independent question (Brighouse and Swift 2014: 49)). and in fact, this is already taking place with modern fa mi ly a rra ngements where chi ldren a re loved deeply by t heir pa rents, stepparents, and godparents. insofar as it is feasible and desirable for the child to enjoy a loving relationship with each one of them, it seems odd (if not somewhat disrespectful to the child) to artificially limit the size of the family just so that each adult can exercise more authority over her life. 6. concluSion in this essay i have engaged with the question of “why is it good for children to be raised by parents, and good for parents to raise children” (Brighouse and Swift 2014: iX). and in particular, i have asked whether Brighouse and Swift answer to this question delivers a successful justification of the parent- child relationship. w hile i have argued that their account fails on t wo desiderata and that an account in the vicinity might be superior, i believe the fiduciary account still stands out for helping us make significant progress on the foundational question of what is so special about the family. Why the Family? 219 LEAP 3 (2015) BiBlioGraPhy Blustein, J., 1982: Parents and Children: The Ethics of the Family, oxford university Press. Brighouse, h., and Swift, a., 2006: “Parents’ rights and the value of the Family”, Ethics 117: 80-108. — 2014: Family Values, Princeton: Princeton university Press. clayton, M., 2006: Justice and Legitimacy in Upbringing, oxford: oxford university Press. cowden, M., 2012: “what’s love Got to Do with it? why a child Does not have a right to Be loved”, Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 15: 325-345. Ferracioli, l., and terlazzo, r., 2014: “educating for autonomy: liberalism and autonomy in the capabilities approach”, Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 17: 443-455. Ferracioli, l. 2014: “the State’s Duty to ensure children are loved”, Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy 8: 1-19. — 2015: “the anarchist’s Myth: autonomy, children and State legitimacy”, Hypatia 30: 370-385. Gheaus, a., 2012: “the right to Parent one’s Biological Baby”, Journal of Political Philosophy 20: 432-455. hall, B., 1999: “the origin of Parental rights”, Public Affairs Quarterly 13: 73-82 vallentyne, P., 2003: “the rights and Duties of childrearing”, in William and Mary Bill of Rights Journal 11: 991-1009. Macleod, c., 2010: “Parental responsibilities in an unjust world”, in Procreation and Parenthood, eds. D. archard and D. Benatar, 128-150, oxford: oxford university Press. Meyers, D. t., 1987: “Personal autonomy and the Paradox of Feminine Socialization”, Journal of Philosophy 84: 619-628. narayan, u., 1999: “Family ties: rethinking Parental claims in the light of Surrogacy and custody”, in Having and Raising Children: Unconventional Families, Hard Choices, and the Social Good, eds. u. narayan and J. Bartkowiak, 65-86, university Park, Pa: the Pennsylvania State university Press. Pettit, P., 2008: “Freedom and Probabilit y: a comment on Goodin and Jackson”, Philosophy & Public Affairs 36: 206-220. rawls, J., 1999: A Theory of Justice, rev. ed., cambridge, Ma: harvard university Press. LEAP 3 (2015) Advantage, Authority, Autonomy and Continuity: A Response to Ferracioli, Gheaus and Stroud H A R Ry BR iGHOuSE University of Wisconsin-Madison A dA M S W iF T University of Warwick Abstract we address three critiques of our book Family Values: The Ethics of Parent-Child Relationships (Brighouse and Swift 2014), published simultaneously with this reply. in response to Stroud (2016), we emphasize the specificity of parents’ rights, and the modesty of our claims about them, challenging her laissez faire position on parents' right to confer advantage on their children, and stressing the merely illustrative role that we give to fair equality of opportunity. in response to Gheaus (2016), we clarify our “dual-interest” approach and the content of the adult interest in parenting, while defending the claim that that interest is releva nt to t he justif ication of a rra ngements for t he ra ising of children. in response to Ferracioli (2016), we explain our views about how many adults may properly parent a child, the significance of ch i ld ren’s autonomy, a nd t he va lue of cont i nu i ng relat ionsh ips between parents and their adult children. Keywords: family, children, right to parent, autonomy introDuction it is gratifying to have our views subjected to such careful attention. Much of our response will consist of clarification—explaining what we are a nd, perhaps more impor ta nt ly, a re not t r y ing to do. our a rg ument is wide- ranging in that we address a series of issues concerning the ethics of parent- child relationships that are often treated separately, and ambitious in that we offer a novel and unified theoretical approach to those topics. But in other ways it is modest, more modest than it has seemed to some readers. 221 Harry Brighouse & Adam Swift LEAP 3 (2015) Bet ween them, our three critics offer a varied and contrasting set of objections. Stroud (2016) focuses on the egalitarian or distributive dimension of our argument, challenging our views about the limited scope of parents’ rights to confer advantage on their children. Gheaus (2016) addresses rather what we call the liberal challenge to the family: issues concerning the moral basis of the right to parent and of parents’ rights over their children. while Stroud is enthusiastic about our “expanding the discourse around the family by high light ing t he interests of (wou ld-be) parents” (2016 : 1, orig ina l emphasis), it is precisely our willingness to give adults’ interests any role in justifying childrearing arrangements that troubles Gheaus. Ferracioli (2016), for her part, endorses a dual-interest approach like ours but thinks we have misidentified the interests! Stroud raises the most general methodological questions. She generously credits us with some ‘game-changing insights and argumentative strategies’ (2016: 180) but it soon emerges that in her view we are playing the wrong game! So we begin by explaining what game we are and are not playing, and why we think it’s the right one. those explanations underlie our approach to parental partiality and parents’ rights to confer advantage on their children, which is the substantive aspect that Stroud criticizes. they also provide a framework for discussing key issues raised in the other papers. it is precisely because there is something morally distinctive, sui generis we might say, about cla iming rights to cont rol a not her huma n being t hat Gheaus is doubtful about our dual-interest account. our attempt to explain those rights depends on our specific conception of the parental role as fusing love and intimacy, on the one hand, and authority or control, on the other—a fusion that is challenged by both Ferracioli and Gheaus. 1. BeinG SPeciFic Stroud wonders both why we want a sui generis justification of parents’ rights and why we limit them to the minimum necessary. the answer is that we regard parents’ rights as distinctive, and distinctively problematic, in two ways that she appears not to. on the distributive side, parents’ rights and duties to act partially towards their children conf lict with ideals such as equality of opportunity; children will have better or worse prospects in life depending on their parents’ ability and willingness to confer advantage on them. this challenge demands an account of why exactly parents should be free to do things to, for, or with their children that benefit them relative to others, and what they should be free to do. the liberal challenge, on the other hand, arises from the fact that parent and child have distinct and sometimes conflicting interests, and children are vulnerable and non-consenting parties to the relationship. we need an explanation of why exactly adults Advantage, Authority, Autonomy and Continuity 222 LEAP 3 (2015) should have rights over children, which adults should have them, and what those rights should be. For us, then, the family raises specific justificatory questions that require specific