SELIM03.pdf


109

Julia Fernández Cuesta, Selim 3 (1993): 103-116

A PRAGMATIC APPROACH TO THE WIFE OF BATH’S TALE

1. INTRODUCTION

Pragmatics of Human Communicaton (1967), by psychologists Paul 

Watzlawick, Janet Beavin Bavelas and Don D. Jackson is basically an attempt

to analyze and explain pathological communication and its possible causes 

from the perspective of pragmatics. One of the most attractive aspects of the 

book is the fact that the writers turn frequently to literature in search of 

examples to illustrate their thesis. It was precisely from one such example that 

the idea for this article arose.

In the seventh chapter of the book, there is an interesting reference to the 

relationship between the witch and the knight in The Wife of Bath’s Tale,1 as

a case of what is referred to in the book as ‘double bind’. Double bind situa-

tions arise, according to Watzlawick (1967: 197), when:

1. Two or more people participate in an intense relationship that is highly 

important for the physical or psychological survival of one, several or all of 

them.

2. In this context, one of them gives a message which is structure d in such 

a way that: a) it states something, b) it states something about the statement

itself c) both statements are mutually exclusive.

Thus, the message is an instruction that must be disobeyed in order to be 

obeyed. The hearer is prevented from escaping the framework established by 

that message, either by metacommunicating on it or withdrawing. Therefore, 

1 From now on, I will refer to the tale as WBT.



110

although the message makes no sense from the logical point of view, it con-

stitutes a pragmatic reality: the hearer cannot help reacting to it, but at the 

same time s/he cannot react to it appropriately (not paradoxically), since the 

message is, in itself, paradoxical.

In this paper I intend:

a) To make an analysis of the prologue and the WBT  from the point of 

view of pragmatics.

b) To find out if both the prologue and the tale pursue/achieve the same 

effect in the audience/reader, although through different stylistic devices.

c) To verify whether the conclusions reached in the analysis, from the 

perspective of pragmatics, coincide with Watzlawick’s conclusions (1967) 

reached from a psychological approach.

2. THEORETICAL SUPPOSITIONS OF THE ANALYSIS

My analysis is based on Teun A. Van Dijk’s theory of pragmatics (1977) 

and the postulates set forth by Geoffrey Leech (1983). In questions relating to 

literary politeness, I have basically followed the work of Roger Sell (1985, 

1986).

Literary pragmatics considers the literary text as an interactive process 

between the writer and the reader, always linked to the social context in which 

it evolves. Sell (1985:2) writes: "(Literary Pragmatics) does not fundamentally

distinguish the communication between literary writers and their readers from 

any other type of communication". If we accept these assump tions, the next 

step would be to ask ourselves what exactly is to be understood by context in 

a literary text, and how it differs from the context of a real conversation.

Sperber and Wilson (1986) understand context (in a conversation) to be 

the knowledge that the hearer has of the speaker, of the situation, of other 

more remote situations related to this one, and of the world in general. This 

context is what allows him, by deduction, to reach a series of conclusions as 



111

to the communicative intention of the speaker, beyond the literal content. In 

the case of a literary text, it is more difficult to define exactly what constitutes

the context, because there is not just one but rather several contexts, since 

the text, although originally intended for the public of a particular period, has 

also, as its audience, anyone who may read it in later times. Thus, we must 

perhaps speak of various contexts in the reception of a literary text and, 

logically, of different interpretations of it; from there, it also follows that the 

greater our knowledge is of the period in which a particular work was written, 

and of the circumstances surrounding its creation, the more reward ing our 

reading of the text will be, and the greater our enjoyment. Our context as 

readers, however, will always be different from that of the audience of the 

period in which the text was written. This is why, for us, it will also have other 

connotations, other nuances.

Apart from this ‘external’ context, in which the relationship between writer 

and reader would be situated, there exists another ‘internal’ context which 

includes everything that happens within the text. Génette (1980) pro posed the 

terms extradiegetic level (external) and intradiegetic level (internal) for these 

two types of context.1

In the Canterbury Tales, since we are dealing with a story within a story, 

we should perhaps speak of two different contexts at the intradiegetic level. 

