Stoekl, ''Round Dusk: Kojeve at "The End"', Postmodern Culture v5n1
URL = http://infomotions.com/serials/pmc/pmc-v5n1-stoekl-round.txt

Archive PMC-LIST, file stoekl.994.
Part 1/1, total size 55126 bytes:

------------------------------ Cut here ------------------------------
               'Round Dusk: Kojeve at "The End"

                                  by

                             Allan Stoekl

           Departments of French and Comparative Literature
                    Pennsylvania State University

             Postmodern Culture v.5 n.1 (September, 1994)

               Copyright (c) 1994 by Allan Stoekl, all rights
               reserved. This text may be used and shared in
               accordance with the fair-use provisions of U.S.
               copyright law, and it may be archived and
               redistributed in electronic form, provided that
               the editors are notified and no fee is charged
               for access. Archiving, redistribution, or
               republication of this text on other terms, in any
               medium, requires the consent of the author and
               the notification of the publisher, Oxford
               University Press.

[1]  The postmodern moment has been characterized as one of the
     loss of legitimacy of the master narratives--social,
     historical, political; Hegelian, Marxist, Fascist--by which
     lives were ordered and sacrificed throughout the nineteenth
     and twentieth centuries.^1^

[2]  The demise of the great story, which gave direction and
     purpose to struggle and violence, has opened a space for a
     proliferation of conflicting modes of interpreting and
     speaking.  Of course those modes can only be partial: they
     can never aspire to the horrifying totalization promoted by
     overarching certainties.  And they will likely interfere
     with each other, cross over, meld and (self) contradict,
     because the possibility of their autonomy has been given
     up; at best we can say that they are "language games" now,
     rules for representation, argument, and analysis; no longer
     are they the ground of teleology, satisfaction, and
     self-certainty.

[3]  But there is a problem with this kind of argument, as I
     see it.  It's not that I do not find it "true," because of
     some kind of empirical counter-evidence, such as: the old
     nationalist narratives still hold sway; history is still
     slouching toward a goal; history isn't slouching toward a
     goal, but it is nevertheless still slouching, etc.  One can
     probably develop all sorts of arguments based on empirical
     observation concerning the postmodern.  Or one can just as
     easily "deconstruct" the master stories from within, by
     taking them apart while still, necessarily, acting in full
     complicity with them (for what "space" could be said to
     open beyond their margins?).  The problem, as I see it, is
     that this kind of argument is closely tied to the "end of
     history" arguments that were current in the immediate
     postwar period, and that have recently had a renewed but
     highly contested efflorescence.^2^  This is of course
     immensely ironic, because philosophers such as
     Lyotard--spokespersons of the postmodern--have informed us
     that the possibility of a larger teleology is lost for
     good, along with the knowledge that flowed from it.  But
     there still is a larger knowledge, after all--the one that
     proclaims the death of the possibility of a larger
     knowledge.  Whether arrived at empirically or logically,
     this awareness comes at the end of a series of historical
     actions and tragedies, and the certainty associated with it
     is no doubt due to lessons derived from those failures.
     This history will still have the form of a narrative,
     albeit one that lacks, perhaps, the power of retrospective
     justification that characterized the Hegelian model.  Its
     lessons might be purely practical, or they might be derived
     from a study of the incoherences or contradictions of the
     earlier paradigms.  The net result, whatever the means of
     their determination, development and (self) cancelling,
     will be a generally valid knowledge that mandates the end
     of generally valid knowledges.  The language games that
     proliferate, then, in a postmodern epoch will be allowed
     and encouraged to do so only because the way has been
     opened by yet another master narrative: the narrative of
     the end of narratives.  The freedom to be enjoyed by the
     games is the result of the master story's knowledge--but,
     to be sure, the games' actions, their orientations, will
     not be determined by it.  They will be independent of
     it--but the preservation of their semi-autonomous
     functioning is nevertheless the goal of a postmodern
     theoretical project (such as one that affirms adjudication
     between different, conflicting, games).  Further, it is
     their guarantee that they will participate in a stable
     postmodern order: without the postmodern narrative and its
     powers of harmonization, they would risk falling into
     particularist discourses into which "nationalist"
     ideologies are prone.

[4]  Is this postmodern version of things that different from a
     theory of the "end of history" that envisages a State
     founded on the mutual recognition of free subjects?  On the
     surface, yes: the postmodern view concerns itself not with
     subjectivity, consciousness as productive labor, and the
     like, but on the recognition of difference between partial
     discourses and "constructed" cultures.  The posthistorical
     model seems almost quaint with its emphasis on codified law
     and the State as guarantor of a freedom identifiable with
     labor and construction.  But beyond these evident
     differences there may be a more fundamental similarity.

[5]  Just as the postmodern presents language games as
     independent of transcendent social reason, so too the
     posthistorical imagines the moment of the ultimate end of
     history as a kind of definitive break, after which life
     will go on, but in which unidirectional history will be
     supplanted by "playful" activities that may be enjoyable in
     themselves, but that will by necessity not be recuperable
     in any larger social or historical scheme.  The State at the
     end of history will be as unconcerned with these ludic
     activities--sports, arts, love making, and so on--as the
     postmodern regime will be with justifying the logic of the
     language games of what we would call the cultures,
     subcultures, and micro-cultures whose disputes would be 
     subject to its acts of arbitration.^3^

[6]  On the surface of it at least, Alexandre Kojeve's
     take on Hegel in his _Introduction to the Reading of Hegel_
     can be seen as being not an attempt at the ultimate
     vindication of a "grand" historical and philosophical
     narrative--the triumph of the end of history and the
     univocal (self) satisfaction of the entire population of
     the earth--but instead the surprising mutation of that
     certainty, that knowledge, into a postmodern generation of
     discourses and styles.^4^  History as narrative triumphs,
     but it also ends: its termination is the opening for the
     proliferation of poses and play that is literally post
     modern.  Rather than contradicting Kojeve, then, or
     demonstrating the extent to which a Hegelian modernism is
     null and void, a rigorous postmodern might see itself as
     deriving from a completion and fulfillment of a dialectical
     project.  It *might*.

