Mathematical Problems of Computer Science 56, 65–72, 2021. UDC 510.6 On Proof Complexity of Some Type of Tautologies Vahagn N. Altunyan and Garik V. Petrosyan Yerevan State University e-mail: altunyanv@gmail.com, garik.petrosyan.1@gmail.com Abstract In this paper, we investigate the proof complexities of a special type of tautologies, which are described as tautologies consisting of implications and literals. In particular, we prove that the proof of this kind of tautologies can be polynomially reduced to the proof of tautologies consisting of formulas that are described by sign-alternating trees. Keywords: Frege systems, Tautology, Sign-alternating tree, Proof complexity. 1. Introduction One of the most fundamental problems of the proof complexity theory is to find an efficient proof system for classical propositional calculus. There is a widespread understanding that polynomial-time computability is the correct mathematical model of feasible computation. According to the opinion, a truly effective system should have a polynomial-size p(n) proof for every tautology of size n. In [1], Cook and Reckhow named such a system a super system. They showed that NP = coNP iff there exists a super system. It is well known that many systems are not super. This question about the Frege system, the most natural calculi for propositional logic, is still open. In many papers, some specific sets of tautologies are introduced, and it is shown that the question about polynomially bounded sizes for Frege-proofs of all tautologies is reduced to an analogous question for a set of specific tautologies. In particular, Lutz Strasburger introduced in [2] the notion of balanced formulas and showed that if there are polynomially bounded Frege proofs for the set of balanced tautologies, then the Frege systems are super. An analogous result for some other class of tautologies is proved in [3]. In this work, we introduce formulas that can be described by sign-alternating trees (sat formulas) and show that the proofs of tautologies that contain only ⊃ and ¬ symbols, where ¬ is used only in literals, can be polynomially reduced to proofs of specific formulas constructed from sat formulas. 2. Main Notions and Notations We will use the current concepts of a classical tautology, Frege proof systems for classical propositional logic, proof and proof complexity [1]. Let us recall some of them. 65 66 On Proof Complexity of Some Type of Tautologies A Frege system F uses a denumerable set of propositional variables, a finite, complete set of propositional connectives; F has a finite set of inference rules defined by a figure of the form A1A2...An B (the rules of inference with zero hypotheses are the axioms schemes); F must be sound and complete, i.e., for each rule of inference