responses, and explain why, for us, parents’ rights are the minimum compatible w ith the kind of parent-child relationship that w ill realize familial relationship goods for its participants. like many liberal theorists, we see relationships involving some people exercising authority over the lives of non-consenting others as prima facie problematic. that exercise requires justification, and limitation, because those subject to that authority can properly demand an account of why they should be, or should have been, subject to those people within that domain of decision. like many egalitarian theorists, we think that relationships creating inequalities of oppor t u n it y a re prima facie problemat ic. t hose i nequa l it ies requ i re justification, and limitation, because those on the wrong end of them can properly demand an account of why they should be worse off than others just because they were raised by different parents. to be sure, t he libera l cha l lenge is more distinctively problemat ic. controlling other non-consenting human beings requires special justification; that’s why parents’ rights to exercise authorit y over their children pose peculiar problems. indeed, they trouble Gheaus enough for her to argue that “the claim to a right to control a child’s life must be grounded exclusively in the child’s interest, in which case there is no sui generis right to parent” (2016: 202). Benefitting others, by contrast, is commonplace. People routinely act pa r t ia l ly in favor of pa r t icu la r ot hers—f riends, lovers, co-relig ionists, compatriots—and these other types of relationship might be invoked to justify their doing so. indeed, one might doubt that relationships of any kind are required to justify inequality-creating interactions. Plausibly, there is a general prerogative—one that has nothing at all to do with relationships, valuable or other w ise—not only to pursue one’s self-interest but also to confer benefits on others in ways that depart from equality. indeed, conferring benefits on others might be part of what it is in one’s self-interest to do. Stroud seems surprisingly unconcerned on both counts. For her (2016: 183), “one might doubt whether parents raising children requires a sui generis justification in terms of the distinctive values it realizes, as opposed to simply falling under a more general and less demanding moral schema… [B]eing a parent is something that a great many adults very much want to do with their life. if someone very much wants to do x with her life, one might think that alone creates a significant moral presumption in favor of allowing her to do x—regardless, it would seem, of x’s specific content, or of whether her (or anyone’s) doing x would realize important objective values”. 223 Harry Brighouse & Adam Swift LEAP 3 (2015) we are not sure quite what counts as a “presumption”, but for us—as for Gheaus - the specific content of x in the child-raising case puts the burden of justification on those claiming the right to engage in that particular activity. it is problematic to claim the right to control the current life, and inf luence the future life, of another human being by appeal to considerations other than that other’s own interests. according to Stroud (2016: 184), “there is no issue facing us as a society, to be settled collectively, about how to bring up children: there are only individual adults who want to parent children”. as a claim about how parents should be allowed to raise their children this is false. our society is constantly making collective decisions on such controversial questions as what kind of discipline parents should be permitted to exercise, what forms of medical treatment they should be permitted to administer or obstruct, what kind of education they should be permitted or required to provide for their children. But it also looks mistaken as a claim about whether there should be parent- child relationships—or, according to our stipulation, “families”—at all. the mere fact that individual adults want to parent children is not sufficient to establish the moral propriety of their doing so. her view on the distributive side is also surprisingly laissez faire. readers may disagree with our view that parents do not have the right to bequeath substantial wealth to their children, but surely few will reject it so quickly. Disclosing that an inheritance from her husband’s mother made possible the purchase of the vermont farmhouse in which she wrote the first draft of her paper, she writes (2016: 185): “She loved her son, and the rest of us, and we know she would be deeply gratified by all the new horizons her bequest has opened up for us. Faced with this vivid awareness of what her bequest has made possible for her son and my family, i find it simply impossible to accept that my mother-in-law ought not to have been able to leave my husband that money: that it would violate nobody’s rights to prevent or prohibit people from doing any such thing”. let us assume that the sum in question was indeed justly her mother- in-law’s in the first place; that she had the moral, and not merely the legal, right to any say over it. even so, it is strange to think that one could assess whether she had the right to bequeath it to her son merely by awareness, however v iv id, of t he va lue of t he bequest to her a nd its benef icia ries. Suppose t hat t he state had ta xed t he in herita nce suf f icient ly to ma ke purchasing the farmhouse impossible. would awareness of what could have been enjoyed in the absence of that tax make such a constraint on the bequest similarly “impossible to accept”? Advantage, Authority, Autonomy and Continuity 224 LEAP 3 (2015) we a nd St roud, t hen, approach t hese mat ters f rom ver y d i f ferent perspectives. But we must also emphasize the limits of our ambition. the f lip side of our offering a sui generis treatment of parent-child relationships is that we do not address all the rights that adults may properly claim with respect to the children they parent; we confine ourselves to those that invoke the fact that the adult is the child’s parent. we want to know when “because i am your parent” is a good answer to the question “why do you have the right to do that to, or with, me?” we want to know when “because i am her parent” is a good answer to the question “w hy do you have the right to do that for her?” (see Brighouse and Swift 2014: 120). other good answers to such questions might be available. Perhaps parents have permissions, deriving from sources other than the familial relationship, that permit them to pursue their own projects in ways that will affect what they may legitimately do, all things considered, by way of exercising authority over their children’s lives (see Brighouse and Swift 2014: 121-2). Perhaps they have permissions to confer benefits on anybody they like, including their children, which derive from a more general moral schema of the kind that Stroud mentions. it would be a different task to engage with those other justifications. as far as our theory of parents’ rights is concerned, we are interested only in what kinds of partiality, and what exercises of authority, can be justified specifically on the ground that the other person involved is a child one is parenting. So Stroud is mistaken in attributing to us (2016: 182) the v iew that “if disallowing pa rents a cer ta in right or priv i lege wou ld not impede t he development of a f lourishing parent-child relationship, then that putative right or privilege stands exposed and undefended against any arguments that could be raised against it” [original emphasis]. the putative right or privilege stands, for us, exposed and undefended only against the kind of argument that appeals to the fact that the alleged right or privilege holder is the child’s parent. indeed, when assessing what, all things considered, they should be free to do with respect to their children, we acknowledge the relevance not only of parents’ other roles or statuses but also of more indirect factors such as incentive considerations (see Brighouse and Swift 2014: 130-1). our contribution