Jürgen Habermas and Bush’s Neoconservatives:


Studies in Social Justice 
Volume 5, Issue 2, 167-182, 2011 
	
  

 
Correspondence Address: Vivienne Matthies-Boon, Department of International Relations and 
International Organisation, University of Groningen, Oude Kijk in 't Jatstraat 26, 9712 EK Groningen, 
The Netherlands. Tel.: +31 (0) 50 363 7254; Email: e.a.v.matthies-boon@rug.nl 
 
ISSN: 1911-4788 
 

 
 

 
 
 

 
Jürgen Habermas and Bush’s Neoconservatives: 
Too Close for Comfort? 
 
VIVIENNE MATTHIES-BOON    
Department of International Relations and International Organisation,  
University of Groningen, The Netherlands 
 
 
ABSTRACT  In his recent political writings, Habermas has opposed his cosmopolitan project 
to that of the Bushite neoconservatives. However, this article argues that in some  
respects Habermas's works come closer to the neoconservative agenda than he realises and 
that this poses a potential danger of its being appropriated by precisely the camp he 
opposes. These problems particularly come to the fore in his analysis of Islamic 
fundamentalism, democracy and the Middle East, but also in his recommendations 
concerning UN-based internationalism and his appeals to Woodrow Wilson. By tracking 
these problematic areas in Habermas's work, this article argues that Habermas needs to 
engage in a more carefully articulated, concrete and empirical analysis if he is to avoid 
these problems. 
 
 
Introduction1 
  
In his recent political writings, Habermas has fervently opposed the neoliberal and 
neoconservative policies of the Bush administration. In opposition to this unilateral 
hegemon, which hides its power interests behind the ethical façade of spreading 
democracy and human rights abroad, Habermas argues, that we should instead 
embrace a cosmopolitan political order. Such a cosmopolitan order would be 
characterized by a multi-levelled system of governance and a further 
institutionalization of international law, as well as by the promotion of procedural 
opinion- and will-formation (Habermas, 2001, 2003, 2006a, 2006b). In advancing 
such a model, Habermas hopes to follow in the footsteps of Immanuel Kant, with a 
view to implementing a truly cosmopolitan world order devoid of illegal war 
(Habermas, 1997).   

On first sight, this project seems admirable. After all, the invasion of Iraq by the 
“Coalition of the Willing,” the institutionalization of torture and human rights 
abuses, the bending of international and national law, as well as the ideological 
rhetoric of the Western “us” versus the terrorist “them” is surely only to be 
deplored. Yet, as I shall argue, the relation between Habermas's work and the 
neoconservative outlook is more complex than his political utterances suggest. The 



168   Vivienne Matthies-Boon 
 
	
  

Studies in Social Justice, Volume 3, Issue 1, 21-36, 2009 
 
Studies in Social Justice, Volume 5, Issue 2, 2011 

	
  

problem is that on closer inspection there appears to be a hitherto unremarked 
affinity between Habermas's proposals and those of the neoconservatives. This 
raises the question of whether Habermas's work might not run the risk of being 
appropriated by the those he opposes—namely, by Bushite neoconservatives such 
as Paul Wolfowitz, Dick Cheney, William Kristol, David Frum and Daniel Pipes 
(among others)—in order to support their own ideological agenda rather than 
Habermas's cosmopolitan project2.  Indeed, John Yoo and Robert Delahunty (2010) 
have already done just this. For the irony is that, despite the fact that Habermas 
clearly opposes his approach to that of the neoconservatives, he in the end affirms 
at least some of the core ideological values and perceptions of the Bush 
administration. Three central instances are these. First, like the neoconservatives, 
Habermas (2003) espouses a belief in the universal value of democracy; like them 
(and of course like many others) he believes that a spread of democracy to the 
Middle East will lead to a peaceful and prosperous future, as well as the demise of 
Islamic fundamentalism. Second, just like the neoconservatives and their allies, 
whether explicit or implicit, Habermas fails to look into the important influence of 
colonialism and postcolonialism in the region and believes that the mere imposition 
of proper formal democratic processes would lead to a resolution of political 
violence. Like the neoconservatives, he fails to analyse the historical, political, 
social, cultural and economic role of the West and other occupying forces have 
placed in the Middle East. Rather, he sees the region and the problems of 
fundamentalism that emanate from it through the lens of his largely Western-based 
theory of modernity, with all the problems that brings. Third, in his opposition to 
the neoconservatives, Habermas (2008) frequently appeals to the internationalist 
stance of Woodrow Wilson and posits this as an alternative approach to the Bush 
administration (p. 94, pp. 155-158). Yet, what is interesting here is that the Bush 
administration itself frequently referred to the Wilsonian legacy in order to 
legitimate its own imperialist projects (p. 94, pp. 155-158). Moreover, in his 
appeals to Wilsonianism, Habermas overlooks the extent to which Wilson himself 
was engaged in the imperialist spread of democracy to Latin America and other 
parts of the world (Encarnación, 2005). While this does not necessarily imply that 
Habermas's own project has imperialist tendencies, it does indicate that Habermas 
has failed sufficiently to reflect on the affinity between some aspects of his own 
work and the core imperialist ideological beliefs of neoconservatism. My worry is 
hence that Habermas might all too easily be coming close to what he criticizes—
and thus might run the danger of being systematically appropriated by 
neoconservative ideologues. 

Of course, Habermas differs from the neoconservatives in his analysis of the free 
market and its putative benefits, arguing that, against the neoconservatives, the 
market needs to be brought under control by democratic institutions on a global 
level. The difficulty here, however, is that, practically at least, Habermas's accounts 
rely on a rather naïve analysis of the concrete workings of international institutions 
such as the UN. He argues that these kinds of institution will be able to open up the 
way for a truly cosmopolitan future, but fails to see the extent to which these 
institutions have themselves become informed, even dominated, by neoliberal 
values. This oversight is, I believe, due not only to the abstract nature of 



Habermas and Bush’s Neoconservatives   169 

 
Studies in Social Justice, Volume 5, Issue 2, 2011 

	
  

Habermas's account but also his own implicit endorsement—and however much 
that goes against his explicit position—of the apparent benefits of the free market. 