According to this, we would place the relationship between the characters of 

the works in a first intradiegetic level, whereas the action within the work 

would be situated in a second intradiegetic level. The contents of both levels 

are obviously related: what happens at the second intradiegetic level, within 

the tale, is of great consequence for what happens at the first extradiegetic 

level. Sell (1986:487-512) used these concepts in his analysis of The Miller’s 

Tale and showed that the two intradiegetic levels are clearly related in 

Chaucer’s Tales. At the first intradiegetic level, the pilgrims interact with one 

another, asking questions, interrupting each other, and discussing the

1 For a more detailed explanation of these two concepts see Génette (1980).



112

content of their tales (second intradiegetic level) among themselves. It is 

precisely the contents of both intradiegetic levels that which determines the 

relationship established at the extradiegetic level, between speaker/writer and

the hearer/ reader. In Sell’s own words (1985: 499):

The events at the second intradegetic level, within his story, are in fact of 

consequence for relationships at the first intradiegetic level, between the pil-

grims. Furthermore, and in somewhat the same fashion, what happens at both 

intradiegetic levels is of consequence for the extradiegetic relationships be-

tween the writer and the reader.

All the levels are, thus, related. In WBT, what happens at the second in -

tradiegetic level (the Wife’s narration) is clearly linked to the contents of her 

sermon in the prologue (first intradiegetic level). In fact, the Wife’s tale is 

clearly a parable (exemplum) of what has been said in the prologue. On the 

other hand, the relation between them both (prologue and tale) is what makes 

us aware of what the "moral" of the tale is, and what it has to say about 

women and the relationship between the sexes.

Having made these observations on the context, I will now proceed to the 

analysis of the tale and its prologue.

3. STUDY OF THE PROLOGUE (FIRST INTRADIEGETIC LEVEL)

As has been said, WBT belongs to the Canterbury Tales and has a well 

defined place within the general plan of Chaucer’s work. The subject of both 

the prologue and the tale is the same: the situation of dominance held by the 

wife over the husband, and the need for this situation to be maintained in or-

der to preserve peace and family harmony.

The prologue contains all the ingredients of a typical sermon of the time: 

quotations from the Holy Scriptures, from the Church Fathers, from the clas -

sics, and references to mythology and astrology. However, all these elements 

are used in such a way that they achieve effects which are opposite to those 



113

sought by a sermon of the period, the purpose of which would be the edifica-

tion of the Christian.

In her sermon, the wife of Bath makes a passionate defense of sex and 

lechery, inviting her listeners to take pleasure in them, and supporting her 

cause with passages from the Holy Scripture, the meaning of which she in -

terpre ts (or misinterprets), by means of a series of "sui generis" inferences 

that the reader, however little he may know of the Bible and exegetics, rec-

ognizes at once as having been clearly distorted. An apparent defense of 

marriage is made (in fact, a justification for sex and lust), with reference to the 

Bible (advice given by Christ for chastity and virginity), quotations from the 

Apostle and other picturesque arguments, such as one citing the function of 

the sexual organs (115-134). It is a grand mixture of theological and bio logical

arguments that help bring out the ironical aspects of the argumentation, and 

the fact that at no time must it be taken seriously, but simply for what it is: an 

attempt at using the rhetoric of the sermon for purposes which are very 

different from those belonging to the period’s moral principles on marriage.

The conclusions to be reached from what is said by the goodwife in her 

sermon, make the reader (or those listening to the goodwife) take all of this 

with good humor: the Wife of Bath is using all her erudition to support her 

theories, distorting the meaning of the Holy Scripture, at least in its traditional

interpretation, the only one valid at that time. The words used by the 

pardoner when he interrupts her: "Now, dame, by God and by seint John! Ye 

been a noble prechour in this cas" (164-65) are a reflection of this irony and of 

the fact that the audience, to whom the Wife’s words are really addressed, is 

fully aware of it.

It might be asked why the rest of the pilgrims do not take the widow’s 

words seriously. From the point of view of pragmatics, the goodwife violates 

the Quantity and Quality maxims of the Cooperative Principle, besides that of 

Manner, in her confused exposition, lack of order and ambiguity. As an 

example, her version of Christ’s meeting with the Samaritan might be cited. 