on the distributive side pursues a suggestion from Samuel Scheff ler, for whom parental partiality raises, in a particular form, the general issue of the “distributive objection” to special responsibilities that arise in the context of valuable relationships: “the problem with such responsibi lit ies is … t hat t hey may confer unfa ir benef it. … [S]pecia l responsibilities give the participants in rewarding groups and relationships increased claims to one another’s assistance, while weakening the claims 225 Harry Brighouse & Adam Swift LEAP 3 (2015) that other people have on them”. Scheffler (2003: 102) observes that his account “is compatible with the view that the strength of one’s responsibilities depends on the nature of the relationships that give rise to them, and on the degree of value that one has reason to attach to those relationships. As far as the content of the responsibilities is concerned, we may assume that this too depends on the nature of the relationships in question . . .” [added emphasis]. our aim is to put the parent-child relationship under the microscope while allowing that a host of other considerations will be relevant to questions of leg it imate pa renta l pa r t ia lit y, a l l t hings considered, in a ny pa r t icu la r circumstances. it is compatible with recognition both that other relationships may generate ot her dist ribut ive cla ims a nd t hat indiv idua ls may enjoy prerogatives to favor themselves and others in ways that make no reference to relationships at all.1 whether we are playing the right game, or even a game worth playing, depends, then, on how important it is to identify, and isolate, this particular kind of justification. in our view, parents’ rights to exercise authority over their children are t y pically and substantially defended by appeal to the specific thought that the adults in question are indeed the child’s parents. we acknowledge that rights to benefit children are, by contrast, more often presented in a more general frame: “it’s my money and i can do what i want with it. if i want to leave it to my children or spend it on their education, that’s up to me”. But even here, distinctively familial considerations are often invoked, especially in attempts to justify blocking egalitarian measures. (“My job is to promote my child’s interests; you violate my rights as a parent if you interfere with my capacity to do that by, for example, limiting bequest, or restricting my freedom to spend my resources on her education”.) the task of identifying and isolating “family values properly understood”, and thereby exposing as unwarranted many such normative appeals to “the family”, seems to us a game well worth the candle. 2. conFerrinG aDvantaGe that remains true even if, as Stroud (2016: 191-192) claims, “the prohibition not just of bequests, but of all the various ways in which parents might seek to use their superior financial resources to benefit their children (think private schooling), would have only an insignificant effect on the unequal distribution of prospects for desirable jobs, etc. across children. that is, parents’ direct use of money to benefit their children is—it turns out—a relatively minor contributor to inequality of opportunity (Brighouse and 1 a “relationship goods” approach may be relevant to those also. For an initial schematic move in one particular direction, see Brighouse and Swift (2011). Advantage, Authority, Autonomy and Continuity 226 LEAP 3 (2015) Swift allude to this at 31-32 and 125-127.)” She thinks (2016: 192) that this admission makes “overly optimistic” our claim that our “account of ‘family values properly understood’ … mitigates—massively mitigates—the conflict with equality” [original emphasis]. But any appearance of tension between these two claims is illusory; dispelling that illusion may help to clarify our aim further. the first is an empirical point about existing societies. Given current reward schedules, and the mechanisms by which people reach their places in the distribution, the direct use of parents’ money to benefit children may indeed be less significant contributors to inequalities of opportunity, between children raised in different families, than parent-child interactions of the kind endorsed and protected by our theory. the second is an observation about the kind of society that would be compatible with our account: it is perfectly possible to respect, and promote, what is important and valuable about the family without allowing parent-child relationships to produce anything like the inequalities of opportunity that they currently do. one way of doing this would be by reducing the extent to which children who participate in those relationships also benefit, in other ways, from doing so—that extent depends on how other social institutions are designed (see Brighouse and Swift 2014: 33). at present, “family values” are often invoked to defend not only the interactions w ithin the relationships but also the conferral of external benefits that they currently involve. By rejecting the claim that parents (qua parents) have the right to confer advantage on their children in ways that conf lict w ith fair equalit y of opportunit y, we challenge that defense. the game is still worth the candle, we believe, even when we add a further caveat: although we invoke “familial relationship goods” to identif y the interests that ground parents’ rights, we are explicit that the rights we are talking about are prima facie only. indeed, strictly speaking, the category of “familial relationship goods” is intended only to isolate those parent-child interactions that are “susceptible to justification by appeal to the parent-child relationship” (see Brighouse and Swift 2014: 146). Some of those goods, and hence some of the interactions that produce them, are worthy of protection even when they conflict with fair equality of opportunity. others – such as the loving general promotion of one’s child’s interests – are not, we claim, weighty enough to warrant the cost in terms of that distributive value. Just as one might have rights to benefit one’s children that do not derive specifically from the fact that one is their parent, so too one might not have, all things considered, the right to do things for them that one has, prima facie, in virtue of being their parent. Perhaps, in a world where some lack what they need for mere survival, much of the time and energ y spent by 227 Harry Brighouse & Adam Swift LEAP 3 (2015) aff luent parents on the provision even of core familial relationship goods, for themselves and their children, exceeds the scope of any plausible right— especially where parents have more than one child. having identified a criterion for evaluating parent-child interactions as important contributors to valuable familial relationships, and so prima facie protected by parents’ rights, we offer a judgment about the considerations at stake in the conf lict between the advantage-conferring aspects of familial relationship goods, on t he one ha nd, a nd fa ir equa lit y of oppor tunit y, on t he ot her. But we explicitly refrain from offering judgments about the rights that parents have, all things considered, in circumstances (which we take to be our own) where the distributive ideal with which those rights might conf lict is more urgent than fair equality of opportunity (see Brighouse and Swift 2014: 143-5) we similarly refrain from considering what kinds of conferrals of advantage on children might fall under the parental dut y of care – the discharge of which is justified even where it conf licts with fair equality of opportunity – in circumstances where societal arrangements mean that those children face the risk, as adults, of falling into poverty or lacking medical treatment.2 a lot more is needed to get from (i) a criterion for identifying which parent-child interactions are and are not important enough to be worth protecting even where they conf lict with fair equality of opportunity to (ii) all things considered evaluations of particular prescriptions—whether political policies or indiv idual actions—in our current