A1A2...An B every truth-value assignment, satisfying A1A2...An, also satisfies B, and F must prove every tautology. The particular choice of a language for the presented propositional formulas is immaterial in this consideration. However, for some technical reasons, we assume that the language contains propositional variables, logical connectives ¬, ∧, ∨, ⊃ and parentheses (, ). Note that some parentheses can be omitted in generally accepted cases. By |φ| we denote the size of a formula φ, defined as the number of entries of all logical signs in it. It is obvious that the full size of a formula, which is understood to be the number of all symbols is bounded by some linear function in |φ|. In the theory of proof complexity, the two main characteristics of the proof are: t- complexity (length), defined as the number of proof steps, l-complexity (size), defined as the sum of sizes for all formulas in the proof (formal definitions are, for example, in [4]). Let ϕ be a proof system and φ be a tautology. We denote by lϕφ(t ϕ φ) the minimal possible value of l-complexity (t-complexity) for all ϕ-proofs of tautology φ. Let M be some set of tautologies. Definition 1: We call the ϕ-proofs of tautologies from a set M l-polynomially (t- polynomially) bounded if there is a polynomial p such that lϕφ ≤ p(|φ|) (tϕφ ≤ p(|φ|)) for all φ from M. Definition 2: We call the ϕ-proofs of tautologies from a set M l-linearly (t-linearly) bounded if there is a linear function f such that lϕφ ≤ f(|φ|) (tϕφ ≤ f(|φ|)) for all φ from M. Now we’ll give the definition of sat formulas and prove some lemmas, which are necessary for proving the main result. Definition 3: We’ll say that a formula is described by a sign-alternating tree (sat formula) if it satisfies the following rules. 1. it’s a literal 2. has a form r ∧ (T1 ∨ T2), where r is a literal and T1, T2 are sat formulas Lemma 1: For any formulas A, B, C, the following formulas have polynomially bounded proofs. 1. A ≡ (C ⊃ A) ∧ (¬C ⊃ A) 2. A ⊃ (B ⊃ A) 3. (¬A ⊃ (B ⊃ A)) ≡ (¬A ⊃ ¬B) 4. ¬¬A ≡ A 5. A ⊃ (B ⊃ C) ≡ A ∧ B ⊃ C 6. A ∧ ¬A ∧ B ⊃ C V. Altunyan and G. Petrosyan 67 7. A ∧ B ⊃ A 8. ¬(A ⊃ B) ≡ A ∧ ¬B 9. A ⊃ (B ∧ C) ≡ (A ⊃ B) ∧ (A ⊃ C) 10. A ⊃ (B ⊃ C) ≡ B ⊃ (A ⊃ C) 11. A ⊃ (A ⊃ B) ≡ A ⊃ B 12. (A ⊃ B) ∧ (C ⊃ B) ≡ (A ∨ C) ⊃ B The proof is trivial as all the formulas are tautologies and have fixed length proofs, so the proof complexities may be assumed to be linearly bounded. Lemma 2: Tautologies of the form A ⊃ (B1 ⊃ ...(Bn−1 ⊃ (Bn ⊃ A))...) have polynomially bounded proofs. Proof. We can prove the tautology above by the following steps. A ⊢ A A ⊢ A ⊃ (Bn ⊃ A) 2nd formula of Lemma 1 A ⊢ (Bn ⊃ A) modus ponens A ⊢ (Bn ⊃ A) ⊃ (Bn−1 ⊃ (Bn ⊃ A)) A ⊢ (Bn−1 ⊃ (Bn ⊃ A)) modus ponens ... A ⊢ (B1 ⊃ ...