The intention of this article is thus neither to repudiate cosmopolitan political 
philosophy nor to strengthen the visions of the neoconservative camp.  Rather, my 
aim is much more modest than that: I seek merely to put out a warning sign, to 
point out that Habermas—and Habermasians—need to reflect more carefully and 
closely on the possible affinity between his work and the positions and 
commitments of the neoconservatives. Not least because, as I have said, 
neoconservatives have already incorporated insights from the progressive left in 
order to advance their own program, such a task is as politically urgent as it is 
intellectually salutary. In order to relay this warning sign, I shall first outline 
Habermas’s proposals for a cosmopolitan world order, in the course of which he 
opposes his own work to that of the neoconservatives. I shall then proceed to his 
political commentary on Islamic fundamentalism where some affinities between his 
approach and that of the neoconservatives come to light particularly sharply. 
Following this, I shall analyze the extent to which his proposed cosmopolitan 
resolution to the problems of the Middle East offers a viable alternative to the 
imperialist project of the neoconservatives, questioning especially the extent to 
which international institutions such as the UN offer a practical alternative to the 
neoliberal ideology of the neoconservatives. Finally, I shall go on to point out the 
oddity of Habermas's appeals to the internationalist Wilsonian legacy, a legacy 
explicitly exploited by the Bush administration in the development of its “Freedom 
Agenda.”  
 
 
Habermas's Multilateral Cosmopolitan Governance vs. Neoconservative 
Unilateral Imperialism 
 
In his recent political writings3 Habermas (2009) argues against the neoliberal and 
neoconservative actions and outlook of the Bush administration, and while he 
endorses the Obama administration (p. 185) the latter hardly signals anything very 
different (Khan, 2011, p. 21). The trigger for Habermas was the invasion of Iraq, 
where the Coalition of the Willing commenced the “Shock and Awe” strategy 
without a resolution from the Security Council. What angered him was not only the 
illegitimacy of the war itself, but also that the United States plainly ignored, 
sidelined and even sought to modify international law as it pressed its own interests 
upon the international community (Habermas, 2006a, p. 182). This, he insists, is a 
dangerous precedent: one that could potentially lead to a crumbling of the 
cosmopolitan order. For Habermas (2006a) believes that, with the formation of the 
UN, the establishment of International Courts, and the enforcement of human 
rights, the international community has slowly but surely moved beyond classical 
international law—which merely governed inter-state relations—towards a 
cosmopolitan legal order. Hence, by bypassing the UN, the Bush administration 
went directly against the evolving cosmopolitan world order that Habermas 
advocates.  

Since 2003, Habermas has thus been more active in his condemnation of the 
neoconservative outlook and also stepped up his own campaign for a normative 
cosmopolitan alternative. In this campaign, he posits an alternative cosmopolitan 



170   Vivienne Matthies-Boon 
 
	
  

Studies in Social Justice, Volume 3, Issue 1, 21-36, 2009 
 
Studies in Social Justice, Volume 5, Issue 2, 2011 

	
  

project that would be free of any despotic or imperialist traits, owing to the fact that 
it would bring democracy into being across the globe, ensuring that “no one could 
unilaterally determine the boundaries of what is tolerated” (Habermas, 2003, p. 40). 
There is, hence, no one agent who can impose their will on others. Rather, the 
world is offered a rational model where opinions and will-formations are 
discursively created and multilateral, rather than unilateral, actions are undertaken. 
Central to this cosmopolitan framework are international organizations such as the 
United Nations. By this model, it would function as a global police force, 
regulating and inspecting the behaviour of nation states so as to ensure that they 
adhere to human rights and to international law (Habermas, 2004). In order to 
ensure that such a global order led by the UN would not begin to take on the 
characteristics of a despotic world state, Habermas proposes a multileveled model 
of governance. In such a model of governance, supranational institutions spanning 
the entire globe would be supported, informed and influenced by the discursive 
features of a broad range of actors: from social movements to nation states to 
regional blocks. Within this order, transnational regional institutions such as the EU 
would play an important role as they would be able to bring the interests of an 
entire region to the attention of the UN and solve many of their problems 
transnationally. 

Here, Habermas clearly builds further on his earlier proposals for a stronger 
integrated European Union based on the idea of a constitutional patriotism,4 which 
he posited as another necessary tool to counter American neoconservativism 
(Habermas, 2001). A stronger, integrated Europe was necessary, he argued, both to 
counter American imperialism on a world stage, as well as to deal with problems 
caused by global economic forces that could no longer be contained at the level of 
individual nation states.5 Europe would be the prime actor fighting the corner of 
cosmopolitanism against the unilateralist neoconservative policies of the Bush 
administration and its followers as it pushes for international multilateralism and 
the further institutionalization of democracy.  

Moreover, referring to historical instances such as the Second World War and 
postcolonialism, Habermas insists that Europeans are particularly well suited to 
play this civilizing role. For, in contrast to the United States of America, Europe 
has a stricter division between church and state, a greater sensitivity towards human 
rights as a result of decolonization and, most of all, Europe has been on a 
cosmopolitan learning curve as a result of the painful experiences of the Second 
World War (Habermas, 2005, p. 11; see also Boon, 2007, p. 297; 2009, pp. 31-34). 
In these works, he argued passionately against any actors, such as the heads of state 
in Central and Eastern Europe, as well as the United Kingdom, who favoured a 
weaker rather than a stronger European Union (Boon, 2007, p. 293; Habermas, 
2005, p. 5). For him, the threats posed by American neoconservativism are so 
serious that there is no other choice: either Europe takes on this civilizing role or 
cosmopolitanism will fail and the USA’s imperialist unilateralism will triumph 
(Habermas, 2006a, p. 52).   

It is imperative to note here that, for Habermas, this cosmopolitan struggle against 
the imperialist tendencies of the United States is not a fight against the idea of the 
West as such: rather, he positions his work firmly within the Western political 
tradition (Habermas, 2006a, p. 50). Moreover, he fears that any general arguments 



Habermas and Bush’s Neoconservatives   171 

 
Studies in Social Justice, Volume 5, Issue 2, 2011 

	
  

against the idea of the West could end up throwing out the baby with the bathwater, 
that is to say, they could lead to an outright rejection of the communicative 
rationality which for him clearly developed on the Western side of the Berlin Wall 
(Habermas, 2005, p. 9). Instead, by positioning communicative rationality (that  
of the social realm, the lifeworld) in direct opposition to instrumental rationality 
(that of the economic system) he argues that the tragedy of modernity is a  
one-sided development of reason (Habermas, 1984, 1985, 1987b). This one-sided 
development of reason means that instrumental rationality (which is focused 
merely on achieving strategic ends) has encroached on the lifeworld (characterized 
by reaching understanding) (Habermas, 1987a, 1987b). Thus what needs to happen 
is an opening up of communicative channels so that the system can be brought 
under the control of the lifeworld once again.  