circumstances. indeed, a lot more is needed even, more modestly, to identify the precise content of parents’ rights in those circumstances. Stroud doubts that fair equality of opportunity can bear the weight we put on it. we invoke that distributive principle as a criterion for distinguishing between different types of familial relationship goods. the “core” goods, as we term them, are important enough to be worthy of protection even when that undermines fair equality of opportunity. (though, as just noted, parents would have no complaint were institutions to be designed in such a way that that conflict was reduced or even eliminated.) But the good of generally having one’s interests promoted by a loving parent is not, we say, important enough to be worthy of similar protection; it should y ield to children’s interest in competing on fair terms with others. we agree with her that fair equality of opportunity is not a hugely weighty principle—we emphasize its limitations, and the importance of other distributive values, several times (see Brighouse and Swift, 2014: 33-5, 38-45, 143-8). Maybe we are wrong to claim that, were it the only distributive consideration at stake, it could serve as a constraint on interactions in which the parent is lovingly motivated generally to further 2 For remarks on this issue in the specific case of school choice, see Swift (2003: 119- 125). Brighouse and Swift (2014) attempts no analogous discussion of the more general issue. Advantage, Authority, Autonomy and Continuity 228 LEAP 3 (2015) the child’s interests. if so, that would be an objection to our proposed particular weighting of the conflicting values, not to our methodological approach. But we should also point out that our account of the core familial relationship goods leaves plenty of room for parental spontaneity and discretion in the way that they relate to their children (see Brighouse and Swift 2014: 140-3). that, combined with the recognition that loving parents will be spontaneously motivated to benefit their children quite generally, seems to us to leave sufficient room for the concern in question. in so far as the things that parents do to benefit their children are done as an inev itable part of a hea lt hy lov i ng relat ionsh ip, t hey a re protected by ou r t heor y. aga i n, though, our view is that the familial relationship itself cannot plausibly be invoked to defend any resulting conferral of advantage that gives children better chances than they would enjoy under fair equality of opportunity. the fact that one is spontaneously motivated to benefit one’s children, and hea lt hy relat ionships require space for sponta neit y, ex pla ins why one should be free to act on those motivations, but prov ides no objection to societal attempts to limit, or even eliminate, the impact of those actions on children’s prospects of the kind with which fair equality of opportunity is concerned. 3. claiMinG authority according to Gheaus (2016: 196), “a right to parent is an anomaly by liberal lights: liberals acknowledge no other entitlement to exercise power over another individual legitimized in part by reference to an interest—no matter how important—of the one exercising power”. our dual-interest theory— and our positing different grounds for the right to parent and the rights of parents—is an attempt to strike the right balance between the interests of the different participants in the relationship. But we need to be clear about what exactly it means to have a dual interest theory, and where exactly adults’ interests come into the picture. to clarif y our approach, and our attempt to strike the right balance between the interests at stake, notice that there are at least three somewhat different issues under discussion: I. how children should be raised. here our argument for the family – for parent-child relationships – defends that practice against alternatives such as their being reared by professionals in state- run childrearing institutions. ii. the content of parents’ rights: what rights parents can properly claim with respect to their children in virtue of being those children’s 229 Harry Brighouse & Adam Swift LEAP 3 (2015) parents. one can know that children should be raised by parents without having a full specification of parents’ rights.3 here we challenge conventional views that grant parents extensive rights to confer advantage on their children and to shape their children’s values. iii. how to match up children and adults in families. one can know that children should be raised by parents and what rights their parents should have without knowing who should parent, or by parented by, whom. here, inter alia, we reject both the view that genetic connection establishes an adult’s claim to parent a child and the claim that children have a right to be parented by the best available parent. in our view, different considerations are relevant to addressing these different issues. with regard to (ii), the content of parents’ rights, our account is exclusively child-centered. the rights in question are those needed properly to discharge the role of parent, which role is itself entirely fiduciary. But it’s a separate question, of type (iii), who has the right to be a parent, and our answer to that question invokes the adult interest in fulfilling the role (see Brighouse and Swift 2014: 121). understanding this position depends on keeping in mind the specific point with which we started: that parents’ rights are specifically the rights one has qua parent. the right to parent, by contrast, is one that one has, if one has it, simply as an adult. clarif ying the structure of our view does not show it is valid, or even coherent, but before moving on to that challenge, we can illustrate it further by attempting to address one of Gheaus’ concerns. She is troubled, inter alia, by the right of parents to exclude others from having close relationships with their children, and attributes to us the view that parental authority includes a right to exclude those others “for reasons other than the protection of the child’s interest” (2016: 202). But, for us, the duty on the part of others not to undermine the relationship bet ween parent and child, like the right of parents to exclude others where it is likely to do so, derives entirely from children’s interests in the relationship (see Brighouse and Swift 2014: 87). it is precisely because—and only in so far as—it would be bad for children to have their familial relationships disrupted that parents have a right to exclude others from forming relationships with their children. that right, like all parents’ rights, is limited by, and justified in terms of, that fiduciary consideration. this is consistent with children having interests in relationships with other adults and indeed with facilitating such relationships being part 3 of course this is not an entirely separate enterprise. to justif y the family just is to justif y a child-raising arrangement in which particular adults have certain rights over the children they parent (see Brighouse and Sw ift, 2014: 86-7). Still, the detailed and careful specification of the rights that one has, qua parent, is sensibly conceived as a further task, to be carried out after one has done enough to answer the first two questions. Advantage, Authority, Autonomy and Continuity 230 LEAP 3 (2015) of parents’ fiduciary role. Gheaus may object that the right to exclude is not properly characterized as a right one that one has qua parent. rather, she might suggest, it should be seen as an aspect of the right to parent. after all the right to parent includes the right to exclude others. Something of this kind, indeed, is true of all parents’ rights: the relationship involves various rights (and duties), so in claiming the right to parent one is claiming the rights of a parent. if, as we think, adults’ interests are relevant to deciding who has the former, then they are obviously relevant to deciding who gets the latter. So adult interests do indeed come into the story that explains why they have the right to exclude others from relationships with particular children; they