(Bn−1 ⊃ (Bn ⊃ A))...) The number of proof steps is linearly bounded and the size of each formula in proof is also linearly bounded, so the proof is polynomially bounded. Lemma 3: Tautologies of the form d1 ⊃ (d2 ⊃ (... ⊃ dk)...) where d1, d2, ..., dk are literals, have polynomially bounded proofs. Proof. After applying the operation of replacement by an equivalent formula (k − 2) times using the 5th formula of Lemma 1, we get: d1 ⊃ (d2 ⊃ (... ⊃ dk)...) ≡ d1 ∧ d2 ∧ ... ∧ dk−1 ⊃ dk In this case, if there exist 1 ≤ i, j, ≤ k − 1 such that di = ¬dj then replacing them with equivalent formulas using the 6th formula of Lemma 1, we’ll get a polynomially bounded proof, or if there exist such 1 ≤ i ≤ k − 1 such that di = dk then replacing it with equiv- alent formulas using the 7th formula of Lemma 1, we’ll get a polynomially bounded proof, otherwise the formula isn’t a tautology. 68 On Proof Complexity of Some Type of Tautologies 3. Main Result Definition 4: Any propositional formula A is called sat-constructed if it is in the following form: A = ¬(T1 ∧ T2 ∧ ... ∧ Tn), where Ti(1 ≤ i ≤ n) are sat formulas. Theorem 1: Let M be the set of all sat-constructed tautologies. If proofs of formulas from the set M are l-polynomially (t-polynomially) bounded, then proofs of all tautologies contain- ing only ⊃ and ¬ symbols, where ¬ is used only in literals, are l-polynomially (t-polynomially) bounded. Proof. We need to prove that any tautology A containing only ⊃ and ¬ symbols, where ¬ is used only in literals, can be reduced to a sat-constructed tautology in polynomially bounded number of steps and length. If the number of implications in the formula is bounded by, let’s say, 3, then it can be reduced to ¬(p1 ∧ ¬p1), and the reduction complexity will be constant which is also a polynomial. We now assume that formula A contains more than 3 implications. A can be expressed in the following form: A = (S1 ⊃ ...(Sc−1 ⊃ (Sc ⊃ q1))...) (1) where Si(1 ≤ i ≤ c) are sub-formulas and q1 is a literal. We can replace A with an equivalent formula using the 1st formula of Lemma 1 and get (q1 ⊃ A) ∧ (¬q1 ⊃ A). The first half has a polynomially bounded proof by Lemma 2. For the second half, we can apply the operation of replacement by an equivalent formula using the 3rd formula of Lemma 1 and get: ¬q1 ⊃ (S1 ⊃ ...(Sc−1 ⊃ (Sc ⊃ q1))...) ≡ ¬q1 ⊃ (S1 ⊃ ...(Sc−1 ⊃ ¬Sc)...) So the proof of A has been polynomially reduced to the proof of ¬q1 ⊃ (S1 ⊃ ...(Sc−1 ⊃ ¬Sc)...). If Sc is a literal, then we can repeat the same process for the formula we got. After some repetitions, we’ll end up either with a tautology d1 ⊃ (d2 ⊃ (... ⊃ dk)...), where di(1 ≤ i ≤ k) are literals. This tautology has a polynomially bounded proof by Lemma 3. Or we’ll end up with the following formula: d1 ⊃ (d2 ⊃ ... ⊃ (dm ⊃ (U1 ⊃ ...