[7]  The postmodern, we could argue, has already come part of
     the way.  It has posited a knowledge--the authority of its
     own text--that in spite of itself stands as a knowledge at
     the end of a long history of illusions.  It takes itself as
     a stranger to, and grave digger for, the Hegelian
     tradition.  Kojeve, on the other hand, at least
     recognizes the inescapability, the inevitability, of the
     univocal truth of his own system.  But he is blind to the
     consequences of the termination of history: the
     proliferation of signs and acts that, by their very nature
     as partial constructions, challenge the totalizing power of
     the Concept.

[8]  To get any further we will have to look at certain key
     passages of Kojeve's _Introduction_.  Most often in
     footnotes and asides, he grapples with the really crucial
     questions: what does it mean for "Man" to "die"?  What will
     come "after" the end of history?  If "Man" is dead, what
     will remain of human labor?  What will be the status of the
     "Book" in which Knowledge resides?  The answers to these
     questions will enable us to consider in more detail the
     problem of the relation been posthistory and the postmodern.

[9]  According to most historians of French philosophy of the
     twentieth century, it was Kojeve who single-handedly
     popularized Hegel in France, through a brilliant series of
     lectures in the 1930s.  After decades of idealist
     neo-Kantianism, the Hegel that Kojeve preferred was
     a welcome change: History could now be seen as a
     dialectical progression in which Man ineluctably moves
     toward a social satisfaction in which the desire for
     recognition--and the recognition of the other's desire for
     recognition--is fulfilled.  The posthistorical State alone
     is capable of recognizing Man for what he is: beyond all
     superstition, all theology, Man is the creative/destructive
     agent whose labor ends in the recognition of all by all
     through the mediation of the State.  The labor of Hegel's
     slave, its destructive and formative action, "transforms"
     "natural given being": Man is the "Time that annihilates
     [nature]" (158).  But in the end all transformative labor
     ceases.  History comes to an end because, eventually at
     least, the labor leading to full reciprocal recognition
     will have been carried out: at the end of history, there
     will be nothing new to accomplish.

[10] Now the end of history for Kojeve is the ultimate
     ideological weapon because it justifies, retrospectively,
     just about anything that went before that made its arrival
     possible.  Man for Kojeve is a type: the Master, the
     Slave, the Philosopher, and, at the end, the impersonal
     Hegel (and his reader, Kojeve), that is, the Wise
     Man (%le Sage%).  The negativity that made the arrival of
     the end possible will, in retrospect, be judged moral, no
     matter how it seemed at the time.  And since Man himself is
     defined as temporality and negation (IRH 160), even the
     bloodiest violence or the grossest injustice, if necessary
     for the eventual completion, will be (or will have been)
     good.
          The true moral judgments are those borne by the State 
          (moral=legal); States themselves are judged by universal 
          history.  But for these judgments to have a meaning, 
          History must be completed.  And Napoleon and Hegel end 
          history.  That is why Hegel can judge States and
          individuals.  The "good" is everything that has made
          possible Hegel, in other words the formation of the
          universal Napoleonic Empire (it is 1807!) which is
          "understood" by Hegel (in and through the 
          _Phenomenology_).  What is good is what exists, the 
          extent that it exists.  All action, since it negates 
          existing givens, is thus bad: a sin.  But sin can be 
          pardoned.  How?  Through its success.  Success absolves 
          crime, because success--is a new reality that *exists*. 
          But how to judge success?  For that, History has to be 
          completed.  Then one can see what is maintained in
          existence: definitive reality. (ILH, 95)

[11] This is the "ruse of reason": reason acting in and through
     History reaches its end in ways that might seem to have
     nothing to do with accepted ("Christian") morality.
     Certainly anyone attempting to judge the morality or
     immorality of events before the end of history will be
     incapable of it; only with Hegel (and Kojeve) will
     the true value and morality of actions be evident.  Not only
     do the ends always justify the means, but they do so
     retroactively, so that agents ("people") will never be
     competent to judge the acceptability of their own behavior.
     The "Owl of Minerva flies at dusk," to use a Hegelian
     formulation: only when the outcome is final and its
     corresponding overview are grasped can all preceding events
     be fully *known*.^5^

[12] But in a way all this is irrelevant: since history for
     Kojeve is already ended, everything that takes place
     now is a purely technical "catching up" process.  The end of
     History was achieved at the battle of Jena: Napoleon's
     conquering forces brought the egalitarian ideals of the
     French revolution, codified and implemented by the State,
     to others.  From now on History will only be a series of
     lesser battles of Jena, leading to the implementation
     throughout the world, by bureaucratic governments, of
     rights and liberties.  What at first might seem to be the
     ultimate 1930s justification of ruthlessness at any cost
     (indeed Stalin comes to replace Napoleon for Kojeve
     in the pre-World War II period) leads inevitably, in the
     late 40s and 50s, to a recognition that the difference
     between ideologies is largely irrelevant.  How one arrives
     at the "classless" society, the society of the mutual
     recognition of the desire for recognition, is of no
     interest to the "Wise Man": it is a purely *technical*
     question.  The seemingly great postwar problem of the
     conflict of ideologies, or the question of the defense of
     Soviet ideology in the face of American pressure
     (Merleau-Ponty, _Humanisme et terreur_, Sartre, _Les
     Communistes et la paix_) simply does not exist for
     Kojeve.  The end of history is the end of ideology.
     In a "Note to the Second Edition" of the _Introduction to
     the Reading of Hegel_, inserted in 1959, Kojeve
     states: "One can even say that, from a certain point of
     view, the United States has already attained the final
     stage of Marxist "communism," seeing that, practically, all
     the members of the "classless society" can from now on
     appropriate for themselves everything that seems good to
     them, without thereby working any more than their heart
     dictates" (IRH, 161, note).