come in as considerations taken into account by the procedure that grants to adults the (entirely fiduciary) rights that they have with respect to the children they parent. Gheaus may yet be right to reject our view: we have not yet defended the claim that adults’ interests are indeed relevant considerations. But we doubt that those adults who, as a result of the allocation, are excluded from relationships with those particular children, have a valid complaint. their exclusion is the outcome of the right way of deciding who should get to exclude. let’s think about Gheaus’ refugees. in her scenario, the refugees seem only to be refugees. there is a question about how they should be socialized into the host community but no suggestion that, having been socialized, they might in turn be involved in the socialization of future waves of refugees. Suppose, instead, that migration is expected to continue, and that most of the current refugees, having been socialized, will come to have a strong interest in playing a socializing role for those future refugees. Suppose we agree with Gheaus (2016: 201) that “it is exclusively the refugees’ interests that determine the ideal way of socializing them”. which way of socializing refugees does in fact serve these refugees’ interests best? the answer will surely take into account not only their interests qua refugees, but also the future or prospective interest they are likely to develop, qua prospective socializers. imagine asking a refugee how she would like to be socialized: “would you rather be socialized in whatever way was best for you, or in a way that meant that your opportunit y to take your turn in socializing future refugees did not depend entirely on whether you were the best available socializer?” wouldn’t she reply: “i’m not sure i understand the question. the way of socializing me that’s best for me is the one that is best for me over my life as a whole. if it’s very valuable for me to have the opportunity to socialize future refugees, then the system of socializing that would be best for me, over my life as a whole, is unlikely to be one that makes that opportunity depend entirely on my being the best available socializer 231 Harry Brighouse & Adam Swift LEAP 3 (2015) of any one of them”. this is one sense in which a theory of childrearing arrangements could be “dual interest”: it takes into account people’s interests both as children and as the adults those children will become. if, as we claim, and Gheaus does not deny, many adults do indeed have a weighty interest in parenting a child, then so do the children who are going to become those adults. they are the same people. on this interpretation, a child-centered view might be one that regarded as relevant only people’s interests as children, i.e. during the period of life in which they are children. Such a position is deeply implausible. children’s interests in that sense are indeed important, and we agree that there has been a tendency to overemphasize the view of children as “adults in the making”, to see them too much as “becomings” and not enough as “beings”, and to underplay the value of what we might think of as the intrinsic or special goods of childhood. But, in standard cases, nobody would seriously suggest that we could assess childrearing practices by ignoring their formative impact on the adults that children become. indeed, this understanding of what it would mean for a theory to be child-centered would run contrary to standard usage in the literature. when philosophers talk about children’s interests in how they are raised, they include their developmental interests, their interest in developing capacities that will benefit them when they reach adulthood. those, like us, who frame their views in terms of a contrast between the childrearing interests of children and adults actually intend something different: by “children’s interests” we mean simply all those interests in how they are raised, including those that will affect their lives as adults, except the interest they will have, as adults, in how children are raised. we are interested in people’s lifetime interest in childrearing arrangements, but we separate out that particular adult interest for analytical purposes, and to show how giving it its proper weight qualifies the extent to which their other interests should determine those arrangements. a child-centred account, on this interpretation, would treat that adult interest as irrelevant to the question of how children should be raised. that too strikes us as implausible. to be clear, on this construal, a dual interest view does not guarantee that any particular child will be raised by the particular adult(s) who would in fact have been best for her over her lifetime. nor do children collectively have a claim to that particular allocation of adults to children that will be best, overall, for children over their lifetimes. the point is not that, once we have the right account of children’s lifetime interests, they do have a claim to the best available parents after all. rather, they should be parented according to childrearing arrangements—understood as a way of arranging the raising of children and, more specifically, a way of arranging who is parented by whom—that Advantage, Authority, Autonomy and Continuity 232 LEAP 3 (2015) is best for them over their lifetime. the rationale for a dual interest view is that the price, for children themselves, of being parented according to childrearing arrangements in which children are parented by their best available parents will be too high. Discussing how much we owe children, Matthew clayton (2015: 251) points out that: “what is best for us as children … may not be best for us taking our lives as a whole when we factor in the costs of fulfilling the duty to provide the best childhood for any offspring we might have”. Similarly, the way of arranging the raising of children that is best for us “as children” may not be best for us taking our lives as a whole, when we factor in the costs of fulfilling the duty to provide children with the best way of raising them “as children”. an entirely child-centered way of arranging the raising of children, in either of the senses we have identified, will be costly in two different ways. First, it could leave adults who have a weighty interest in parenting unable to do so simply because there would not be any children for whom their pa rent ing wou ld be best. Second, less obv iously, a nd empirica l ly less plausibly, it could require adults who have no interest in parenting—indeed whose lives would go much worse—to serve in that role, simply because, as it happened, en l ist i ng t hei r ser v ices wou ld be opt i ma l for ch i ld ren. thinking about people’s interests over the life course, this surely gets the intra-individual balance of interests wrong. what about a child who will never reach adulthood, so has no interest in being able to parent? it might seem that her interests are decisive against the claims of any would-be parents. But what drives our intuition in that case may be not the fact that she is a child but rather that her life’s shortness, and her failure to develop into adulthood, mean that she will be so badly off, on a lifetime view, that her interests during the short time that she has should be regarded as decisive. think instead about children whose lives w ill other w ise go normally, but who, as it happens, have no interest in themselves becoming parents. it is true that we cannot say to them that their lifetime interests are better protected by a way of arranging childrearing that gives some weight to the adult interest in parenting. But it is not clear to us why the interests of adults who do have that interest should be ignored altogether. imagine a parent saying to her child: “i know that someone else would have done a better job of parenting you. i know, further, that you will not personally benefit from the way in which our societ y’s childrearing arrangements protect people’s interests in becoming parents. But i hope you agree that it was so wonderful for me to get to be your parent that