 
 
Habermas on Islamic Fundamentalism: The Desired End of  
Western Democracy 
 
It is also on the basis of this perspective of his Western-based theory of a one-sided 
rationality that Habermas interprets the phenomenon of Islamic fundamentalism.6 
In his interview with Borradori, Habermas perceives Islamic global terrorism as a 
thoroughly modern phenomenon bound up with modernizing processes and  
the alienation caused by economic misery. He explains that the same globalizing 
and modernizing processes that swept through Europe are now sweeping through 
the Middle East.7 Yet, in Europe these modernizing processes were at least 
compensated for by significant benefits, whilst the Middle East has only seen a 
widening gap between the economic winners and losers (Habermas, 2003, p. 32). 
The upshot is that in the Middle East “a process of productive destruction does not 
hold the same promise of compensation for the pain of the disintegration of 
customary ways of life” (p. 32). 

Hence, rather than perceiving Islamic fundamentalism in light of Huntington’s 
thesis of the clash of civilizations, Habermas (2003) points towards its economic 
causes. Given these economic origins, he does not deem it surprising that the 
terrorists chose to strike at the heart of the capital enterprise of the USA, the 
country regarded in the Arab world as the driving force of capitalist modernization. 
He remarks that “the West in its entirety serves as a scapegoat for the Arab world’s 
own, very real experience of loss suffered by populations torn out of their cultural 
traditions during processes of accelerated modernization.” Nevertheless, “with its 
unapproachable lead in development and with its overwhelming technological and 
economic, political and military superiority, the USA appears as an insult to their 
self-confidence whilst simultaneously providing a secretly admired model” (p. 32).  

It is this level of frustration caused by economic deprivation, he argues, that has 
led religious fundamentalists to have recourse to pre-modern beliefs and traditional 
notions of identity. For the alienation caused by the uprooting of a way of life 
makes people yearn for a return to a shared, pre-modern, meaning-endowing 
identity (Rosenfeld, 2007, p. 159). This yearning is unrealistic, however, in that in 
modern complex societies an exclusive claim to truth by one faith can no longer be 
maintained. So, if Middle Eastern societies want to renounce such dogmatic 
attitudes, they would need to embark upon a path of self-reflexivity akin to the one 



172   Vivienne Matthies-Boon 
 
	
  

Studies in Social Justice, Volume 3, Issue 1, 21-36, 2009 
 
Studies in Social Justice, Volume 5, Issue 2, 2011 

	
  

undertaken in Europe. For “in Europe, the confessional schism and the 
secularization of society have compelled religious belief to reflect on its non-
exclusive place within a universal discourse shared with other religions and limited 
by scientifically generated secular knowledge” (Habermas, 2003, p. 31). As long as 
“fundamentalists—and states like Iran—strive for the reestablishment of an Islamic 
form of theocracy, they repress any cognitive dissonances and thus remain tied 
within a fundamentalist framework” (pp. 31-32). In order to embark on this journey 
of enlightenment and be able to grapple with cognitive dissonances, what needs to 
be improved is—rather unsurprisingly—communication.  

For, while it is economic problems that underlie Islamic fundamentalism,  
the issue can be solved by rectifying patterns of distorted communication.  
After all, these conflicts primarily “arise from distorted communication, from 
misunderstanding and incomprehension, from insincerity and deception.” 
(Habermas, 2003:35) It is here that the spiral of distorted communication begins, 
which then leads to mutual mistrust, eventually resulting in a complete breakdown 
of communication. This spiral of distorted communication is further strengthened 
by the fact that both the Islamists and the Bush administration are geared towards 
strategic action rather than communicative action, in that they both seek to achieve 
their particular ends rather than reach understanding. Yet Habermas (2003) does 
not lose his optimism for “if violence . . . begins with a distortion in 
communication, after it has erupted it is possible to know what has gone wrong and 
what needs to be repaired” (p. 35); namely, communication. However, in terms of 
repairing communication, his proposals remain rather abstract and vague. First, he 
puts forward a general argument for a stronger legal international order and a 
particular reinforcement of the UN. At the moment, the UN is reduced to the 
proverbial paper tiger, but with some further encouragement the cosmopolitan 
seeds within the UN can grow and can begin to flourish on a world stage (p. 39). 
Second, he argues that a model of democratic constitutionalism can be seen as a 
solution to the problems pestering the Middle East: for he insists that only such a 
deliberative political order would enhance reflexivity so as to be capable of 
incorporating civil disobedience, even beyond its own boundaries of tolerance (p. 
41). A constitutional democracy is reliant on an active civil society, and will be 
able to incorporate Islamic resistance. As he explains, “the democratic project of 
the realization of equal rights actually feeds off the resistance of minorities, which, 
although appearing as enemies of democracy to the majority today, could actually 
turn out to be their authentic friends tomorrow.” Not only that, but a constitutional 
order would also ensure that a universalistic liberal legal order is established, 
characterized by an “egalitarian individualism of a morality that demands mutual 
recognition, in the sense of equal respect and reciprocal consideration for 
everybody” (p. 42). As Michel Rosenfeld (2007) nicely points out, the gist of 
Habermas's story thus seems to be that  

 
From the standpoint of Muslim societies . . . communicative action would lead to the 
abandonment of authoritarianism, and the use of Islam to inflame masses. Muslim 
politics could willingly embrace the material gains of a globalization fine-tuned to 
promote equal opportunities and social justice. Moreover, Muslim societies would 
adjust their own lifeworld and legal and political institutions in order to reconcile 
Islam, modernism and fair and responsible globalisation. The resulting Islam would 



Habermas and Bush’s Neoconservatives   173 

 
Studies in Social Justice, Volume 5, Issue 2, 2011 

	
  

not be fundamentalist but accepting of pluralism, like other great religions that have 
adjusted to the conditions of modern multiculturalism. (p. 168) 
 

However, such a conception is highly problematic. The first notable difficulty is 
that Habermas nowhere directly engages with Islamicist political thought or even 
with Middle Eastern politics. As a result of this, Habermas, like the Bushite 
neoconservatives, directly equates the problem of Islamic fundamentalism with the 
turbulence of Middle Eastern politics and society. And as Middle East expert 
Olivier Roy (2008) explains, this is a mistake commonly made by Western 
commentators, and serves to allow them to project familiar problems that exist in 
Europe (caused by migration) onto the quite different area of the Middle East. Yet 
that this projection is ambiguous comes to the fore when one realizes that  

 
Al Qaeda’s recruitment map [does not necessarily] mirror conflicts in the Middle East, 
since there is a predominance of young second generation European Muslims and 
converts, but there are no Palestinians or Afghans and very few recruits from the Middle 
East. The Islamists, like the Arab Muslim Brotherhood, are not involved in international 
terrorism. Nor do neofundamentalists [within the Middle East] recruit in traditional 
milieus, but instead among migrants, refugees, the second generation, the new social 
classes, or among tribes undergoing change. (p. 52) 

 
Hence the move from the problem of Islamic fundamentalism directly to Middle 
Eastern politics is rather too quick in Habermas's account, just as it is too quick in 
the neoconservative’s worldview, where “9/11” was the directly invoked reason to 
invade Iraq in 2003. Of course, I am not claiming here that Habermas's model 
would lead to, or even directly encourage, such direct invasions, but rather I am 
making the more modest claim that both strands of thought are engaged in the same 
mistake of projection and that a more careful, sensitive and differentiated empirical 
analysis is needed. 