(Uk ⊃ ¬F)...))...) (2) where di(1 ≤ i ≤ m) are literals and F is not a literal. Suppose F = F1 ⊃ F2, applying the replacement by an equivalent formula using the 8th formula of Lemma 1, we’ll get: d1 ⊃ (d2 ⊃ ... ⊃ (dm ⊃ (U1 ⊃ ...(Uk ⊃ ¬F)...))...) ≡ d1 ⊃ (d2 ⊃ ... ⊃ (dm ⊃ (U1 ⊃ ...(Uk ⊃ (F1 ∧ ¬F2))...))...) Applying the operation of replacement by an equivalent formula multiple times using the 9th formula of Lemma 1, we’ll get: d1 ⊃ (d2 ⊃ ... ⊃ (dm ⊃ (U1 ⊃ ...(Uk ⊃ (F1 ∧ ¬F2))...))...) ≡ d1 ⊃ (d2 ⊃ ... ⊃ (dm ⊃ (U1 ⊃ ...(Uk ⊃ F1)...))...)∧ d1 ⊃ (d2 ⊃ ... ⊃ (dm ⊃ (U1 ⊃ ...(Uk ⊃ ¬F2)...))...) V. Altunyan and G. Petrosyan 69 So, after polynomially bounded number of steps, we reduced the proof of A to the proof of two formulas, the first one of which has the form (1) and the second one has the form (2). Repeating the same process for these formulas, we’ll get l tautologies, and the proof of A will be reduced to the proof of these tautologies: d11 ⊃ (d 1 2 ⊃ ... ⊃ (d 1 m1 ⊃ (d1 ⊃ (d2 ⊃ ... ⊃ (dm ⊃ (U1 ⊃ ... ⊃ ¬Uk))...)))...) d21 ⊃ (d 2 2 ⊃ ... ⊃ (d 2 m2 ⊃ (d1 ⊃ (d2 ⊃ ... ⊃ (dm ⊃ (U1 ⊃ ... ⊃ ¬Uk))...)))...) ... dl1 ⊃ (d l 2 ⊃ ... ⊃ (d l ml ⊃ (d1 ⊃ (d2 ⊃ ... ⊃ (dm ⊃ (U1 ⊃ ... ⊃ ¬Uk))...)))...) where di1, d i 2, ..., d i mi (1 ≤ i ≤ l) are literals. There are no repetitions among di1, d i 2, ..., d i mi , d1, ..., dm, otherwise we can keep a single one of each repetition - replacing by equivalent formulas using the 10th and 11th formulas of Lemma 1. We may also assume that there are no variable repetitions, because if a variable and it’s negation are present, then the formula can be polynomially proved. So we can assume that all the literals among di1, d i 2, ..., d i mi , d1, ..., dm are different and all the variables are also different and so the number of those literals doesn’t exceed |A|. Also note that each time a new formula was generated an implication from F was removed, so l < |F| < |A|. Applying the operation of replacement by an equivalent formula using the 10th formula of Lemma 1, we’ll get the following form for our l formulas: C1 = d2 ⊃ (d3 ⊃ ... ⊃ (dm ⊃ (d1 ⊃ (d11 ⊃ ... ⊃ (d 1 m1 ⊃ (U1 ⊃ ... ⊃ ¬Uk))...)))...) C2 = d2 ⊃ (d3 ⊃ ... ⊃ (dm ⊃ (d1 ⊃ (d21 ⊃ ... ⊃ (d 2 m2 ⊃ (U1 ⊃ ... ⊃ ¬Uk))...)))...) ... Cl = d2 ⊃ (d3 ⊃ ... ⊃ (dm ⊃ (d1 ⊃ (dl1 ⊃ ... ⊃ (d l ml ⊃ (U1 ⊃ ... ⊃ ¬Uk))...)))...) At this point, we’ve reduced the proof of A to the proof of C1 ∧C2 ∧ ...