you don’t have any complaint against me for parenting you, despite not being the person who would have parented you best, or, more relevantly, not being the parent you would have had under a system that regarded children’s 233 Harry Brighouse & Adam Swift LEAP 3 (2015) interests as the only ones that matter. after all, i was good enough”. of course there is a question about quite how much worse than the relevant alternative a parent could be before the child did indeed have a complaint; that is the quest ion of whet her “good enough” shou ld be const r ued in absolute or comparative terms (see Shields 2016). But to resist Gheaus’ objection we need only defend the v iew that adults’ interests should play some role in deciding childrearing arrangements. two considerations, both raised by Gheaus’ example, might seem to lend support to the view that only children’s interests should count. one is the suggestion, more than hinted at by the analogy with refugees, that children are in a parlous state and in need of rescue. this would correspond to the thought that childhood is a “predicament”, an unfortunate state, certainly inferior to adulthood (Schapiro 1999). Suppose childhood is a predicament from which people need to be rescued. would it follow that they should be rescued in the way that was best for them, without any regard to the interests of the rescuers? when we think of refugees, of course, we typically imagine them to be not only in desperate need through no fault of their own but also victims of injustice. But unless we regard children as wronged simply by being brought into ex istence, we doubt t he a na log y holds. indeed, in standard rescue cases it’s not obvious that potential rescuers have to rescue in the best possible way, and with no regard to the costs, to them, of different ways of rescuing. in the case of children, we need to keep in mind that, for all we know, children may go on to have much better lives, overall, than those who parent them—even if their interests are not the only ones that determine how they are raised. with that clearly in mind, why should we only think about them when deciding how they should be raised? Perhaps, however, the problem is specifically that the child is subject to the authority of the parent. She needs others to exercise control over her and, as we have said, there is something distinctively problematic about one person claiming a right to authority over another on grounds other than that other’s interests. this is what Gheaus (2016: 200) calls ‘the republican response’: “if it were possible to promote the refugee’s current well-being and future autonomy without locking her into any particular relationship, then giving you—or another private individual—authority over her would be w rong because it wou ld ma ke her subject to (perhaps benevolent) domination”. this frames the point in relation to issue (i): should children be raised by parents (in families) at all? But it applies also to issue (iii). Grant, for the sake of argument, that it is best for children to be raised in families. one might still think it objectionable, on republican grounds, to Advantage, Authority, Autonomy and Continuity 234 LEAP 3 (2015) subject particular children to the authority of particular adults except on the grounds that the matching-up of children to adults is optimal for the children.4 it is misleading to give too much emphasis to the idea that parents have a n interest in exercising aut horit y as such. Gheaus is more ca ref u l, but Ferracioli (2016: 217) claims that we vindicate “the current model of parental authority” by arguing that parents have an interest in “exercising authority over ch i ld ren”. ou r ex posit ion of t he adu lt i nterest empha si z es t he normative significance of the particular combination of features of the parenting relationship (see Brighouse and Swift 2014: 88-93). it’s valuable to play the fiduciary role, and to have responsibility for decisions affecting the child’s upbringing, in the context of a relationship with other distinctive features, which might be summarized as loving intimacy. controlling, or exercising authorit y, plays a key role in our analysis because this is the distinctively troubling aspect of the relationship, and the one that has led some theorists to develop entirely child-centered accounts. But that does not mean that it is the interest in controlling, or exercising authority, that does the work on the adult side. Someone who wanted to parent in order to control or exercise authority over a child would be badly missing the point. Both Gheaus and Ferracioli press us on the way in which our account of the parent-child relationship fuses intimacy and authority. we emphasize t he va lue to t he ch i ld of ex per ienci ng her pa rent a s bot h lov i ng a nd authoritative, as well as the adult interest in having some responsibility for a nd discret ion over how she conducts her relat ionship w it h her chi ld. (imagine the reading of prescribed bedtime stories as the dutiful execution 4 at the end of her paper, Gheaus considers how the way that children come into the world might relate to the question of how they should be raised and, if parented, who should parent them. it is, as she says, surely an important disanalog y between children and her refugees that children already have connections of various kinds to particular adults. although she ta lks about biolog y, a n a na ly tica lly distinct—t hough empirica lly of ten associated— connection should perhaps be particularly salient to those worried by the idea of adults appealing to their own interests to justif y claims to parent children. w hat’s objectionable, for Gheaus, is an adult claiming a parenting relationship with a child on the ground that the relationship will benefit the adult. in general terms, we might say, the adult is using the— non-consent i ng— ch i ld a s a mea ns to t he adu lt’s ends. if Gheaus t h i n k s t hat wou ld be troublesome in a world where babies were brought by storks, she shou ld surely be much more concerned about a world, like our own, where babies are typically produced in order to serve the interests of those producing them. it seems less problematic to allow hosts’ socializing interests to influence how refugees are socialized than it is to allow adults’ interests to inf luence how children are raised when those adults have deliberately created the children and have done so in order to claim a parental relationship with them. that really does look like using children as a mea ns to one’s ow n ends. rat her t ha n a gestator y relationship helping to establish a right to raise a particular child, as she has elsewhere suggested (Gheaus 2012), perhaps an adult’s interests should count less where she has deliberately created the being that now stands in need of rescue-by-authority from his predicament. 235 Harry Brighouse & Adam Swift LEAP 3 (2015) of state directives.) But interesting questions arise about the extent to which, and ways in which, these two features need to go together, and how they might come apart while preserving the essential core of the relationship. in thinking about this, it might be useful to distinguish micro-authority, understood as the day-to-day regulation, disciplining, and control of the chi ld, f rom macro-aut horit y, understood as t he ma k ing of big picture decisions, such as where the child goes to school, whether she eats meat, whether she attends religious services, and so on. we already insist that the weighty familial relationship goods at the heart of our account could be produced in parenting regimes that gave parents much less discretionary authority than they currently enjoy on macro-issues, so we think of ourselves as attempting to limit the authoritative dimension to the minimum necessary. those goods are surely hard to produce when parents are having to deny or conceal too much of themselves, or to raise their children in ways that they regard as deeply misguided. But we are in principle sympathetic to Gheaus’ suggestion (2016: 202) that (macro) authority and intimacy might be disentangled in so far as