Instead of the traditional interpretation -Jesus tells the Samaritan that her 



114

sixth husband is not really her husband, since (we infer) he is her lover- the 

goodwife states that she does not understand Christ’s words, and wrongly 

as sumes that he is not her husband because he is the sixth: "Why is the sixth 

not her husband? Is it that one can only have five?". For her it is apparently 

just a question of the number of marriages permitted in a lifetime, not the dif-

ference between marriage and cohabitation1.

Starting from verse 195, the Wife of Bath tells us the story of her mar-

riages; she boasts, in the first place, of how badly she has always treated her 

husbands, something which is altogether paradoxical in the mouth of a 

woman, unless that woman is perverse. This has surprised many readers of 

the tale, as well as scholars. Pedro Guardia (1987: 195) states that Alisoun is a 

woman who, trying to be feminist, becomes, in fact, antifeminist. One might 

ask whether the widow’s speech is really absurd. In my opinion, it is not so at 

all; we must bear in mind the pragmatic principle of Irony and, in the light of 

this principle, interpret the apparent paradox of a woman who speaks badly of 

women and boasts of faults and bad habits which are generally attributed to 

the female sex.

Leech (1983: 82) defines the Principle of Irony in the following way:

1 'Thou hast yhad fyve husbondes', quod he,
  And that ilke man that now hath thee 
  is noght thin husbonde', thus seyde he certeyn.
  What he mente thereby, I kan nat seyn;
  But I axe, why that the fifthe man
  was noon housbonde to the Samaritan?
  How manye myghte she have in marriage?
  Yet herde I nevere tellen in myn age
  Upon this nombre diffinicioun.
  Men may devyne and glosen, up and doun,
  But wel I wot, expres, withoute lye,
  God bad us for to wexe and multiplye;
  That gentil text kan I wel understonde. (17-39)



115

If you must cause offence, at least do so in a way which does not overtly 

conflict with the Politeness Principle, but allows the hearer to arrive at the of-

fensive point of your remark indirectly, by way of implicature.

This is the principle at work in the prologue, strongly linked to the notion 

of politeness. The satire aimed at the female sex, a recurre nt topic in me dieval

literature, becomes more effective if that criticism is expressed by a woman, 

and is much more subtle on the part of the writer than if it were expressed

either by a male character, (cf. The Clerk’s Tale and The Merchant’s Tale, or

directly by remarks made by the narrator.

For those listening to the goodwife tell her tale as well as for us, who are 

familiar with the mentality of the period, the argument might be as follows:

1. The goodwife boasts of how badly she has treated her husbands (at 

times, true enough, in return for their meanness or jealousy). Nevertheless, 

there is no doubt that her behaviour is promiscuous.

2. This behavior is morally objectionable. So says the Apostle St. Paul: 

wives must be bound to their husbands, and, should the husband die, it is 

advisable for them not to remarry but rather to remain single1. Likewise, the 

Parson, at the end of his tale, in what has been considered as a moralizing 

conclusion of the entire work, reproaches this type of behaviour2.

CONCLUSION

1 The wife is bound by the law as long as her husband liveth; but if her husband be dead, 
she is at liberty to be married to whom she will; only in the Lord. But she is happier, if 
she so abide after my judge ment: and I think also that I have the spirit of God. (Cor. 7, 
39-40)

2 Now that a wommam sholde be subject to hire hosbonde, that telleth Seint Peter. First, 
in obedience. And eek, as seith the decree, a womman that is wyf, she hath noon 
auctoritee to swere ne to bere witnesse withoute leve of hir husbonde, that is hire lord.



116

The Wife of Bath is, then, an immoral character. Thus, through irony and 

through implicatures, the satirization of a particular type of woman is 

achieved, and this woman is represented by the goodwife. Like Satan, in the 

Anglosaxon poem Genesis B, Alisoun becomes likeable as she tells us her 

complaints and claims her "rights"; yet the public/reader of the period knows 

well enough that she is going against one of the fundamental principles of 

traditional morality: a wife must be subject to her husband, as previously 

cited sources testify and as the woman herself recognizes when she exclaims: 

"Allas! Allas! that ever love was sinne!" (614).