[13] Ideology, in the end, is thus utterly unimportant: it too
     fades away once history is at an end.  If it contributes or
     has contributed to that end it is good, if not bad.  Like
     all means it is justified by the end, but *at* the end it
     has no specificity other than its "success."  From the
     perspective of the end, all bloody action is over: it can
     be judged, but it no longer is effective.  In time and as
     time Man is free to act, but he does not know; at the end
     of Time, History is known, but Man can no longer act (he
     has nothing more to do)--hence he no longer even exists.  At
     the end, there are no longer even any means to be
     justified.  History and its ideologies are a matter of utter
     indifference.

[14] This leaves an enormous question, one typical of the
     1950s.  The completion of history is perfectly ahistorical,
     but ahistory itself is a function of history.  True, we are
     now delivered from history, action, and all the hard--and
     ambiguous--moral questions.  The machine of history has
     functioned so well that it has erased itself: its mechanism
     was the unfolding of Truth, but now that we are in the
     definitive era of Truth, History has ceased to exist, and
     its moral conundrums are irrelevant.  At the end of history,
     ideology is finished, and so ceases to exist: but "Man"
     therefore no longer exists either.
          The %Selbst%--that is, Man properly so-called or the 
          free Individual, *is* Time and Time is History, and only
          *History*. . . . And Man is essentially *Negativity*, for
          Time is *Becoming*--that is, the *annihilation* of Being 
          or Space. Therefore Man is a Nothingness that nihilates 
          and that preserves itself in (spatial) Being only by 
          *negating* being, this Negation being Action Now, if Man 
          is Negativity,--that is, Time--he is not eternal. He is 
          born and he dies as Man. He is '%das Negativ seiner 
          selbst%,' Hegel says. And we know what that means: Man 
          overcomes himself as Action (or %Selbst%) by ceasing to 
          oppose himself to the World, after creating in it the 
          universal and homogeneous State; or to put it otherwise, 
          on the cognitive level: Man overcomes himself as *Error* 
          (or "Subject" opposed to the Object) after creating the 
          Truth of "Science" (IRH, 160; emphasis in original).

[15] Man dies at this strange juncture point between History
     and the End (in both senses of the word) of History.  In the
     future, after the end, Kojeve tells us that "life is
     purely biological" (ILH, 387).  But this is a, and perhaps
     the, crucial question for Kojeve: if history stops,
     if Man and Time and negating labor is dead, how then is Man
     any different from the animals?  He had originally
     constituted himself *against* Nature ("But Man, once
     constituted in his human specificity, opposes himself to
     Nature"); nature for Kojeve is timeless and can in
     no way be incorporated in the dialectic.  No "dialectics of
     nature" can therefore be conceived within the
     Kojevian reading of Hegel.^6^  But if man is an
     animal, History itself is not so much completed as dead.  It
     will be--or is now, since History is *already* ended, in
     principle at least--as if History had never existed.

[16] Kojeve presents two approaches to this problem in
     the long footnote to his interpretation of Chapter VIII of
     the _Phenomenology_ (IRH, 158-62), a passage of which I
     have already cited.  First he states that Man indeed is an
     animal, but a happy one, "in *harmony* with Nature or given
     Being."  True, he no longer can engage in productive
     Historical activity, "Action negating the given, . . . the
     Subject *opposed* to the Object."  But he has plenty of
     other consolations: "art, love, play, etc. etc.--in short,
     everything that makes man *happy*" (IRH, 159).  This is a
     "world of freedom" in which men "no longer fight, and work
     as little as possible."

[17] It sounds almost too good to be true: the world itself is
     transformed into a vast, postmodern Southern California,
     its inhabitants concerned above all with training their
     bodies and trading their automobiles and art objects.  It is
     here that one recognizes with a start the perfect
     transformation of a Hegelian modernism into an
     anti-Hegelian, but soft, postmodernism: at the End of
     History History is replaced with a heterogeneous collection
     of lifestyle choices.  Indeed we learn, in the footnote
     added to the second edition of 1959, that Kojeve had
     earlier (in the immediate postwar period, "1948-58") seen
     the "American way of life" as the true posthistorical
     regime--although he also saw the Soviet Union and the
     Chinese Communists as nothing other than "still poor
     Americans" (IRH, 161).  The only larger coherence is a
     general lack of coherence: one is free to cultivate one's
     own interests and ignore the larger movement by which all
     personal activities are justified.  The new human animals
     will "recognize one another without reservation," but this
     recognition will be of the right of each one to be
     completely different, in what promise to be mainly physical
     pursuits.

[18] In a second footnote added in 1959 (the first dates from
     1946), Kojeve objects to his own theory.  Reading his
     earlier note quite literally, he argues that if all Action
     is eliminated from Human life, Man will actually be not an
     American, but an animal:
          "If Man becomes an animal again, his acts, his loves, 
          and his play must also become purely 'natural' again. 
          Hence it would have to be admitted that after the end 
          of History, men would construct their edifices and 
          works of art as birds build their nests and spiders 
          spin their webs. . . . 'The *definitive annihilation* 
          of Man *properly so-called*' also means the definitive 
          disappearance of human Discourse (%Logos%) in the strict 
          sense. Animals of the species %Homo sapiens% would react 
          by conditioned reflexes to vocal signals or sign 
          'language,' and thus their so-called 'discourses' would 
          be like what is supposed to be the 'language' of bees. 
          What would disappear, then, is not only Philosophy or 
          the search for discursive Wisdom, but also that Wisdom 
          itself." (IRH, 159-60; emphasis in original)