that can be done without undue cost to relationship goods. like Gheaus, Ferracioli objects to our claim that both adults and children have an interest in the adult simultaneously loving, caring for, and having considerable authority over, the child. the family as we understand it is coercive, t he pa rent exercising power over t he chi ld, a nd we cla im t hat ch i ld ren need at lea st one person who both loves t hem a nd exercises discipline over them. children need one person to love them because being loved is a precondition for their healthy emotional, moral, cognitive, and even physical development. they—especially when they are very young— need someone who disciplines them because they are inexperienced in the world (they do not, for example, know what is dangerous) and lack the kind of self-control necessary f luently to exercise agency. and they need these roles to be played by a single person because that person will then more successfully guide them understand and regulate their emotional reactions to the world and develop the tendency to react appropriately to it. Someone who disciplines them w ithout lov ing them or being loved by them may, perhaps, be able to get them to comply with commands through fear, or charisma, but the important developmental aim of disciplining a child is not to secure their compliance in the moment, but to get them, over time, to internalize disciplinary regulation. this is one reason why children can only have a limited number of parents—we don’t know the number, but in the book we suggest that four might be the limit. Ferracioli sees this as a drawback, and poses an alternative that would allow for “more dispersed authority among parties who care robustly for a child, and so, in principle, allows for more than four parents”. For her (2016: Advantage, Authority, Autonomy and Continuity 236 LEAP 3 (2015) 218), “this is already taking place with modern family arrangements where children are loved deeply by their parents, stepparents and godparents … it seems odd to artificially limit the size of the family just so that each adult can exercise more authority over her life”. our suggestion that a child cannot have more than four parents is a conjecture, not a stipulation. we just don’t know how many parents (in the sense of lovers who also discipline) a child can have. But too many—and we suspect that five would be too many—carries risks. First the child may not receive sufficiently harmonized information about how to interpret and interact with the world. adults have different parenting styles, conveying different messages; though all five may discipline the child well, for example, her development may be impaired by too many mixed signals. Second, she may not be well enough cared for, because the coordination costs escalate as the number of caregivers increases. consider a typical day with a toddler. you look after the toddler for 6 hours, and then a second parent takes over while you go to work for a while. to look after the toddler well the second parent needs a good deal of information—what mood is she in today? how might it affect her behavior? when did she last eat and did she eat well? is a tooth bothering her? Did she nap well, or not at all? has anything happened that might produce a delayed reaction? it is easier to convey this information well if the other parent has spent a good deal of time with her recently; pa r t ly because he t hen ha s a good dea l of t he necessa r y backg rou nd information about the child, but also because his skills of caring for her are still in good shape. the more transitions the child makes among adults, the leakier the information bucket, and the rustier the carers’ skills. Finally, as the number of parents with authority increases, the potential for disputes about what the interests of the child are and how to meet them escalates, as do the costs of resolving them, while the prospect of resolution diminishes. already, with just two parents, this can be difficult. the reason to limit the number of parents, then, is not so that any individual can exercise more authority over a child’s life, but so that children’s interests can be better realized all that said, our claim that parents rightfully have authority over their children does not imply a vision of a cramped, socially isolated, nuclear family. it is in children’s interests that parents exercise considerable authority over them, and others must be careful not to undermine the parent-child relat ionsh ip. But over t he cou rse of t hei r ch i ld hoods ch i ld ren have a profound interest in having relationships with a variety of suitable adults: it helps them to see alternative ways of being an adult, and alternative ways of dealing with the world, giving them resources to ref lect on who they really are, what they really value, and how to conduct themselves. Parents have a duty to facilitate and encourage those relationships (see Gheaus 2011). 237 Harry Brighouse & Adam Swift LEAP 3 (2015) 4. accoMoDatinG PluraliSM Fer raciol i proposes t wo desiderata for a just i f icat ion of t he fa m i ly : it should account for the value of the family over the life-course (2016: 201- 212); and it should be pluralistic, in that it should be able to justify the family in “non-liberal cultural contexts” (2016: 212-214). our theor y, she says, satisfies neither. it fails on the first because it focuses on relationship goods produced by the interactions between parent and child during the latter’s childhood; those goods are, for the most part, no longer produced once the child has become an independent adult. it fails on the second because of its emphasis on parents’ obligation to facilitate their child’s autonomy; parents in some non-libera l cu ltura l contex ts a re indif ferent or host i le to t he development of autonomy but st i l l “ma nage to enjoy a g reat deg ree of intimacy, love and af fection w it h t heir children, and … t he lives of a ll parties go much better as a result of partaking in such loving relationships” (2016: 213). let’s start with pluralism. Ferracioli (2016: 213) claims that we are “too quick in assuming that parents are typically capable and willing to ensure that their child develop the agential skills needed to make their own life choices…” and “fail to see that the right of children in becoming sufficiently autonomous can instead correlate with a duty on the part of the state to create a neutral system of compulsory public education” (2016: 213-214). But we assume neither that parents will be motivated to facilitate autonomy nor that, even if so motivated, they will be able to do so without a cooperative environment, such as the right kind of schooling and a reasonably f luid and pluralistic culture. w hen the environment is not supportive – when, for example, adequate schooling is unavailable, or, as for some Black families in some american cities, access to it puts children in physical danger—parents are raising children in non-ideal circumstances. as we have said, we make no attempt at the complex task of weighing the different considerations that apply to parents in such circumstances. nevertheless, in liberal societies, autonomy is an important achievement, and parents who successfully resist t he development of t heir chi ldren’s autonomy in a libera l societ y a re w ronging those children. More, they are losing something valuable for themselves—the challenge of raising a child to independence, aiming to enable her to separate herself from them, while hoping that, nevertheless, they can remain close. the value of autonomy—and of raising a child to be autonomous—enable us to say something about what is wrong with illiberal societies and societies that, although not illiberal, permit environments in which parents’ concern for their children’s wellbeing rightly inclines them not to facilitate their Advantage, Authority, Autonomy and Continuity 238 LEAP 3 (2015) children’s autonomy. one thing that is wrong is just this: that they make it harder, or dangerous, for children to become autonomous, and make it harder, or wrong, for parents to experience the good of raising