Worse even than this, however, is the fact that Habermas’s perception of Islamic 
fundamentalism and the Middle East is not only inaccurate, but also extremely 
offensive. It is offensive in that he completely ignores the complex colonial history 
of the Middle East and merely interprets these issues in light of his western theory 
of modernity (Habermas, 1979a, 1987a). This theory of modernity is anyway 
problematic, in that it is based on his account of social evolution which (despite his 
own assertions) leads him to interpret historical events in an evolutionary line that 
culminates in a cosmopolitan post-conventional order. This evolutionary line is 
modelled explicitly on Western developments (Boon, 2009, chapter 2). The upshot 
of this is that when he looks at Middle Eastern affairs, it becomes a case of these 
“Middle Easterners” needing to become more like “us.” They are simply lagging 
behind on the evolutionary scale, and need to become more reflexive, as well as to 
implement a constitutional democracy. Only when they discover the fruits of liberal 
democracy will they find peace and security. The complexity of Islamic 
fundamentalism as well as Middle Eastern politics is reduced and their alterity 
changed into familiar Western concepts which, of course, ensures that the West 
gets off extremely lightly. For example, while at one point he remarks that 
disappointment with an autocratic regime might boost Islamic fundamentalism, he 
nowhere reflects on the active role of the West in keeping these regimes in power. 
At no point does Habermas refer to the legacy of colonialism or to the unfair 



174   Vivienne Matthies-Boon 
 
	
  

Studies in Social Justice, Volume 3, Issue 1, 21-36, 2009 
 
Studies in Social Justice, Volume 5, Issue 2, 2011 

	
  

policies inflicted upon the Middle East by the Western powers both in the present 
and in the past. He does not even mention Western meddling, interference and 
cheating in Middle Eastern affairs—let alone the three biggest traumas inflicted 
upon the Middle East in recent history, namely the Sykes Picot agreement in 1916, 
the establishment of the State of Israel in 1948 and the overthrow of the Sunni 
political primacy in the Middle East as a result of the 2003 Iraq invasion (e.g. Roy, 
2008, pp. 76-79). But given this colonial history, it is simply outrageous to argue 
that the very same processes of rationalization that occurred in Europe are now 
taking place in the Middle East. For a start, we might point out that Europe has not 
been recently colonized.8 Hence, rather than seeing the Middle East’s alterity, he 
insists that it is simply the economy that is to blame, rather than Western political 
order itself having any role. But this is simply untenable.  

His blindness to the colonial past also stops him from questioning the values of a 
liberal constitutional democratic order, values which are not automatically shared 
by many actors in the Middle East. In fact, much of the Islamist ideology that 
Habermas criticizes developed in direct response to Western developments and 
Western concepts of individualism, liberty and freedom. He completely overlooks 
this relation between Islamicism and Western ideologies, such as nationalism, 
liberalism and socialism, none of which were seen by the Islamists as viable and 
authentic alternatives to the autocratic regimes in the Middle East. The reason why 
these strands of thought were deemed unsuitable by the Islamists was precisely 
because they were tainted by Western (conceptions of) reason and thus lacked the 
requisite authenticity when transferred to a different context (Roy, 1998, passim). 
This kind of objection can be properly acknowledged only if one takes into account 
the impact of colonialism and post-colonialism which Habermas simply ignores. To 
offer liberal democracy as a response to problems arising at least in part out of that 
democracy and from responses to it is neither realistic nor respectful of those 
formerly colonized.  

In this matter in particular, the issue is that Habermas comes closer to the 
neoconservatives than he realizes. For they too looked for the root causes of 
Islamic terrorism and they too ruled out any direct Western responsibility for 
radical Islamic violence (Roy, 2008, p. 29). Rather,  

 
in their view, the source of this violence is the Arab societies’ institutional structures 
which are hindering human, political and economic development. . . . For the 
neoconservative lobby, the structural explanation of terrorism argues that it is spawned by 
poor “governance” of the Muslim countries in general, and of Arab ones in particular. (p. 
29) 
 
It is the lack of such governmental structures that keeps “them” from becoming 

like “us.” Hence, like, Habermas, they “are diametrically opposed to Huntington’s 
‘clash of civilisations’ theory” (Roy, 2008, p. 30) and, again like Habermas, they 
seek to resolve the problem of Islamic fundamentalism through the development 
and export of formal democratic political institutions. Hence, like Habermas, they 
are in favour of the development of active civil societies, which for them too are 
positioned in-between the state and the individual and can hold a potentially 
authoritarian state to account (Roy, 2008, p. 34). They too believe that encouraging 
a vibrant civil society will resolve and incorporate the difficulties of Islamic terror. 



Habermas and Bush’s Neoconservatives   175 

 
Studies in Social Justice, Volume 5, Issue 2, 2011 

	
  

Hence, both Habermas and the neoconservatives take the ends of democracy, 
individualism and an active civil society for granted and see the creation and 
strengthening of democratic political institutions as a viable—indeed as the only—
response to the problems of the Middle East. But neither Habermas nor the 
neoconservatives engage with concrete processes on the ground. Their theoretical 
and/or ideological preferences leads them both to posit as desirable the goal of 
formal democratic processes based on the Western democratic model, without any 
empirical analysis, without allowing the people on the ground any voice. 
 
 
International Institutionalism vs. Neoliberalism? 
 
However, where the neoconservatives and Habermas differ is in their respective 
analyses of the benefits of the free market.9 The former’s neoliberalism demands 
that the primary role of the state or international institutions is not to counter the 
negative effects of the market, but rather to encourage its growth. Or rather, as Roy 
puts it, “for the neoconservatives democracy implies the full acceptance of the 
market economy, and therefore of privatization” (Roy, 2008, p. 31). Hence, in 
contrast to Habermas, the neoconservatives have a very limited conception of 
politics, namely as one the primary aim of which is not to interfere with market 
forces (e.g. Hassan, 2009, p. 25). In contrast, for Habermas the market should not 
be entirely “free,” on account of its negative effects on processes of rationalization 
and its unequal distribution of wealth and resources. Rather, he insists, the market 
needs to be brought under the control of international regulation and deliberation 
through multilateral organizations such as the UN.  