[19] The posthistorical, in other words, must be saved from any
     threat of animality--that is, of purely unreflected-upon
     behavior.  Kojeve does not really consider the
     consequences of "art, love, play, etc. etc." because,
     fortunately, he has another example of activity "after the
     end of History."  This is, surprisingly enough, Japan: the
     "American way of life" is now replaced by a model of
     Japanese culture that has been "at the End of History" "for
     almost three centuries."  While "American" posthistory is
     associated with sheer animality, Japanese culture is seen
     by Kojeve as a pure *formalism*.  Unlike the animal,
     Man continues to be a "Subject opposed to the Object,"
     although "action" and "Time" have ceased.  Forms are opposed
     to one another, and values themselves come to be "totally
     *formalized*"--the Japanese tea ceremony, Noh theatre, even
     the suicide of the Kamikaze pilot represent an opposition
     to the Object that, while empty, nevertheless continues to
     be an opposition: Man is now a snob.  It is as if the
     armature of labor, negation and Historical activity
     continues to function, but in a void, since there can no
     longer be any negating or any History.

[20] In this model, "Opposition" continues, and so Man does
     too.  The difference between the two versions (that of '46
     and that of '59) lies in the fact that while the first
     proposes an activity that can be purely individual, so long
     as it is in accord with nature, the second, "Japanese,"
     entails a struggle for recognition, and therefore derives
     its power from the earlier, and decisive, Master-Slave
     dialectic.  After all, the purpose of snobbery, of dandyism,
     is to be recognized by the Other, even if that recognition
     is totally meaningless.  Thus a society is implied, and a
     culture; this was not the case, finally, for the "animals,"
     no matter what their "way of life" might have been.

[21] But the larger posthistorical culture--if such a thing can
     even be written of--will be unthinkable because Absolute
     Knowing will play no part in it.  Kojeve inadvertently 
     indicates the irrelevance of the Wise Man--of reflexive 
     consciousness at the end of History--by choosing
     the example of the Japanese: if they were carrying out
     posthistorical acts one hundred years before the birth of
     Hegel, Hegel and his book, and Kojeve in their wake,
     need never have existed.  History culminates in perfect
     *indifference* to Wisdom.  From the other side of the end of
     History, it now appears clear that the _Phenomenology_ is
     perfectly pointless.  Purely formal activities therefore
     will take place, and will have meanings, perhaps, within
     certain posthistorical cultures; those cultures, however,
     will exist in perfect isolation, without a larger Wisdom to
     unify them and give them meaning.  Here, then, is yet
     another Kojevian postmodernism, this time one based
     not on the particularity of desires but on the multiplicity
     and radical non-congruence of separate cultures.  Absolute
     knowing finds its completion in a series of social
     practices or lifestyles which are united only in the fact
     that as formal activities each one is precisely a lack of
     knowledge of the whole.  The snob's gesture is a forgetting,
     willful or not, of the larger significance--or
     insignificance--of his or her act.  Its success can be
     judged only by its immediate impact: the dandy walking his
     lobster on a leash can bask only in the recognition given
     *here* and *now*.  The act excludes any larger "meaning."

[22] How then, under these circumstances, can one say that
     History is ended?  It does not seem that, if the Japanese
     (as represented by Kojeve) are to be our models,
     there can be any history or historical consciousness at
     all.  Elsewhere--in passages and footnotes dating from the
     original (1947) publication of _Introduction la lecture de
     Hegel_--it seems that Kojeve himself recognized the
     necessity of historical memory and historical text--and
     thus of the writing of the _Phenomenology_ itself--for the
     ultimate completion of History.  A few pages after the
     footnote that I have discussed, Kojeve writes: "It
     is first necessary that *real* History be completed; next,
     it must be *narrated* to Man; and only then can the
     Philosopher, becoming a Wise Man, *understand* it by
     reconstructing it %a priori% in the _Phenomenology_" (IRH,
     166).  Kojeve adds in a footnote appended to this
     passage (more precisely, to the phrase that ends "narrated
     to Man"): "Moreover, there is no real history without
     historical memory--that is, without oral or written
     Memoirs."

[23] Here we are back at our earlier problem: if the Japanese
     constitute an ahistorical end of history, a posthistorical
     moment that has nothing to do with history, how can *they*
     be said to be Human?  If Man is determined in and through
     history, then it would seem that the Japanese, in their
     sophisticated and useless labor, are no more Human than are
     the bee-like posthistorical animals that Kojeve in
     1959 saw as implicit in his earlier footnote (of 1946), and
     rejected.  The Natural--the realm of the inhuman that, for
     Kojeve at least, simply had nothing to do with Human
     activity, Time, or History--seems to triumph once again.  In
     the case of the simple human-animals we might say that the
     Owl of Minerva flew, but that its flight seen from a
     posthistorical perspective was the equivalent of the
     movement of any other animal, the Owl of Minerva being no
     different from any owl--no matter how endangered--in the
     forest.  For the Kojevian Japanese, however, and for
     all the rest of us who will necessarily emulate them, the
     Owl of Minerva need never have flown in the first place.
     Perhaps it did, perhaps it didn't; in any case it is now
     stuffed and resides in a European museum, where it is
     routinely photographed by hurried groups of Japanese
     tourists.

[24] What, finally, is the status of the Book--the
     _Phenomenology_ itself as a summation of History and
     embodiment of Wisdom--at the end of History?  This is
     perhaps the most important question in Kojeve's
     Hegelianism, and, characteristically, he never poses it
     explicitly; instead, we must try to formulate an answer on
     the basis of two elliptic and ironic footnotes.  Yet, as we
     will see, the status of "Self-Consciousness" *at* and
     *after* the end of History will remain very much in
     question.