This set of implicatures is also very clear when the goodwife tells stories 

of wicked women, which were told to her by her last husband. It would be 

absurd for her to tell such stories directly since, as a woman herself, she ab-

hors them. Yet, by putting them in the mouth of her husband, their appear-

ance in the tale is justified and the ironical effect increases.

It is precisely one of these stories that brings about the happy outcome of 

her last marriage, the only successful one. Fed up with the stories that her 

husband tells her of wicked women, Alisoun destroys one of his books by 

throwing it into the fire. In a fury, her spouse beats her so hard that the 

goodwife pretends to die from the fight. Frightened to death at the idea of the 

crime that he has supposedly committed, the poor man swears to submit to 

his wife’s will if she "decides" to live. The wife finally agrees, and thus ends 

the narration of her marriages and the prologue of the tale 1.

From the point of view of pragmatics, in deceiving her husband, Alisoun 

flouts the maxim of Quality of the Cooperative Principle. By doing so, she has 

1 And neer he cam, and kneled faire adoun,/ and seyde, “Deere suster Alisoun,/ As help 
me God! I shal thee never smyte./ That I have doon, it is thyself biseke!”/ And yet eft -
soones I hitte hym on the cheke,/ And sayde, “Theef, thus muchel am i wreke;/ Now 
wol I dye, I may no longer speke.”/ But atte laste, with muchel care and wo,/ We fille 
acorded by us selve two./ He yaf me al the bridel in myn hond,/ To han the governence
of hous and lond,/ And of his tongue, and of his hond also;/ And made hym brenne his 
book anon right tho. (803-806)



117

achieved her ends: the power over her own personal environment which 

society denies her.

4. STUDY OF THE TALE (SECOND INTRADIEGETIC LEVEL)

The tale of the wife of Bath is the account of something that happened 

long, long ago: "In TH’OLDE dayes of Kyng Arthour/ of which that Britons

speken greet honour" (857-58).

I have considered, within the tale, the following units of meaning that or-

ganize the macro -structure1 of the story:

1. A knight rapes a maiden. The initial balance is broken by this act of 

violence.

2. The young man is denounced, tried and condemned to death by the 

king.

3. The queen intercedes on his behalf, and the king places the life of the 

knight in the hands of his wife.

4. The queen asks the young man to solve a riddle: "What is it that 

women most desire?", in exchange for his life.

5. The young man tries unsucessfully to find the solution to the riddle, 

questioning everyone he meets.

6. Finally, a witch offers to give him the answer in return for the young 

man’s promise to grant her whatever she may ask him, if it is in his hands to 

do so. The young man agrees and the pact is sealed2.

7. The queen is pleased by the young man’s answer, which saves his life, 

but the witch, reminding him of his promise, demands that he marry her. The 

young man has no choice but to accept.

1 The concept of macro-structure has been taken from Van Dijk (1988).
2 The nexte thyng that I require thee,/Thou shalt it do, if it lye in thy myght,/ And I wol 

telle it yow er it be nyght. (1010-12)



118

8. On the wedding night, the knight lies beside his wife in desperation. 

She suggests another alternative: he can choose either to have a young, but 

unfaithful wife or a wife who is faithful, but old and ugly. Desolate in the face 

of the two alternatives, the knight refuses to make a choice and grants his 

wife this power: "I do not fors the wheither of the two; / For as you liketh, it 

suffiseth me" (1234-35).

9. The witch then turns herself into a young woman, both beautiful and 

faithful.

The dramatic interest of the tale lies in the fact that the audience/reader 

knows from the start that the knight is being the victim of a game (perhaps as 

a revenge for the act committed by him against the opposite sex in the rape of 

the maiden).

There are two key moments in the account, which are extremely useful for 

explaining the relation that exists between the prologue and the tale. I will 

now refer to these.