 Yet there is a practical difficulty here: namely, that the UN, given in Habermas’s 
work the task of bringing the market under control, has in fact become one of the 
prime agents for the promotion of market values across the world. So how exactly 
can this institution further his cosmopolitan approach? Without a more detailed, 
empirically informed and concrete analysis, Habermas's appeals to the UN as the 
harbinger of cosmopolitanism are at best empty and at worst stand to lend 
legitimacy to the very neoliberal order that he opposes. For since the former 
Secretary-General Kofi Annan reformed its institutions and redesigned the rationale 
and conduct of many of its programs at the end of the 1990s, the UN has embraced 
the free market and sought to spread “democracy” and “good governance” across 
the world. The perceived benefits of the market were notably lauded in a speech 
given by Kofi Annan to the World Economic Forum in Davos in 1997, where he 
stated that the UN should from now on promote “economic and political 
liberalization and the development of dynamic private sectors as the best strategy 
for effective peace-keeping across the world” (Cammack, 2006, p. 6). He even 
went so far as to argue that 
 

First, there is a universal understanding that market forces are essential for sustainable 
development. Second, the role of the state is changing in most of the developing world, 
from one that seeks to dominate economic life to one which creates the conditions 
through which sustainable development is possible. Third, there is growing and 
compelling evidence that the poor can solve their own problems if they only are given 
fair access to business and development services. (Annan, 1997) 

 



176   Vivienne Matthies-Boon 
 
	
  

Studies in Social Justice, Volume 3, Issue 1, 21-36, 2009 
 
Studies in Social Justice, Volume 5, Issue 2, 2011 

	
  

This announcement set the tone for the transformation of the UN’s developmental 
policies, which held that a growth in global trade was advantageous and mostly that 
the poor should by no means be excluded from the benefits unleashed by the global 
market. Not only that, but private market forces were perceived as the primary and 
lasting solution to instability and insecurity. Hence, Annan even insisted that  
 

in today's world the private sector is the dominant engine of growth; the principal 
creator of value and wealth; the source of the largest financial, technological, and 
managerial resources. If the private sector does not deliver economic [sic] and economic 
opportunity—equitably and sustainably—around the world, then peace will remain 
fragile and social justice a distant dream. (Annan, 1997) 

 
This view, naïve in its analysis of market forces as it may be, has since continued to 
set the tone for the UN’s institutional structure and content of its development 
programs. Basically, the UN now merely ensures that the right infrastructures for 
the flow of capitalism are put in place, after which it leaves it up to the people in a 
particular country or area to grab their opportunity and buy into market logic in 
order to help themselves. In other words, rather than providing structural 
development money for the state or state-sponsored institutions, the UN has now 
cultivated a kind of do-it-yourself model of development entirely in line with the 
neoliberal agenda (Berger, 2001). The role of the state is thus reduced to that of 
facilitating capitalist market forces, and is actually held accountable by the 
international institution if insufficient progress has been made on this front. This 
progress has been further developed and monitored by a competitive model of peer 
review since the Brussels Declaration and Program of Action in 2001. Here, 
“model” apprentices10 are accorded the honour of reviewing their less performing 
peers, i.e. ones that had not made as much progress in economic liberalization in 
order to help spread “good practice” (Cammack, 2006, p. 16).  

This belief in competition and the logic of free market has been further 
entrenched in the United Nations through its institutional reforms, for example the 
closer collaboration between the Economic and Social Council, the UN 
Commission on Trade and Development the Bretton Woods organisations (the IMF 
and World Bank) and the World Trade Organisation11 (Cammack, 2006, p. 11). It is 
clear that the Secretary-General believed in the poverty reduction programs led by 
the Bretton Woods institutions and carved out a special role for the UN in further 
facilitating these neoliberal programs. An active link in this closer cooperation and 
the further development of the neoliberal agenda within the UN was Mark Malloch 
Brown, a “completely self-confessed free-trader,” who had previously served as the 
World Bank’s “chief propagandist (Vice-President and Director of External 
Relations)” before becoming the United Nations Development Program 
Administrator (Cammack, 2006, p. 11; see also UN, 2011). He pushed forward an 
interventionist agenda where the UN institutions, in close collaboration with the 
IMF, would act to open up markets in developing countries. It is for instance this 
kind of vision that is at the heart of the Millennium Development Goals, adopted in 
September 2000, which sought to eradicate poverty, enhance rights and protect the 
environment through the standard panacea of so-called transparency and good 
governance.  



Habermas and Bush’s Neoconservatives   177 

 
Studies in Social Justice, Volume 5, Issue 2, 2011 

	
  

The point of this brief discussion of the United Nations reforms and its embracing 
of neoliberalism is to show how hard it is to regard the UN as one of the leading 
agents in a cosmopolitan model such as that proposed by Habermas. For in 
Habermas’s account, the international institution would not only counter the 
neoconservative unilateralist point of view, but also correct market forces 
communicatively. In practice, however, it seems that the UN is doing precisely the 
opposite: it is opening up markets under the banners of democracy, good 
governance and human rights. So when the UN states that “good governance at the 
national and international level; the rule of law, respect for all internationally, 
human rights […and] the promotion of democracy […] are all essential in order to 
realize the vast and untapped human and economic potential in LDCs [Least 
Developed Countries] [emphasis mine]”(UN General Assembly, in Cammack, 
2006, p. 14) what might be Habermas’s response? After all, this kind of reasoning 
is precisely what he opposes, when he argues, against the Bush administration, that 
“the West presents itself in a form deprived of any normative kernel so long as its 
concern for human rights only concerns the attempt at opening up new free 
markets” (Habermas, 2003, p. 33). This in turn leads one to wonder how Habermas 
could possibly have just overlooked the neoliberal ideology underpinning these 
international institutions. Admittedly, his is a highly abstract and idealized account, 
and one which perhaps inevitably leads him to cherry-pick those instances that suit 
his own theoretical framework and to see actual developments through social 
evolutionary-tainted lenses.12 Nevertheless, the oversight is in the circumstances 
remarkable. 