a child to become autonomous. it also enables us to say something about what parents do wrong when unduly insistent that their child “uncritically endorse what they take to be deep truths about the world” (Ferracioli 2016: 213). Does our theor y justif y the family in non-liberal cultural contexts? assume t hat non-libera l contex ts a re cha racteri zed by indif ference or hostility to autonomy: parents do not aim to make their children autonomous and independent, and the social environment does not take up the slack, as it were, so autonomy is neither valued as an aim, nor an achieved as an outcome. in such contexts the family can still be valuable, and can still be justified, and our theory does explain why: parents can still oversee children’s development, and both parties can enjoy intimate, close, loving relationships and enjoy familial relationship goods. But both parties are also missing something of great value—a v ital developmental interest of children is neglected, and parents miss out on the distinctively rewarding challenge of acting as a fiduciary for someone whom one is raising to full independence of thought and word and deed. Someone who did not value autonomy, or was even hostile to it, could accept a great deal of our theory, while rejecting the claims we make about t he impor ta nce of autonomy for chi ldren, a nd t he dist inct ive va lue of fostering autonomy as part of the fiduciary obligation toward children. She would offer different content for children’s interests, and hence for the adult interest in acting as a child’s fiduciary, but could nevertheless think we have said enough that is right both to justify the family, and to vindicate, for example, our analysis of legitimate parental partiality. 5. valuinG continuity Fer r ac iol i’s second desider at u m for a successf u l ju st i f ic at ion of t he parent-child relationship is that it can explain the continuing value of the r el at ion s h ip b et w e en pa r ent a nd c h i ld a f ter t he c h i ld h a s r e ac he d adulthood. while we agree that there is great value to such relationships— and we think our theory explains it—we reject her view if it is understood as proposing an adequacy condition on a justification of the family. we nevertheless found this objection helpful in clarifying what the project of justifying the family is. the task of justifying the family is different from the task of exposing all of the good-making features of the family. Ferracioli’s description of the 239 Harry Brighouse & Adam Swift LEAP 3 (2015) value of continuing relationships bet ween parent and child beyond the latter’s childhood does, indeed, seem to us to be a description of something very good in human relationships, that the family (or something very like it) makes possible. in justifying the family, though, we are trying to justify a distinctive arrangement that, given its unusual character and, in particular, its assignment of considerable discretion in the use of coercive power to some human beings over others who are asymmetrically dependent and vulnerable, appears to call for justification. a principle of parsimony seems in order: we should invoke just those good-making features that are needed in order to do the justificatory work, and no more. we do think that the good of continuing relationships in adulthood adds to the value of the family, but invoking it to justify arrangements of this kind is not necessary and, in fact, probably does no work, because the relationship it refers to is among consenting adults. anticipating this response, Ferracioli (2016: 212) rejects it as follows: “one reason why this response is unsatisfactory is that the inability of the child to exit a parent-child relationship is not a necessary feature of this sort of relationship and that it is possible for there to be intimate relationships where the child actually enjoys exit options. these are, for instance, relationships where a parent lacks custody rights over the child and decides to give the child a lot of space to choose whether or not, and to what extent, to partake in the relationship. one might think that the enjoyment of exit options on the part of the child dispels the need for justification in such cases, but i take it that the degree of int imacy involved at a l l stages of t he relat ionship, a nd t he mere possibi lit y t hat societ y cou ld be a rra nged dif ferent ly, suf f ice for ma k i ng t he pa rent-ch i ld relat ionsh ip, at its most genera l level, proper subject of philosophical justification. it would therefore be unsatisf y ing if Brighouse and Sw ift were solely in the business of explaining why it is permissible for there to be relationships between competent parents and children where the latter have no prospect of exiting the relationship”. we are not sure whether we understand the case properly. if the child had exit options from the start of the relationship it seems to us that it just isn’t a parent-child relationship. is the child mature enough that a responsible parent is justified in giving her exit options, as opposed to on the one hand making the choice for her (because he is in the rare situation of having good reasons to believe she will be much better off without him) or, on the other, giving her temporary space to spend less time with him? if so, then it is not clear that he is, any longer, a parent to her because, even before she exits, he is no longer playing the fiduciary role. in any case, we agree with Ferracioli Advantage, Authority, Autonomy and Continuity 240 LEAP 3 (2015) that something is going wrong in this relationship, and we agree that our theory does not explain what is going wrong, but we are not unsatisfied with this. that said, we think that our justification of the family does help to explain the value of the continuation of the parent-child relationship into the child’s adulthood. in general, it is good for people to continue intimate relationships with others, and it is easy to see why, for the parent, continued intimacy with an adult whom he has raised from childhood would be especially good. it is similarly easy to see why the loss of that relationship might be devastating. For the child, continuing into adulthood a relationship with someone who has overseen her development, but from whom she is now independent, is distinctively valuable, and in ways that go beyond the disorientation likely to result from the ending of the relationship. concluDinG coMMent it is delight f u l to have one’s work read at a l l. to have it read ca ref u l ly, thoughtfully, and engaged with by excellent critics is an honor. we’re grateful to the editors for prompting the critics and to the critics for giving us such rich food for thought. BiBlioGraPhy Brighouse, h., and a. Swift, 2011: “legitimate Partiality: Parents and Patriots”, in Arguing for Justice: Essays for Philippe Van Parijs, ed. a, Gosseries and y. vanderborght, 115-24, louvain-la-neuve: Presses universitaires de louvain. — 2014: Family Values: The Ethics of Parent-Child Relationships, Princeton nJ: Princeton university Press. clayton, M., 2015: “how Much do we owe to children?”, in Permissible Progeny?, ed. S. hannan et al., 246-64, new york: oxford university Press. Ferracioli, l., 2016: “why the Family?”, Law, Ethics and Philosophy 3: 205-219 Gheaus, a., 2011: “arguments for nonparental care for children”, Social Theory and Practice 37:483-509. — 2012: “the right to Parent one’s Biological Baby”, Journal of Political Philosophy 20: 432-55. — 2016: “is there a right to Parent?”, Law, Ethics and Philosophy 3:193-204 Schapiro, t., 1999: “what is a child?”, Ethics 109: 715-38. Scheffler, S., 2003: Boundaries and Allegiances: Problems of Justice and Responsibility in Liberal Thought, oxford: oxford university Press. Shields, l., 2016: “how Bad can a Good enough Parent Be?”, Canadian Journal of Philosophy: published online, Doi 10.1080/00455091.2016.1148306. Stroud, S., “egalitarian Family values?”, Law, Ethics and Philosophy 3: 180-192 Swift, a., 2003: How Not To Be A Hypocrite: School Choice for the Morally Perplexed Parent, london: routledge. LEAP 3 (2015)