[25] The first question, which arises in Kojeve's
     discussion of the third part of Chapter VIII of the
     _Phenomenology_, is the role of the Wise Man, the
     post-philosopher (or %Sage%), in the establishment of the
     posthistorical regime.  At one point Kojeve writes:
     "One can say . . . that, in and by the Wise Man (who
     produces absolute Science, the Science that entirely
     reveals the totality of Being), Spirit 'attains or wins the
     Concept'" (ILH, 413).  He soon modifies this, though, in a
     footnote (ILH, 414).  If the Wise Man--Hegel, Kojeve,
     the "authors" of the _Phenomenology_--are those who
     "produce" Science, the true end of History and reign of
     Self-Consciousness will be possible only when mediated by
     the State.  The State, in effect, will guarantee the
     recognition of the freedom of all by all; the satisfaction
     it provides will do away with all opposition between
     Subject and Object, for-itself and in-itself.  This clearly
     implies more than the personal teaching of a single person:
     rather what is at stake now is the universalization of a
     definitive doctrine contained in a book.  Kojeve
     writes:
          To turn out to be true, philosophy must be universally 
          recognized, in other words recognized finally by the 
          universal and homogeneous *State*.  The
          empirical-existence (%Dasein%) of Science--is thus 
          not the private *thought* of the Wise Man, but his 
          words [%sa parole%], universally recognized. And it is 
          obvious that this "recognition" can only be obtained 
          through the publication of a book. And by existing in 
          the form of a book, Science is effectively detached 
          from its author, in other words from the Wise Man or 
          from Man [%du Sage ou de l'Homme%]. (ILH, 414)

[26] This is a passage fraught with difficulties, but one that
     is well worth considering.  It is recognition, first of all,
     that determines truth; the truth of the book is determined
     by its recognition by the State.  The book consists of the
     words--or literally, the word--of the author, but the book
     itself, on publication, is detached not only from the Wise
     Man, but from Man himself.  The detachment and recognition
     of the book is the determination of its truth--which in
     turn guarantees the universality and homogeneity of the
     State.  The book is detached from Man himself; presumably at
     this point Man has nothing more to do, and passes from the
     scene (as we will see in yet another footnote, discussed
     below).

[27] But note that the "private thought" of the Wise Man is not
     at stake here.  Rather his words are recognized, and this
     makes them "true"; the same gesture by the
     State--recognition--*makes it a State*.  Truth and Statehood
     are generated reciprocally, at the same instant, by the
     same act.

[28] Now if they are the result of the immediacy of what seems
     to be a purely formal act, Truth and Statehood cannot be
     generated out of reading.  Kojeve never explicitly
     poses the question, but it is in any case an obvious one:
     does anybody *read* this book?  Who?  Are recognition and
     reading the same thing?  It does not seem likely: reading
     here does not appear as a social or even
     physical/psychological phenomenon: it is not a question of
     the appropriation of the Wise Man's teaching, the reading
     of the book on the highest levels of government, its
     dissemination through the schools, etc.  For that is an
     interminable process: reading necessarily implies
     interpretation, misinterpretation, questioning, rephrasing,
     codification.  There is none of that here: in a single
     gesture, in one movement, the book and the State are
     "recognized."  Recognition, then, has nothing to do with
     reading--and by reading I mean, on the simplest level, a
     bare acquaintance with the contents of the book.  The word
     will be "recognized," it seems, without having to be
     deciphered.

[29] My interpretation is borne out in another footnote that
     comes some twenty-five pages before the one I have just
     discussed.  It explicitly links the death of Man to the book
     as inanimate, and presumably unread, object.  Once again
     this note attempts to face the ultimate problem: the fate
     of Man "after" the closing of History: 
          The fact that at the end of Time the Word-concept 
          (%Logos%) is *detached* from Man and 
          exists--empirically no longer in the form of a
          human-reality, but as a Book--this fact reveals the
          *essential finitude* of Man.  It's not only a given 
          man who dies: Man dies as such.  The end of History 
          is the *death* of Man properly speaking.  There 
          remains after this death: 1) living bodies with a 
          human form, but deprived of Spirit, in other words 
          of Time or creative power; 2) a Spirit which
          exists-empirically, but in the form of an inorganic
          reality, not living: as a Book which, not even having 
          an animal life, no longer has anything to do with 
          Time.  The relation between the Wise Man and his Book 
          is thus rigorously analogous to that of Man and his
          *death*.  My death is certainly mine; it is not the 
          death of an other.  But it is mine only in the future; 
          for one can say: "I am going to die," but not: "I am 
          dead."  It is the same for the Book.  It is my work 
          [%mon oeuvre%], and not that of an other; and in it it 
          is a question of me and not of anything else.  But I am 
          only in the Book, I am only this Book to the extent 
          that I write and publish it, in other words to the
          extent that it is still a future (or a project).  Once 
          the Book is published it is detached from me.  It ceases 
          to be me, just as my body ceases to be mine after my 
          death.  Death is just as impersonal and eternal, in 
          other words inhuman, as Spirit is impersonal, eternal 
          and inhuman when realized in and by the Book.  (ILH, 
          387-88, footnote; Kojeve's emphasis)

[30] We see now posthistorical Man as an "animal," no longer
     carrying out a task or striving toward self-Consciousness.
     But "he" is not *just* an animal--a bee or beaver--because
     he has the word, the Logos, which guarantees his movement
     from the Human to a kind of higher-order animality.  (This
     difference is something that Kojeve seems to have
     forgotten when he wrote the 1959 addendum to his long
     footnote on "animality," discussed above.)  But clearly the
     Book is not something to be read: there can be no *labor*
     of interpretation or inculcation.  For that reason the book
     is explicitly presented as dead, as "inorganic" (%i.e.%,
     lifeless) material.