How might it be explained? Might the explanation lie simply in Habermas's own 
implicit belief in and endorsement of capitalist market forces? While he of course 
criticizes the one-sided rationality of market forces, his very distinction between 
the communicative realm and the realm of the system seems to posit the capitalist 
system as a necessary ingredient for modernization (Boon, 2010, p. 159). For the 
structural problems caused by the economic system lead to developments in the 
social realm as it seeks new solutions: in other words, the market is a necessary 
condition of evolutionary development. But even if that were too harsh a reading of 
Habermas, it would make no difference to the present problem. For Habermas 
agrees with Kofi Annan that “today, market capitalism has no major ideological 
rival.” (Annan, 1997) when he claims that “since 1989-1990 it has become 
impossible to break out of the universe of capitalism; the only option is to civilise 
and tame the capitalist dynamic from within” (Habermas, 2009, p. 187) through 
communicative processes. But given his “realism” about capitalism, one might 
have expected Habermas at least to offer an explanation of how the facts of 
“actually existing capitalism” do not render his communicative idealism redundant 
just as they render redundant other ideals; and to show how his own approach is 
compatible with capitalist realities, in particular, how the UN can serve in the way 
he envisages to ensure that capitalism “promote(s) both prosperity and justice” as 
Annan hopes it might (Annan, 1997). But he does not. Nowhere in his work does 
Habermas offer even a minimal account of how capitalism might be open to 
“communicative adjustment.”  

 
 

 



178   Vivienne Matthies-Boon 
 
	
  

Studies in Social Justice, Volume 3, Issue 1, 21-36, 2009 
 
Studies in Social Justice, Volume 5, Issue 2, 2011 

	
  

Wilsonian Internationalism vs Neoconservativism? 
 
The final element of affinity between Habermas and Bush’s neoconservative 
project is their common appeal to the internationalist legacy of Woodrow Wilson. 
When countering Bush’s unilateralism, Habermas appeals to the American 
Wilsonian legacy in order to remind the neoconservatives of what he perceives as 
America’s multilateral and cosmopolitan traditions (Habermas, 2006a, p. 156), 
hoping in so doing that the neoconservatives will see the light and embrace a more 
cosmopolitan future: for he firmly believes that Wilsonian internationalism will 
lead to a spread of liberal democracy and the international rule of law across the 
globe. Yet, as I will show, this appeal to Wilsonian internationalism in fact again 
indicates a somewhat uncomfortable closeness between Habermas and the 
neoconservatives.  

After all, the neoconservatives could not themselves agree more with Habermas's 
appeal to Wilson. They remember Wilson very well. Wilson believed: (1) that the 
spread of democracy across the world would bring peace and prosperity (a thesis 
now known as democratic peace theory13); (2) that democracy was a universal 
value; (3) and that no one was incapable of self-government (including those 
people in Latin America deemed by many as unsuited for self-governance at the 
time); and (4) that, most importantly, the United States was the bearer of the moral 
project of spreading democracy across the world (Encarnación, 2005). On the basis 
of these beliefs, Wilson himself had actively and unilaterally intervened in Latin 
America, where he sought to install democracy with the aim of leading people to 
democratic enlightenment under America’s specific patronage. Now, in the Bush 
administration such a Wilsonian streak became most pronounced after “9/11,” 
when the ideologically loaded Freedom Agenda was explicitly developed by the 
White House to spread both democracy and the benefits of the free market to the 
Middle East, starting with Iraq (see Hassan, 2009, p. 194). Thus, Wilson’s 
interventionist and internationalist philosophy was at the heart of Bush’s 
intervention in Iraq (Dueck, 2003; Hassan, 2009).14 Crucial for this idealist agenda 
was the Wilson-inspired interventionist belief that democracy should be spread 
across the Middle East, that everyone (including Arab Islamic believers) was 
capable of engaging in democratic processes and that the USA had a special duty to 
fulfill in this respect (see Hassan, 2009). The White House thereby broke with 
American policy that had been fearful the spread of democracy would result in the 
election of an anti-American Islamist government (Encarnación, 2005, p. 4715) and 
instead insisted that only the imposition of a democratic order in Iraq would install 
peace and security in the region. As Bush stated at the time,  

 
The world has a clear interest in the spread of democratic values, because stable and 
free nations do not breed the ideologies of murder. They encourage the peaceful pursuit 
of a better life. And there are hopeful signs of a desire for freedom in the Middle East. 
Arab intellectuals have called on Arab governments to address the "freedom gap" so 
their peoples can fully share in the progress of our times. Leaders in the region speak of 
a new Arab charter that champions internal reform, greater politics participation, 
economic openness, and free trade. And from Morocco to Bahrain and beyond, nations 
are taking genuine steps toward politics reform. A new regime in Iraq would serve as a 
dramatic and inspiring example of freedom for other nations in the region. (Bush, 2003) 



Habermas and Bush’s Neoconservatives   179 

 
Studies in Social Justice, Volume 5, Issue 2, 2011 

	
  

 
Bush clearly believed that, in terms of Middle Eastern politics, “democracies would 
not fight each other, they would all recognise Israel, whose security would be 
guaranteed by the democratization of the Arab countries. Terrorism would no 
longer be an option. The domino theory would operate for the benefit of the West” 
(Roy, 2008, p. 40). And so the neoconservatives carved out a special role for the 
United States of America, just as Wilson had believed that “as the definite example 
of democracy, the United States had a special obligation to extend its benefits and 
to instruct backward peoples in its uses” (Wilson cited in Encarnación, 2005, p. 
49). 

The difficulties that arise from the above is that Habermas's own appeals to the 
Wilsonian legacy are insufficiently informed by a critical analysis of what this 
Wilsonian legacy might entail. Had he undertaken a critical, historical and more 
empirical analysis of Wilson’s thoughts and actions, he might have realized that 
Wilson was a dubious basis for an internationalist cosmopolitan project. Indeed, 
given this rather ambiguous legacy it is questionable as to what extent reference to 
Wilson would do anything but affirm a belief in spreading democracy abroad. Of 
course Habermas insists on a multilateral variant of the institutionalization of 
global democracy through international multi-levelled governance: but the point 
remains that Wilson undertook an active policy in exporting and imposing 
democracy abroad. By appealing to this legacy Habermas all too easily positions 
himself closer to this agenda.  