In her first meeting with the knight, the witch rises and greets him with 

these words: "Sire Knight, heer forth ne lith no wey" (1001). These words go 

unnoticed by the knight (second intradiegetic level), who hears only the 

words spoken afterwards, promising help: "Tell me what that ye seken, by 

youre fey! / Paraventure it may the bettre be; Thise olde folk kan muchel 

thyng" (1000-1005). Nevertheless, both for the audience listening to the nar-

rator (first intradiegetic level) and for the readers (extradiegetic level) the 

crone’s first words: "there is no way out through here", do not go unnoticed; 

they fores hadow the young man’s upcoming misfortune, that he will proba-

bly be the victim of one of the witch’s evil arts1. Likewise, when the witch 

imposes her condition, something of a blank check, the young man does not 

hesitate to accept because, at that moment, the only thing he is interested in 

is saving his life. However, the audience/reader, contemplating the story from 

1 Something similar happens in the first meeting between the young man and the old 
man in The Chaser (cf. Garcés: 1990).



119

outside and with a certain perspective, guess that the witch is going to de-

mand something dreadful of the young man in return, which is exactly what 

happens at the end of the story. Once again, the writer plays with the two 

narrative levels (two contexts) which I have already referred to. The audi-

ence/reader knows more than the young man, and is in a position to infer 

more. There lies the dramatic tension of the narration, what makes it interest-

ing, "tellable"1. The writer knows that the reader, with a broader experience in 

life than the young man’s, somehow guesses that the witch is not going to 

play fair, that she will not give something fo r nothing, and that she will make 

the knight pay dearly for her help.

From the perspective of the Principles of Pragmatics, the crone flouts the 

Quantity maxim of the Cooperation Principle, since she takes advantage of 

the young man’s urgent need to solve the enigma and save his life,

something which will make him agree to anything that the witch may ask from 

him.

At the end of the tale, we find the witch and the knight in bed on their 

wedding night. When the young man expresses his disgust at the idea of ly-

ing with his wife, she proposes a new alternative: if he accepts her as she is, 

old and ugly, she will be an honest and faithful wife. If, on the contrary, he 

wishes her to be young and beautiful, she will be so, but also unfaithful. 

Once again, Chaucer is playing with the two narrative levels (intradiegetic 

and extradiegetic). The audience/reader is aware that there is a third possibil-

ity of synthesis: a young and faithful wife. The witch denies the knight that 

possibility: a wife can only be faithful if she is old.

The tale comes to a happy ending when, unexpectedly, the young man re -

fuses to go on playing, and gives up his possiblity to choose, that is, he 

gives up his will, and places it in the hands of his shrewd wife, thus implicitly 

admitting the superiority of female cleverness. Just as the widow in the pro -

logue gains power over her last husband by means of an ingenious trick (by 

1 Cf. Sell (1985) for the concept of “tellability” in the lit erary text.



120

making him believe that she is dying, 805-20), the witch wins the game 

through deception and cunning.

From the pragmatic perspective, the witch flouts the maxim of Quality of 

the Cooperative Principle, and the maxim of Tact of the Principle of Polite-

ness, since the choice offered is false and there is no possible gain for the lis -

tener; no matter what the young man decides, he will always lose. Moreover, 

the witch is clearly in a position of superiority with respect to the man, so that 

he has no choice but not to choose, to relinquish his right to choose (the 

only truly human right) and to place his fate in the hands of h is wife.



121

5. INTERRELATION BETWEEN THE TWO INTRADIEGETIC LEVELS

(PROLOGUE AND TALE)

There is a clear link between the end of the prologue and the beginning of 

the tale, which is the dispute between the Friar and the Pardoner, caused by 

the fact that the latter censures the goodwife for "such a long preamble": 

"Now, dame’ quod he, ‘so have I joye or blis, / This is a long preamble of a 

tale!" (830-31). The host makes peace: "Pees! and that anon!" (850), and 

urges the goodwife to start the tale. She begins by humbly begging the friar’s 

leave: "Al redy, sire,’ quod she, ‘right as yow lest,/ if I have licence of this 

worthy Frere" (854-55), although we can immediately see the irony of this 

opening, since the very first words of her story are precisely directed against 

him.