∧Cl polynomially. Applying the operation of replacement by an equivalent formula using the 9th formula of Lemma 1, we’ll get: C1 ∧ C2 ∧ ... ∧ Cl ≡ d2 ⊃ (d3 ⊃ ... ⊃ (dm ⊃ (C′1 ∧ C ′ 2 ∧ ... ∧ C ′ l))...) where C′1 = (d1 ⊃ (d 1 1 ⊃ ... ⊃ (d 1 m1 ⊃ (U1 ⊃ ... ⊃ ¬Uk))...)) C′2 = (d1 ⊃ (d 2 1 ⊃ ... ⊃ (d 2 m2 ⊃ (U1 ⊃ ... ⊃ ¬Uk))...)) ... C′l = (d1 ⊃ (d l 1 ⊃ ... ⊃ (d l ml ⊃ (U1 ⊃ ... ⊃ ¬Uk))...)) Applying the operation of replacement by an equivalent formula using the 5th formula of Lemma 1, we’ll get the following form for above formulas: C′1 = d1 ∧ d 1 1 ∧ ... ∧ d 1 m1 ⊃ (U1 ⊃ ... ⊃ ¬Uk) C′2 = d1 ∧ d 2 1 ∧ ... ∧ d 2 m2 ⊃ (U1 ⊃ ... ⊃ ¬Uk) ... C′l = d1 ∧ d l 1 ∧ ... ∧ d l ml ⊃ (U1 ⊃ ... ⊃ ¬Uk) 70 On Proof Complexity of Some Type of Tautologies Applying the operation of replacement by an equivalent formula using the 12th formula of Lemma 1, we’ll get: C′1 ∧ C ′ 2 ∧ ... ∧ C ′ l ≡ (d1 ∧ d 1 1 ∧ ... ∧ d 1 m1 ∨ d1 ∧ d21 ∧ ... ∧ d 2 m1 ∨ ...∨ d1 ∧ dl1 ∧ ... ∧ d l m1 ) ⊃ (U1 ⊃ ... ⊃ ¬Uk) Let’s prove that the DNF generated above - (d1 ∧ d11 ∧ ... ∧ d1m1 ∨ d1 ∧ d 2 1 ∧ ... ∧ d2m1 ∨ ... ∨ d1 ∧ dl1 ∧ ... ∧ dlm1) is an sat formula. As we can see, each of the conjunctions includes d1. Note that we can clearly split the DNF into two subDNF’s - one generated from F1 and the other generated from F2. For each of F1 and F2, we repeated the same process and so if the generated DNFs from F1 and F2 are both sat formulas, then the DNF generated above is also an sat formula. Note that we can make the assumption above, as after finite repetitions of splitting operation, we’ll reach a literal, which is an sat formula. At this point, we have polynomially reduced the proof of tautology A to the proof of the following tautology: d2 ⊃ (d3 ⊃ ... ⊃ (dm ⊃ (d1 ∧ d11 ∧ ... ∧ d 1 m1 ∨ d1 ∧ d21 ∧ ... ∧ d 2 m1 ∨ ...∨ d1 ∧ dl1 ∧ ... ∧ d l m1 ) ⊃ (U1 ⊃ ... ⊃ ¬Uk)...) By deduction theorem the proof of the above formula is equivalent to the following proof: d2, ..., dm, (d1 ∧ d11 ∧ ... ∧ d 1 m1 ∨ d1 ∧ d21 ∧ ... ∧ d 2 m1 ∨ ...∨ d1 ∧ dl1 ∧ ... ∧ d l m1 ) ⊢ (U1 ⊃ ... ⊃ ¬Uk)...) Note that all the hypotheses are sat formulas and that we can repeat all the previous steps on formula (U1 ⊃ ... ⊃ ¬Uk) even though we have some hypotheses. Repeating this process, the proof of A will be reduced to the proof of the following formula: T1 ∧ T2 ∧ ... ∧ Tn ⊃ c1, where Ti(1 ≤ i ≤ n) are sat formulas and c1 is a literal. Note that new Ti-s are generated only when we consider the last sub-formula of A and then remove it for the next step, so this guarantees that n ≤ |A|. Applying the operation of replacement by an equivalent formula using the 1st formula of Lemma 1, we’ll get: T1 ∧ T2 ∧ ... ∧ Tn ⊃ c1 ≡ (c1 ⊃ (T1 ∧ T2 ∧ ... ∧ Tn ⊃ c1)) ∧ (¬c1 ⊃ (T1 ∧ T2 ∧ ... ∧ Tn ⊃ c1)) The tautology (c1 ⊃ (T1 ∧ T2 ∧ ... ∧ Tn ⊃ c1)) has a polynomially bounded proof. We reduced the proof of A to the proof of (¬c1 ⊃ (T1 ∧ T2 ∧ ... ∧ Tn ⊃ c1)). Applying the operation of replacement by an equivalent formula using the 3rd formula of Lemma 1, we’ll get: A ≡ ¬(T1 ∧ T2 ∧ ... ∧ Tn) All the operations have polynomial complexity. The number of steps is also polynomially bounded, so the total complexity of reduction