[31] The death of Man is not, strictly speaking, the death of
     self-Consciousness.  The latter is externalized, frozen on
     the pages of a book.  The message is absolute: as
     Kojève states, "The Wise Man who reveals what is
     through the Word [%Parole%] or Concept reveals it
     definitively: for what is thus remains eternally identical
     to itself, no longer modified by uneasiness [%inquietude%]
     (%Unruhe%)" (ILH, 413).  The dead message, moreover, is a
     dead me (or a dead Man), because it is the highest Wisdom
     of me (the Wise Man, Hegel, Kojeve), preserved
     intact forever, apparently well beyond the labor of
     interpretation.  The connection between the Book and "my
     death" is, then, not merely a metaphor: it is both "me" in
     the sense that it consists of my remains, and at the same
     time it is *not* me, or my living project.  It is my dead
     body. And the dead bodies of trees.

[32] If we can understand the role played by the Book in
     Kojeve, we will be able to grasp both the status,
     and the radical limitation, of Absolute Knowledge as it is
     both the Book and the Book's *reading*.

[33] Time is circular, but it is not cyclical.  Hegelian time,
     according to Kojeve, can only be run through
     (%parcouru%) once (ILH, 391).  This is because the end is a
     return to the state before which the Human commences: the
     one in which an opposition between Man and his World does
     not exist.  That opposition, in and through which Man exists
     (and creates himself) in Time and Action, is History.  At
     the end, the opposition between Man and World is overcome,
     and ceases to exist: History ends and Man dies.  The
     difference between beginning and end is that at the end,
     and after it, "Identity is revealed by the Concept. . . .
     It is only at the end of History that the identity of Man
     and World exists *for* Man, as revealed by human Discourse"
     (ILH, 392).

[34] There is a certain irony in all this, upon which
     Kojève does not dwell.  The end is the "discursive
     revelation of its beginning"--yet the higher knowledge that
     is the end, the "comprehension of anthropogenic Desire, as
     it is revealed in the _Phenomenology_" (ILH, 392), is a
     human comprehension ("*for* Man") that nevertheless marks
     the end of Man.  In an impossible moment Man both
     understands and ceases to exist.  His understanding and
     death would seem to have to be simultaneous, as well as
     definitive.  After the end, there is no Man left to whom
     Discourse can reveal the unity of Man and World.

[35] Hence the strange status of the Book.  The Book, we are
     told, is the "empirical existence of Science" (ILH, 394).
     Its return is also its definitive termination, because then
     the "totality of Discourse is exhausted [%epuisee%]"
     (ILH, 393).  There can only be one book, then, that contains
     the defunct but definitive Science.  As we've already seen,
     Kojeve compares this book to a dead body, separated
     for ever from its consciousness/author.

[36] Discourse as well then returns to Nature; Man is dead,
     Action is over, and the "empirical existence of Science is
     not historical Man, but a Book made of paper, in other
     words a *natural* entity" (ILH, 394).

[37] But if all this is the case, why would anyone *read* the
     Book?  If Historical Action is at an end, and if Man is
     dead, there would be no point in doing so.  Yet not to do so
     would consign all of human History--and Absolute
     Knowledge--to a kind of Absolute Forgetting.  In that case
     there would be a return to the origin not on the higher
     level of comprehension, but on the lower level of simple
     repetition.

[38] That clearly is not an option either, so the Book must be
     read.  The crucial question then is: what is reading?
     Whatever it is, it will be the task of the posthistorical
     animal/dandy.  Reading is not Action or historically
     significant labor of any sort--all that is over, ended.  And
     since the cycle only returns to its origin once, it cannot
     be a reading that entails any individual interpretation or
     thought: it can only be a sheer repetition of the one,
     definitive, return of Science and Knowledge.  Kojeve
     writes: 
          Certainly, the Book must be read and understood by men, 
          in order to be a Book, in other words something other 
          than paper. But the man who reads it no longer creates 
          anything and he no longer changes himself: he is 
          therefore no longer Time with the primacy of the
          Future or History; in other words he is not Man in the
          strong sense of the word. This man is, himself, a
          quasi-natural or cyclical being: he is a reasonable
          *animal*, who changes and reproduces himself while
          remaining eternally *identical* to himself. And it 
          is this "reasonable animal" who is the "absoluter Geist,"
          *become* Spirit or completed-and-perfect 
          [%acheve-et-parfait%]; in other words, dead. (ILH, 394)

[39] The end of history, which had promised so much, with its
     State as a kind of institutionalized utopia, mediating
     through law the mutual recognition of the "anthropogenic"
     Desire of all men, becomes a kind of necrotopia of reading.
     The Book cannot not be read.*^7^  But what is commonly
     understood by "reading"--a personal understanding and a
     perhaps wayward interpretation that can, and does, discover
     new things in the text--is out of the question here.  The
     Book cannot therefore be read, either--or we must totally
     redefine reading.  Reading in the Kojevian sense will
     become an animalistic or dead repetition of Discourse, its
     exact repetition by the dead.  This is the strange end of
     the Kojevian mock theology that would replace heaven
     with the State,^8^ and of a mock existentialism that would
     resituate the recognition and reign of death definitively
     as satisfaction and stasis.*^9^

[40] Reading, then, becomes as "natural" as the Book--it is not
     an Action in Time; it is not, on other words, a human
     activity.  The Book is an "objective reality," the only
     possible realization of philosophy, which must be
     recognized by all persons--%i.e.%, by the State--in order
     to be true: mere intention is not enough (ILH, 414, note).
     It is when Kojeve considers the "objective" existence 
     of the Work that we see the problem in his conception 
     of reading, for he can only see publication as subjecting 
     the Work, the Book, to the "danger [that it will be] 
     changed and perverted" (ILH, 414, note).  Kojeve sees this 
     risk of "perversion"--of interpretation, in other words--as 
     a regrettable consequence of the necessity of the Work to 
     be "the objectively-real that maintains itself"--%i.e.%, 
     to be a Work that is published and circulated as a real, 
     solid object--rather than a "pure intention" that "fades 
     away [%s'evanouit%]"--%i.e.%, that is an idea beyond 
     appropriation by all of society, or by the State 
     (ILH, 414, note).  Kojeve, in other words, can only see 
     reading as a function of the passive reproduction of what 
     is "objectively-real"; all deviation from an imagined 
     definitive meaning (or Absolute Knowledge) can only be 
     "perversion."