My point is not that Habermas himself favours the forceful imposition of 
democracy from above by a third party, but rather that he has to be far more careful 
in his choice of historical ally if he is to avoid seeming to propose something all too 
easily compatible with, and even uncomfortably close to, the neoconservative 
agenda. For his close association with the Wilsonian legacy leaves him vulnerable 
to being appropriated by those he seeks to oppose. Habermas opens the way for the 
neoconservatives to employ his own citation of Wilson to advance their own 
agenda, particularly in respect of Habermas’s arguments that a constitutional 
democracy would solve problems of Islamic fundamentalism. Of course, every 
theorist and every philosopher could be appropriated, twisted and used for ends 
they oppose. But this risk of appropriation needs surely to be anticipated, especially 
in an instance such as this, where the neoconservatives incorporate insights 
originating in the political left: principled interventionism, an insistence on human 
rights and freedom, the advancement of civil society and the promotion of 
democracy. Is Habermas really unaware that, as Roy has it, the neoconservatives 
“are closer to a left-wing progressivism that rejects cultural relativism of any kind 
rather than to a colonialism anxious above all to maintain the prevailing order” 
(Roy, 2008, p. 4)?  
 
 
Conclusion  
 
Habermas’s commitment to cosmopolitanism stands in danger of being 
appropriated by a very different form of cosmopolitanism than his own: a 
neoconservative cosmopolitanism. For what else is the Project for the New 
American Century (1997) if not one sort of cosmopolitanism, however partial, self-



180   Vivienne Matthies-Boon 
 
	
  

Studies in Social Justice, Volume 3, Issue 1, 21-36, 2009 
 
Studies in Social Justice, Volume 5, Issue 2, 2011 

	
  

interested and ruthless? To avoid such misappropriation, Habermas needs explicitly 
to differentiate his cosmopolitanism from theirs and to anticipate the contours of 
how such misappropriation might occur. Otherwise not only can his own arguments 
come inadvertently to be invoked to buttress a neoliberal agenda, just as have other 
arguments from the left over the last twenty or more years, but the very idea of a 
left-wing cosmopolitanism might all too easily be lost in consequence. Though the 
responsibility is an onerous one, it cannot be shirked. 
 
 
Notes 
	
  
1    This paper has significantly benefitted from conversations with Andrej Zwitter, Jaap de Wilde and 

my husband Tim Matthies. Thanks also to Bob Brecher for his patience. 
2     Neoconservativism of course has a longer history of thought development as well as political action 

than the Bush administration and is by no means limited to the United States of America. However, 
since I am preoccupied here with a perceived problem in Habermas, I am restricting the term 
neoconservative to that of the Bushite ideologues, the primary target of Habermas's own recent 
political critiques. For more information on neoconservativism prior to Bush, please see Gerson, 
1996. 

3    Some commentators on Habermas would make a distinction between his political and theoretical 
works: however, as I have shown (see Boon, 2009) Habermas himself muddles these two distinct 
analytical categories in his work. For this reason I will not pose an analytical distinction between 
these two modes of writing and instead take them as a whole.  

4    “Constitutional Patriotism” was originally a term developed by Dolf Sternberger for a particularly 
German situation (namely unification). Habermas adopted it to suit his European project, and 
argued that this would open the possibility for a model of European integration not based on thicker 
cultural notions of identity, but on thin legal principles (Habermas, 1996). The irony is that 
Habermas nevertheless searches for thicker notions of European identity to counter American 
imperialism and as a means of endorsing his European project of constitutional patriotism (Boon, 
2009, chapter 1; Müller, 2000, p. 94). 

5     As I shall note in more detail in section 3, Habermas's analysis of the benefits of the free market is 
hence somewhat different from that of the neoconservatives, who regard the advancement of the 
market as one of their primary aims on account of its being, for them, a primary good. 

6      For an earlier critical reading of Habermas's comments on Islamic fundamentalism, see Boon, 2010. 
7    Habermas' comments on Islamic fundamentalism occur prior to the Arab Spring in 2011—for a 

critical analysis of the relation between Habermas' comments on Islamic fundamentalism and the 
Arab Spring. See Matthies-Boon, forthcoming 2012. 

8     Apart from the Eastern and Central European states which were of course part of the Soviet empire 
for several decades: but Habermas has an ambiguous relation to the Central and Eastern European 
legacy and does not count these states as genuinely European. “Europe” for Habermas is definitely 
on the Western side of the Wall. 

9     It is in fact also on this point that Habermas launched a public campaign against the neoconservative 
outlook in the 1980s (Habermas, 1989). Apart from their dubious relation to German history, one of 
his main criticisms was the neoconservatives’ return to heavily freighted notions such as tradition, 
while upholding a blind belief in the free market. In Habermas’s eyes, while they sought to 
compensate for the one-sided instrumental rationality of the market in their stated reliance on, for 
example, tradition, instrumental rationality can be compensated for only by communicative 
processes. He thus insisted that we should not revert to pre-modern notions of tradition or to 
irrational concepts of culture, but rather move forward and look to establish a deliberative social 
order (see Habermas, 1985, 1987a).  

10     States that have in place the necessary governmental support for the growth of free enterprise. 
11    They have held annual meetings since 1998 and have provided a forum for this increasingly close 

cooperation behind the scenes (Cammack, 2006, p. 11). 
12    See Boon (2009) for a more detailed analysis of this problem in Habermas’s work. Also see Hon-

neth and Joas (1988). 



Habermas and Bush’s Neoconservatives   181 

 
Studies in Social Justice, Volume 5, Issue 2, 2011 

	
  

	
  
13   Democratic peace theory ,while popular not only among politicians but also among international 

relations scholars, is problematic in that it looks primarily at the conflict between states rather than 
between states and non-state actors, which is one of the most common forms of conflict in our time. 
It also fails to account for the amount of violence that occurs once a state makes a transition towards 
democracy and thus only takes the end result, a fully-fledged established democracy, as its unit of 
analysis. When imposed by force, of course, it entangles itself in contradiction. 

14    Within American political science the debate on the Wilsonian legacy and the Bush administration 
is too extensive to do justice to here: see, among others, Ambrosius, 2006; Fleming, 2003a, 2003b; 
Hoff, 2007; Kennedy, 2005; Levine, 2006. 

15    This fear is also largely based on the Algerian case in the 1990s where a military coup supported by 
Western forces took aim to prevent the election into government of the Islamic Salvation Front. 
Since the failures of the invasion in Iraq and the entanglements the American administration got 
itself into, this fear has returned and a more pragmatic approach based on realist rather than idealist 
concerns returned to the White House (see Roy, 2008). 