is polynomially bounded. V. Altunyan and G. Petrosyan 7 1 4 . Co n c lu s io n In t h is wo r k, we in t r o d u c e d sat fo r m u la s a n d r e d u c e d t h e p r o o fs o f t a u t o lo g ie s c o n t a in in g o n ly ¾ a n d : s ym b o ls , wh e r e : is u s e d o n ly in lit e r a ls , t o t h e p r o o fs o f sat-constructed t a u t o lo g ie s in p o lyn o m ia lly b o u n d e d n u m b e r o f s t e p s a n d le n g t h . In ve s t ig a t io n o f p r o o f c o m p le xit ie s o f sat-constructed t a u t o lo g ie s is in p r o c e s s . R e fe r e n c e s [1 ] S . A . Co o k a n d A . R . R e c kh o w, \ Th e r e la t ive e ± c ie n c y o f p r o p o s it io n a l p r o o f s ys t e m s " , J ournal of Symbolic logic, vo l. 4 4 , p p . 3 6 -5 0 , 1 9 7 9 . [2 ] L . S t r a s b u r g e r , \ E xt e n s io n wit h o u t Cu t " , Annals of P ure and Applied L ogic, vo l. 1 6 3 , n o . 1 2 , p p . 1 9 9 5 -2 0 0 7 , 2 0 1 2 . [3 ] A . A . Ch u b a r ya n a n d G. V . P e t r o s ya n , \ S o m e n o t e s o n p r o o f c o m p le xit ie s in Fr e g e s ys t e m s " , Sciences of E urope, vo l 1 . # 1 2 ( 1 2 ) , P h ys ic s a n d Ma t h e m a t ic s , p p . 3 1 { 3 4 , 2 0 1 7 . [4 ] J. N o r d s t r o m , \ N a r r o w p r o o fs m a y b e s p a c io u s : S e p a r a t in g s p a c e a n d wid t h in r e s o - lu t io n " , SIAM J ournal on Computing, vo l. 3 9 , n o . 1 , p p . 5 9 -1 2 1 , 2 0 1 9 . Submitted 08.09.2021, accepted 18.11.2021. àñáß ïÇåÇ ÝáõÛݳµ³ÝáõÃÛáõÝÝ»ñÇ ³ñï³ÍÙ³Ý µ³ñ¹áõÃÛáõÝÝ»ñÇ í»ñ³µ»ñÛ³É ì³Ñ³·Ý Ü. ²ÉÃáõÝÛ³Ý ¨ ¶³ñÇÏ ì. ä»ïñáëÛ³Ý ºñ¨³ÝÇ å»ï³Ï³Ý ѳٳÉë³ñ³Ý e-mail: altunyanv@gmail.com, garik.petrosyan.1@gmail.com ²Ù÷á÷áõÙ ²Ûë Ñá¹í³ÍáõÙ áõëáõÙݳëÇñíáõÙ »Ý ³ñï³ÍÙ³Ý µ³ñ¹áõÃÛáõÝÝ»ñÁ ѳïáõÏ ïÇåÇ ÝáõÛݳµ³ÝáõÃÛáõÝÝ»ñÇ Ñ³Ù³ñ, áñáÝù Ýϳñ³·ñíáõÙ »Ù áñå»ë ÇÙåÉÇϳódzݻñáí ¨ ÉÇï»ñ³ÉÝ»ñáí ϳ½Ùí³Í ÝáõÛݳµ³ÝáõÃÛáõÝÝ»ñ: سëݳíáñ³å»ë ³å³óáõóí»É ¿, áñ ³Û¹ ï»ëùÇ ÝáõÛݳµ³ÝáõÃÛáõÝ»ñÇ ³ñï³ÍáõÙÝ»ñÁ µ³½Ù³Ý¹³Ùáñ»Ý ѳݷ»óíáõÙ »Ý Ý߳ݳ÷áË Í³é»ñáí Ý»ñϳ۳óíáÕ ÝáõÛݳµ³ÝáõÃÛáõÝ Ñ³Ý¹Çë³óáÕ µ³Ý³Ó¨»ñÇ ³ñï³ÍáõÙÝ»ñÇÝ: ´³Ý³ÉÇ µ³é»ñ՝ üñ»·»Ç ѳٳϳñ·»ñ, ÝáõÛݳµ³ÝáõÃÛáõÝÝ»ñ, Ý߳ݳ÷áË Í³é»ñ, ³ñï³ÍÙ³Ý µ³ñ¹áõÃÛáõÝ: 7 2 On Proof Complexity of Some Type of Tautologies Î ñëîæíîñòè âûâîäîâ íåêîòîðîãî òèïà òàâòîëîãèé Âààãí Í. Àëòóíÿí è Ãàðèê Â. Ïåòðîñÿí Åðåâàíñêèé ãîñóäàðñòâåííûé óíèâåðñèòåò e-mail: altunyanv@gmail.com, garik.petrosyan.1@gmail.com Àííîòàöèÿ  íàñòîÿùåé ñòàòüå èññëåäîâàíû ñëîæíîñòè âûâîäîâ òàâòîëîãèé ñïåöèàëüíîãî âèäà, êîòîðûå ìîæíî îïèñàòü êàê òàâòîëîãèè ñîñòîÿùèå èç èìïëèêàöèé è ëèòåðàëîâ.  ÷àñòíîñòè, äîêàçàíî, ÷òî âûâîäû òàâòîëîãèé òàêîãî âèäà ìîæíî ïîëèíîìèàëüíî ñâåñòè ê âûâîäàì òàâòîëîãèé, êîòîðûå ÿâëÿþòñÿ ôîðìóëàìè, îïèñûâàåìûìè çíàêîïåðåìåííûìè äåðåâüÿìè. Êëþ÷åâûå ñëîâà: ñèñòåìû Ôðåãå, òàâòîëîãèè, çíàêîïåðåìåííûå äåðåâüÿ, ñëîæíîñòü âûâîäà. 06_Altunyan_56 5555