[41] In light of this it is hard to see why Kojeve makes
     a strong distinction between the book as mere paper and the
     act of reading.  Reading as the pure repetition of a dead,
     frozen state will be as "material" as the thudding pileup
     in a warehouse of the unread copies of a book.  Hermeneutics
     becomes hermetics: the act of reading now is the automatic
     reproduction of a hermetically sealed text, and of a
     "Knowledge" so remote that there is no place in it, or
     around it, for human action: thinking, rethinking,
     questioning.  Cultural reproduction made possible by this
     reading will be the mere repetition %ad infinitum% of the
     assent of the dead, of animals.  So much for the paradise on
     earth that Kojeve saw as replacing the bad-faith
     paradise of all organized religion.

[42] We see here a complete reversal from the position at the
     outset of history, when man confronted nature and
     transformed it through his labor.  That view presented a
     radical duality between a dialectical Man and inert 
     nature.^10^  Now it is Nature--as the material Book, and as
     the dead reading of the Book--that has become dialectical, 
     or at least post-dialectical, whereas Man is simply dead.
     Nature has triumphed, but its triumph is of no concern to
     the "human animals"--the Americans or Japanese, bees or
     dandys, it hardly matters--who engage in their fragmentary
     and formal activities which are of no relevance whatever to
     the genesis, triumph, or demise of Man.

[43] It is here that we can draw some conclusions about the
     radical--and significant--difference between the
     posthistorical and the postmodern.  The posthistorical, as
     we've just seen, posits a radical break, an unbridgeable
     gap, between definitive Knowledge and the freeplay of
     posthistorical action.  The Book can contain nothing of
     interest to say about the residual uses to which leftover
     negativity, in the form of human action, will be put
     "after" the end of History.  In other words it has nothing
     at all to say about the present or the future.  Indeed the
     few pronouncements Kojeve makes on this subject are
     all in footnotes, as if they were tangential to the main
     body of the text.  The postmodern, on the other hand, puts
     forward a "knowledge" that arrives at its end by
     *recognizing* the necessity of the proliferation of what we
     might call "unbound" discourses and language games.  It
     recognizes its death as definitive knowledge in and of the
     proliferation of partial knowledges, activities, and
     languages.  Rather than being essentially closed to them, as
     indifferent as mere paper or rote reading, it is open to
     and dependent on them: it is the very knowledge of their
     incompletion that makes its completion--a provisional
     completion, to be sure, but a completion--possible.

[44] Posthistorical Knowledge always comes too soon--the Owl of
     Minerva always takes off well before dusk--because it
     closes off the possibility of, and is blind to, human
     activity, even though activity will obviously continue,
     albeit without benefit of Wise Man or Book.  Postmodern
     knowledge, on the other hand, comes too soon as well, but
     for the opposite reason: because its larger truth must be
     ignored by the very activities that justify it.  If
     posthistorical Knowledge knows too little, postmodern
     knowledge knows too much.  The postmodern is always already
     in advance of the partial activities it defines: if those
     activities were themselves to recognize fully the
     postmodern, they would simply fall under its aegis: they
     would be coherent parts of a larger narrative, and thus
     fully modern, and ultimately posthistorical.  And yet these
     activities, these games, are thoroughly dependent on a
     postmodern knowledge *which they must not know*: without
     the overarching knowledge of the postmodern, they would be
     indistinguishable from any other human narratives,
     "primitive" or "modern," which have nothing whatsoever to
     do with the postmodern.  And without their *definitive*
     blindness, at the end of modernity which is the postmodern,
     they would only be components of a higher Knowledge, fully
     recuperated by it.  They, in other words, in order to be
     postmodern, must in some sense be as blind to postmodern
     knowledge as posthistorical Knowledge would be to them.

[45] And yet the Kojevian posthistorical might be more
     postmodern than the postmodern.  It, after all, is ignorant,
     locked in its perfect, one-time circularity.  It does not,
     and must not, concern itself with, or know, that which
     comes after it, in an inevitable but supplementary
     relation.  It is the sheer performance, in other words, of
     the blindness of partial knowledges and practices that the
     postmodern can only *know*.  The posthistorical is therefore
     the *enactment* of the postmodern in and through its
     absolutely necessary lack of awareness of itself as
     postmodern; this lack is nothing more than the %a priori%
     failure and completion of postmodern knowledge.  The
     posthistorical will always again come *after* the
     postmodern, supplementing it with its radical not-knowing.
     The posthistorical Owl also always flies too late--well
     after dusk.


                                NOTES:

          ^1^ See section 9, entitled "Narratives of the Legitimation of
     Knowledge," of Jean-Francois Lyotard's _The Postmodern
     Condition: A Report on Knowledge_, trans. Geoff Bennington
     and Brian Massumi (Minneapolis: The University of Minnesota
     Press, 1984), pp. 31-37.