 
 
 
References 
 
Ambrosius, L. E. (2006). Woodrow Wilson and George W. Bush: Historical comparisons of ends and 

means in their foreign policies. Diplomatic History 30, 509-543. 
Annan, K. (1997). Secretary-General in address to World Economic Forum, stressing partnership 

between United Nations, private sector. [Press Release]. Retrieved from  
    http://www.un.org/News/Press/docs/1997/19970131.sgsm6153.html  
Berger, M. T. (2001). The rise and demise of national development and the origins of post-cold war 

capitalism. Millennium: Journal of International Studies, 30, 211-234. 
Boon, V. (2007). Habermas’s writings on Europe: Not Habermasian enough? Ethical Perspectives, 14, 

287-310 
Boon, V. (2009). On a Europe without controversial learning curves: Using Habermas against 

Habermas (Unpublished doctoral dissertation). University of Liverpool, Liverpool. 
Boon, V., (2010). Jürgen Habermas and Islamic fundamentalism: On the limits of discourse ethics. 

Journal of Global Ethics, 6, 153-166 
Bush, G. W. (2003). George Bush's speech to the American Enterprise Institute. Retrieved from 

http://www.guardian.co.uk/world/2003/feb/27/usa.iraq2   
Cammack, P. (2006). UN Imperialism: Unleashing entrepreneurship in the developing world. Papers in 

the Politics of Global Competitiveness, No. 2, Institute for Global Studies. Manchester Metropolitan 
University, Manchester. 

Dueck, C. (2003). Hegemony on the cheap: Liberal internationalism from Wilson to Bush. World Policy 
Journal, 20, 1-11. 

Encarnación, O. G. (2005). The Follies of Democratic Imperialism. World Policy Journal, 22(1), 47-60.  
Fleming, T. (2003a, May 19). President Bush’s Woodrow Wilson problem. Retrieved from 

http://hnn.us/articles/1451.html  
Fleming, T. (2003b, September 8). What we’re grappling with in Iraq is Woodrow Wilson’s legacy. 

Retrieved from http://hnn.us/articles/1668.html  
Gerson, M. (1996). The neoconservative vision: From the Cold War to culture wars. New York, NY: 

Madison Books. 
Habermas, J. (1979a). Communication and the evolution of society. Boston, MA: Beacon Press. 
Habermas, J. (1979b). History and evolution. Telos, 39, 5-44. 
Habermas, J. (1984). The theory of communicative action volume 1. Reason and the rationalization of 

society. Cambridge: Polity Press.  
Habermas, J. (1985). Modernity—an incomplete project. In H. Foster (Ed), Postmodern Culture (pp. 3-

15). London: Pluto Press.  
Habermas, J. (1987a). The philosophical discourse of modernity. Cambridge: Polity Press. 
Habermas, J. (1987b). The theory of communicative action, Volume 2. Lifeworld and system: A critique 

of functionalist reason. Cambridge: Polity Press. 



182   Vivienne Matthies-Boon 
 
	
  

Studies in Social Justice, Volume 3, Issue 1, 21-36, 2009 
 
Studies in Social Justice, Volume 5, Issue 2, 2011 

	
  

	
  
Habermas, J. (1989). The new conservatism: Cultural criticism and the historians debate. Cambridge, 

MA: MIT University Press. 
Habermas, J. (1996). Between facts and norms: Contributions to a discourse theory of law and 

democracy. Cambridge: Polity Press. 
Habermas, J. (1997a). Kant’s perpetual peace, with the benefit of 200 year’s hindsight. In J. Bohman & 

M. Lutz-Bachmann (Eds.), Perpetual peace: Essays on Kant’s cosmopolitan ideal (pp. 113-134). 
Cambridge, MA: MIT University Press. 

Habermas, J. (2001). The postnational constellation. Cambridge: Polity Press. 
Habermas, J. (2003). Fundamentalism and terror. In G. Borradorri (Ed.) Philosophy in a time of terror: 

Dialogues with Jürgen Habermas and Jacques Derrida (pp. 25-45). Chicago, IL: University of 
Chicago Press.  

Habermas, J. (2004). America and the World: A conversation with Jürgen Habermas with Eduardo 
Mendieta. Logos Journal, 3(3). Retrieved from http://www.logosjournal.com/habermas_america.htm  

Habermas, J. (2005). February 15, or, what binds Europeans together: Plea for a common foreign policy, 
beginning in core Europe. In D. Levy, M. Pensky, & J. Torpey (Eds.) Old Europe, new Europe, core 
Europe (pp. 3-14). London: Verso.  

Habermas, J. (2006a). The Divided West. Cambridge: Polity Press. 
Habermas, J. (2006b). Time of transitions. Cambridge: Polity Press. 
Habermas, J. (2009). Europe: The faltering project. Cambridge: Polity Press. 
Honneth, A., & Joas, H. (1988). Social action and human nature. Cambridge: Cambridge University 

Press. 
Hassan, O. (2009). George W. Bush, September the 11th and the rise of the freedom agenda in US-

Middle East relations: A constructivist institutionalist approach. (Doctoral dissertation). Retrieved 
from http://etheses.bham.ac.uk/399/  

Hoff, J. (2007). A faustian foreign policy from Woodrow Wilson to George W. Bush: Dreams of 
perfectibility. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 

Kennedy, D. M. (2005). What “W” owes to “WW.” Atlantic, 295. Retrieved from 
    http://theatlantic.com/doc/200503/kennedy 
Khan, A. (2011). A portfolio theory of foreign affairs: The US relations with the Muslim World. 

Transnational Law and Contemporary Problems, 91, 377-410.  
Levine, P. (2006). George W. Bush and Woodrow Wilson. Retrieved from 
    http://www.peterlevine.ws/mt/archives/000811.html  
Matthies-Boon, V. (in print). Jürgen Habermas and the democratisation of Islamic fundamentalism: The 

case of the Egyptian Muslim Brotherhood. In T. Bailey (Ed.) Habermas from Global Perspectives. 
London: Routledge. 

Müller, J.-W. (2000). Another country: German intellectuals, unification and national identity. New 
Haven, CT: Yale University Press. 

Rosenfeld, M. (2007). Habermas’s call for cosmopolitan constitutional patriotism in an age of global 
terror: A pluralist appraisal. Constellations, 14, 159–181. 

Roy, O. (1998). The failure of political Islam. New Haven, CT: Harvard University Press. 
Roy, O. (2008). The politics of chaos in the Middle East. New York, NY: Columbia University Press. 
UN Senior Management Group. (2011). Mark Malloch Brown. Retrieved from  
    http://www.un.org/News/ossg/sg/stories/dsgbio.asp  
Yoo, J. C., & Delahunty, R. J. (2010). Kant, Habermas and democratic peace. Chicago Journal of 

International Law, 11, pp.1-37. Retrieved from http://works.bepress.com/johnyoo/51