Throughout the tale, Alisoun reminds us, on numerous occasions, with 

her remarks and asides, that she is the one who is telling the story, which in 

turn keeps up the prologue/tale relation and assures that the reader does not 

forget who the narrator is (919-934 ss).

At the semantic level, there are a series of indisputable parallelisms in the 

prologue and the tale. In both, we are introduced to a man who commits a 

violent act: he beats his wife (prologue)/ rapes a maiden (tale). The woman 

(wife, queen, witch), through cunning, by taking advantage of the man’s fear, 

makes him pay dearly for his crime, and finally, achieves control over her 

family environment, if not in theory, then in fact.

There are rather negative ideas about women expressed by women both in 

the prologue and the tale. The satirical purpose of the writer is quite clear. 

Women are not attacked directly, but rather by means of implicatures; 

Chaucer thus saves face: it is not the writer who criticizes women, but women 

themselves, in an obvious paradox.



122

6. CONCLUSIONS

It is clear then, after this analysis, that the prologue and the tale pur-

sue/achieve the same objectives:

a) To present a view of marriage that in practice only works if the wife has 

power over her husband, against all that is established by traditional moral 

principles.

b) By means of irony (implicatures), the writer satirizes a particular type of 

women, represented by the widow of Bath. This type of woman is pre sented

(both in the prologue and in the tale) as ambitious, avid for power, cunning 

and clever. To many present day readers, some of these characteris tics may 

seem positive attributes. This is just what I was referring to at the beginning 

of the paper, when I stated that our context as readers of the tale  in a 

particular period varies, as the interpretation of the same also logically varies.

From the Pragmatics approach, the speaker flouts the Quality and Quan-

tity maxims of the Cooperative Principle: the speaker lies to the lis tener, and 

the Tact maxim of the Politeness Principle: the listener image is not saved.

c) In the tale (second intradiegetic level), the knight finds himself in a 

spiral of false alternatives until he no longer has any alternative other than 

submit to female power. From the pragmatic perspective, the situation re ferred

to by Watzlawick as ‘double bind’ is one in which the Quality maxim of the 

Cooperative Principle and the maxim of Tact of the Politeness Principle are 

flouted, in a situation in which there is a false choice, and the intention of the 

speaker is to manipulate rather than cooperate.

Julia Fernández Cuesta

University of Seville



123

BIBLIOGRAPHY

BHAYA NAIR, R. (1985). "Telling Lies: Some Literary and other Violations of 
theGrice’s Maxim of Quality". Nottingham Linguistic Circular 14,
53-71.

GARCÉS CONEJOS, P. (1993). "Ejercicio Práctico de Pragmática Literaria: Una 
Propuesta Metodológica Multidisciplinar." (en prensa).

GARCÉS CONEJOS, P. (1990). “Cuarta visita a The Chaser: Respuesta 
Pragmática a Shoper, Deyes y Barry". Miscel.lánia Homenatge En-
rique García Díez. Valéncia: Universitat de Valéncia, Conselleria de 
Cultura, Educació i Ciéncia de la Generalitat Valenciana.

CHAUCER, G. (1958). Canterbury Tales. ed. by A. C. Cawley. London: 
Guernsey Place.

CHAUCER, G. (1987). Cuentos de Canterbury. Madrid: Cátedra.

LEECH, G. (1983). The Principles of Pragmatics. Harlow: Longman.

SELL, R. (1985). "Tellability and Politeness in ‘The Miller’s Tale: First Steps in 
Literary Pragmatics". English Studies, 496-52.

SELL, R. (1985). "Politeness in Chaucer: Suggestions towards a Methodology
for Pragmatic Stylistics". Studia Neophilologica 57: 175-185.

SELL, R. (1989). "The Politeness of Literary Texts: A Literary -Pragmatic
Dimension". IAUPE Conference in Lausanne, 1-22.

SPERBER & WILSON. (1986). Relevance. Oxford: Blackwell.

VAN DIJK, Teun A. (1988). Texto y Contexto. Madrid: Cátedra.

WATZLAWICK, Paul et ali. (1967). Pragmatics of Human Communication. 
New York: W. W. Norton and Co.

* * *