          ^2^ See, in this context, Francis Fukuyama's
     neo-Kojevian celebration of the _New World Order,
     The End of History and the Last Man_ (New York: The Free
     Press, 1992).  Jacques Derrida has recently criticized
     Fukuyama for the incoherence of his approach: either the
     end of history is a kind of eschatology, a pure logical
     necessity beyond empirical proof, or it is empirically
     verifiable, in which case it loses the attributes that give
     it its necessity, and also its attractiveness.  One cannot,
     however, demonstrate the logically necessary (or the
     "messianic") by invoking empirical observations.  See
     Derrida, _Spectres de Marx_ (Paris: Galilee, 1993),
     pp. 112-20.  Derrida, at the end of the same chapter
     ("%Conjurer--le marxisme%," pp. 120-27) also considers some
     of the Kojevian footnotes that I discuss in this
     article. I would argue that one could extend Derrida's
     critique of Fukuyama to Kojeve himself: for
     Kojeve too history is ended because it is a logical
     necessity that it end: therefore he is largely indifferent
     to what comes next.  Yet at the same time Kojeve
     points to empirical evidence--America, the Soviet Union,
     Japan, the defeat of the Nazis--to back up his thesis.

          ^3^ On the postmodern and adjudication between language games
     in conflict, see Lyotard's _The Differend: Phrases in
     Dispute_, trans. Georges Van Den Abbeele (Minneapolis: The
     University of Minnesota Press, 1988).

          ^4^ _The Introduction to the Reading of Hegel_ (New York:
     Basic Books, 1969) is an English translation (by James H.
     Nichols, Jr.) of certain sections of Kojeve's
     _Introduction la lecture de Hegel_ (Paris: Gallimard,
     Collection "Tel," 1980).  The editor of the English edition,
     Allan Bloom, has omitted much of the material of the
     1938-39 lectures.  When possible, then, I quote from the
     official English translation, giving page numbers from it,
     following the letters "IRH."  When a citation is not found
     in the English edition, I provide my own translation and
     cite the page number of the French edition, following the
     letters "ILH."  The reader will note that the pagination of
     the now widely available French edition from which I quote
     is different from that of the original French edition
     (Paris: Gallimard, 1947).

          ^5^ "One more word about teaching what the world ought to be:
     philosophy always arrives too late to do any such teaching
     . . . the Owl of Minerva takes flight only as the dusk
     begins to fall" (Hegel, _Preface to the Philosophy of
     Right_).

          ^6^ Kojeve could never admit that a dialectics of nature
     was conceivable.  Prior to human desire, there is simple
     identity.  Judith Butler writes: "Kojeve views nature
     as a set of brutally given facts, governed by the principle
     of simple identity, displaying no dialectical
     possibilities, and, hence, in stark contrast to the life of
     consciousness" (_Subjects of Desire: Hegelian Reflections
     in Twentieth Century France_ [New York: Columbia University
     Press, 1987], p. 67).  Maurice Blanchot rewrites this
     unreadability in his 1948 novel, _Le Tres-Haut_.  In this
     fiction the Book becomes the journal of a perfect civil
     servant of a posthistorical State, a civil servant who is
     at the same time a subversive challenging the State through
     the very act of writing.  The Book for Blanchot becomes an
     allegory of the collapse of political allegory, since all
     writing on the State is both fully recuperable by it, and
     is also its death, its extinction.  Meaning itself is in a
     twilight zone of perfect representation of the State--so
     perfect it's inhuman, or posthuman--but is also, by the
     very fact that it is a written representation, the death of
     that State, but a never dying death.  (The curse of death is
     that it cannot die.)  Such a text is perfectly circular, but
     also unreadable: nothing can ever happen in this State, and
     there is nothing more to be said, and certainly nothing
     more to read--but this nothing, this self-cancelling law,
     will be repeated endlessly, in exactly the same form.  See
     my preface to the translation I have done of this novel,
     entitled _The Most High_, forthcoming from the University
     of Nebraska Press.

          ^7^ This is a gambit that comes out quite clearly in
     Kojeve's article "Hegel, Marx, et le Christianisme"
     (_Critique_, 1, 3-4 (1946): 339-66.  See, for example, p.
     358: "Thus--a supremely curious thing [%chose curieuse
     entre toutes%]--man is completed and perfected, in other
     words he attains supreme satisfaction, by becoming
     conscious, in the person of the Wise Man, of his essential
     finitude."  Kojeve thus links the most profound
     desire of religion (as he sees it)--to guarantee man
     perfection and satisfaction--to that which religion most
     abhors: mortality.

          ^8^ As Mikkel Dufrenne notes (p. 397), Kojeve's stress
     on finitude and mortality establishes his Hegelianism as a
     revisionary Heideggerianism.  See "Actualit de Hegel"--a
     review of Kojeve's _Introduction_ and Jean
     Hyppolite's "Genese et structure de la Phenomenologie de
     l'esprit chez Hegel"--in _Esprit_, 16, 9 (1948): 396-408.

          ^9^ See note 5, above.  Dufrenne for his part sees this duality
     between a nondialectical nature (the "%en-soi%") and
     dialectical Man the "%pour-soi%") as a key inheritance from
     existentialism--one which poses plenty of problems for
     philosophers such as Sartre, in _Being and Nothingness_.
     How indeed does the "%pour-soi%" arise if the "%en-soi%" is
     closed?  How can the two be reconciled beyond a mere "as
     if"?  For Dufrenne, this is the origin of the thematics of
     failure (échec), anguish and despair in Sartre: "A
     linear series of failures cannot be taken for a dialectic"
     (Dufrenne, 401-03).

          ^10^ This statement should not be taken as a "criticism" of the
     postmodern, or an attempt to condemn it by "associating" it
     with the posthistorical.  As is made clear in Blanchot's
     novel (see footnote 7, above) there is no logical space
     outside of the postmodern--or the posthistorical, for that
     matter--from which such a "criticism" could be carried out.

------------------------------ Cut here ------------------------------